m obius functions of posets v gcd matrices
play

M obius Functions of Posets V: GCD Matrices Bruce Sagan Department - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

M obius Functions of Posets V: GCD Matrices Bruce Sagan Department of Mathematics Michigan State University East Lansing, MI 48824-1027 sagan@math.msu.edu www.math.msu.edu/ sagan June 28, 2007 Smiths Theorem The Main Theorem Proof


  1. Recall that if P is a poset and α ∈ I ( P ) then there is an associated matrix M α where M α x , y = α ( x , y ) . If the rows and columns of M α are indexed by a linear extension L of P , then M α is upper triangular. The following is our main theorem. Theorem (Altinisik-S-Tuglu) Let P be a poset and L be a linear extension of P. Suppose α, β ∈ I ( P ) and M has rows and columns indexed by L where � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P Then � det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) . z ∈ P Proof. Let t denote transposition. Then � M α z , x M β M x , y = z , y z

  2. Recall that if P is a poset and α ∈ I ( P ) then there is an associated matrix M α where M α x , y = α ( x , y ) . If the rows and columns of M α are indexed by a linear extension L of P , then M α is upper triangular. The following is our main theorem. Theorem (Altinisik-S-Tuglu) Let P be a poset and L be a linear extension of P. Suppose α, β ∈ I ( P ) and M has rows and columns indexed by L where � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P Then � det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) . z ∈ P Proof. Let t denote transposition. Then � M α z , x M β � ( M α ) t x , z M β M x , y = z , y = z , y z z

  3. Recall that if P is a poset and α ∈ I ( P ) then there is an associated matrix M α where M α x , y = α ( x , y ) . If the rows and columns of M α are indexed by a linear extension L of P , then M α is upper triangular. The following is our main theorem. Theorem (Altinisik-S-Tuglu) Let P be a poset and L be a linear extension of P. Suppose α, β ∈ I ( P ) and M has rows and columns indexed by L where � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P Then � det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) . z ∈ P Proof. Let t denote transposition. Then � M α z , x M β � ( M α ) t x , z M β M x , y = z , y = z , y z z So M = ( M α ) t M β ,

  4. Recall that if P is a poset and α ∈ I ( P ) then there is an associated matrix M α where M α x , y = α ( x , y ) . If the rows and columns of M α are indexed by a linear extension L of P , then M α is upper triangular. The following is our main theorem. Theorem (Altinisik-S-Tuglu) Let P be a poset and L be a linear extension of P. Suppose α, β ∈ I ( P ) and M has rows and columns indexed by L where � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P Then � det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) . z ∈ P Proof. Let t denote transposition. Then � M α z , x M β � ( M α ) t x , z M β M x , y = z , y = z , y z z So M = ( M α ) t M β , implying det M = det M α det M β .

  5. Recall that if P is a poset and α ∈ I ( P ) then there is an associated matrix M α where M α x , y = α ( x , y ) . If the rows and columns of M α are indexed by a linear extension L of P , then M α is upper triangular. The following is our main theorem. Theorem (Altinisik-S-Tuglu) Let P be a poset and L be a linear extension of P. Suppose α, β ∈ I ( P ) and M has rows and columns indexed by L where � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P Then � det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) . z ∈ P Proof. Let t denote transposition. Then � M α z , x M β � ( M α ) t x , z M β M x , y = z , y = z , y z z So M = ( M α ) t M β , implying det M = det M α det M β . By triangularity of M α , M β we have det M = � z α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) .

  6. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms.

  7. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums:

  8. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums: if we let S = { i : 1 ≤ i ≤ n and gcd ( i , n ) = 1 } then we have φ ( n ) = # S

  9. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums: if we let S = { i : 1 ≤ i ≤ n and gcd ( i , n ) = 1 } then we have � φ ( n ) = # S = 1 . i ∈ S

  10. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums: if we let S = { i : 1 ≤ i ≤ n and gcd ( i , n ) = 1 } then we have � φ ( n ) = # S = 1 . i ∈ S To switch the role of sum and individual term we need M¨ obius inversion.

  11. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums: if we let S = { i : 1 ≤ i ≤ n and gcd ( i , n ) = 1 } then we have � φ ( n ) = # S = 1 . i ∈ S To switch the role of sum and individual term we need M¨ obius inversion. The sums in the Main Theorem have two implicit restrictions:

  12. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums: if we let S = { i : 1 ≤ i ≤ n and gcd ( i , n ) = 1 } then we have � φ ( n ) = # S = 1 . i ∈ S To switch the role of sum and individual term we need M¨ obius inversion. The sums in the Main Theorem have two implicit restrictions: α ( z , x ) , β ( z , y ) � = 0 implies z ≤ x and z ≤ y .

  13. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums: if we let S = { i : 1 ≤ i ≤ n and gcd ( i , n ) = 1 } then we have � φ ( n ) = # S = 1 . i ∈ S To switch the role of sum and individual term we need M¨ obius inversion. The sums in the Main Theorem have two implicit restrictions: α ( z , x ) , β ( z , y ) � = 0 implies z ≤ x and z ≤ y . To use M¨ obius inversion we need a single restriction z ≤ w .

  14. In the Main Theorem, the entries of M are sums, � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ∈ P while the factors of det M are individual terms. In Smith’s Theorem, the entries of M are individual terms, while the factors of det M are sums: if we let S = { i : 1 ≤ i ≤ n and gcd ( i , n ) = 1 } then we have � φ ( n ) = # S = 1 . i ∈ S To switch the role of sum and individual term we need M¨ obius inversion. The sums in the Main Theorem have two implicit restrictions: α ( z , x ) , β ( z , y ) � = 0 implies z ≤ x and z ≤ y . To use M¨ obius inversion we need a single restriction z ≤ w . To collapse the two restrictions to one, we specialize to the case of a meet semi-lattice.

  15. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join).

  16. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice.

  17. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice.

  18. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a).

  19. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.)

  20. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } .

  21. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q .

  22. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join:

  23. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x .

  24. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y .

  25. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y

  26. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y then z ∈ Q .

  27. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y then z ∈ Q . So z ≥ ∧ Q .

  28. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y then z ∈ Q . So z ≥ ∧ Q . Example. Π n is a lattice:

  29. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y then z ∈ Q . So z ≥ ∧ Q . Example. Π n is a lattice: Π n is finite and has a ˆ 1.

  30. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y then z ∈ Q . So z ≥ ∧ Q . Example. Π n is a lattice: Π n is finite and has a ˆ 1. Also, any π = B 1 / . . . / B k and σ = C 1 / . . . / C l have a meet,

  31. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y then z ∈ Q . So z ≥ ∧ Q . Example. Π n is a lattice: Π n is finite and has a ˆ 1. Also, any π = B 1 / . . . / B k and σ = C 1 / . . . / C l have a meet, namely the partition whose blocks are the nonempty B i ∩ C j for 1 ≤ i ≤ k and 1 ≤ j ≤ l .

  32. A meet (respectively, join) semi-lattice is a poset P where every x , y ∈ P have a meet (respectively, join). Proposition (a) A finite meet semi-lattice having a ˆ 1 is a lattice. (b) A finite join semi-lattice having a ˆ 0 is a lattice. Proof of (a). Every x , y ∈ P have a meet, so every nonempty Q ⊆ P has a meet. (Induct on | Q | which must be finite.) We need to prove that any x , y ∈ P have a join. Let Q = { z : z ≥ x and z ≥ y } . Then Q � = ∅ because ˆ 1 ∈ Q . So ∧ Q exists and is the join: 1. We have z ≥ x for all z ∈ Q so ∧ Q ≥ x . Similarly ∧ Q ≥ y . 2. If z ≥ x and z ≥ y then z ∈ Q . So z ≥ ∧ Q . Example. Π n is a lattice: Π n is finite and has a ˆ 1. Also, any π = B 1 / . . . / B k and σ = C 1 / . . . / C l have a meet, namely the partition whose blocks are the nonempty B i ∩ C j for 1 ≤ i ≤ k and 1 ≤ j ≤ l . By the proposition, Π n is a lattice.

  33. Let P be a meet semi-lattice.

  34. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) z ≤ x , z ≤ y

  35. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y

  36. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain

  37. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain � M x , y = g ( z ) z ≤ x ∧ y

  38. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain � � M x , y = g ( z ) and det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) z ≤ x ∧ y z ∈ P

  39. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain � � � M x , y = g ( z ) and det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) = g ( z ) . z ≤ x ∧ y z ∈ P z ∈ P

  40. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain � � � M x , y = g ( z ) and det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) = g ( z ) . z ≤ x ∧ y z ∈ P z ∈ P Define f : P → R by f ( z ) = � w ≤ z g ( w )

  41. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain � � � M x , y = g ( z ) and det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) = g ( z ) . z ≤ x ∧ y z ∈ P z ∈ P Define f : P → R by f ( z ) = � w ≤ z g ( w ) so M x , y = f ( x ∧ y )

  42. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain � � � M x , y = g ( z ) and det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) = g ( z ) . z ≤ x ∧ y z ∈ P z ∈ P Define f : P → R by f ( z ) = � w ≤ z g ( w ) so   � �  . M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) and det M = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) z w ≤ z

  43. Let P be a meet semi-lattice. So � � M x , y = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) = α ( z , x ) β ( z , y ) . z ≤ x , z ≤ y z ≤ x ∧ y Let g : P → R be arbitrary. Substituting α ( z , x ) = g ( z ) and β ( z , y ) = ζ ( z , y ) into the Main Theorem, we obtain � � � M x , y = g ( z ) and det M = α ( z , z ) β ( z , z ) = g ( z ) . z ≤ x ∧ y z ∈ P z ∈ P Define f : P → R by f ( z ) = � w ≤ z g ( w ) so   � �  . M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) and det M = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) z w ≤ z Theorem (Wilf, 1968) Let f : P → R where P is a meet semi-lattice and let M be the matrix with M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) . Then � det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) .

  44. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) .

  45. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z q ❆ ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x q

  46. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z ❆ q ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z )

  47. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z ❆ q ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z ) det M = f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( z ) + 2 f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 2 f ( y ) − f ( x ) 2 f ( z ) .

  48. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z ❆ q ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z ) det M = f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( z ) + 2 f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 2 f ( y ) − f ( x ) 2 f ( z ) . On the other hand

  49. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z ❆ q ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z ) det M = f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( z ) + 2 f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 2 f ( y ) − f ( x ) 2 f ( z ) . On the other hand g ( x ) = µ ( x , x ) f ( x ) = f ( x ) ,

  50. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z q ❆ ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z ) det M = f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( z ) + 2 f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 2 f ( y ) − f ( x ) 2 f ( z ) . On the other hand g ( x ) = µ ( x , x ) f ( x ) = f ( x ) , g ( y ) = µ ( y , y ) f ( y ) + µ ( x , y ) f ( x ) = f ( y ) − f ( x ) ,

  51. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z q ❆ ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z ) det M = f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( z ) + 2 f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 2 f ( y ) − f ( x ) 2 f ( z ) . On the other hand g ( x ) = µ ( x , x ) f ( x ) = f ( x ) , g ( y ) = µ ( y , y ) f ( y ) + µ ( x , y ) f ( x ) = f ( y ) − f ( x ) , g ( z ) = µ ( z , z ) f ( z ) + µ ( x , z ) f ( x ) = f ( z ) − f ( x ) .

  52. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z ❆ q ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z ) det M = f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( z ) + 2 f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 2 f ( y ) − f ( x ) 2 f ( z ) . On the other hand g ( x ) = µ ( x , x ) f ( x ) = f ( x ) , g ( y ) = µ ( y , y ) f ( y ) + µ ( x , y ) f ( x ) = f ( y ) − f ( x ) , g ( z ) = µ ( z , z ) f ( z ) + µ ( x , z ) f ( x ) = f ( z ) − f ( x ) . g ( x ) g ( y ) g ( z ) = f ( x ) [ f ( y ) − f ( x )] [ f ( z ) − f ( x )]

  53. � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) z ∈ P where g ( z ) = � w ≤ z µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . y q z ❆ q ✁ Example. Let P = . ❆ ✁ ❆ ✁ x x y z q   x f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( x ) M =  . y f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( x )  z f ( x ) f ( x ) f ( z ) det M = f ( x ) f ( y ) f ( z ) + 2 f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 3 − f ( x ) 2 f ( y ) − f ( x ) 2 f ( z ) . On the other hand g ( x ) = µ ( x , x ) f ( x ) = f ( x ) , g ( y ) = µ ( y , y ) f ( y ) + µ ( x , y ) f ( x ) = f ( y ) − f ( x ) , g ( z ) = µ ( z , z ) f ( z ) + µ ( x , z ) f ( x ) = f ( z ) − f ( x ) . g ( x ) g ( y ) g ( z ) = f ( x ) [ f ( y ) − f ( x )] [ f ( z ) − f ( x )] = det M .

  54. Outline Smith’s Theorem The Main Theorem Proof of Smith’s Theorem

  55. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n

  56. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms.

  57. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1

  58. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. For d | n , let S d ⊆ S be the fractions with denominator d . Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1

  59. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. For d | n , let S d ⊆ S be the fractions with denominator d . Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1 � 1 � � 1 � � 1 3 , 2 � � 1 6 , 5 � S 1 = , S 2 = , S 3 = , S 6 = . 1 2 3 6

  60. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. For d | n , let S d ⊆ S be the fractions with denominator d . Then | S d | = φ ( d ) since c / d ∈ S d iff 1 ≤ c ≤ d and gcd ( c , d ) = 1. Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1 � 1 � � 1 � � 1 3 , 2 � � 1 6 , 5 � S 1 = , S 2 = , S 3 = , S 6 = . 1 2 3 6

  61. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. For d | n , let S d ⊆ S be the fractions with denominator d . Then | S d | = φ ( d ) since c / d ∈ S d iff 1 ≤ c ≤ d and gcd ( c , d ) = 1. Also S = ⊎ d | n S d Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1 � 1 � � 1 � � 1 3 , 2 � � 1 6 , 5 � S 1 = , S 2 = , S 3 = , S 6 = . 1 2 3 6

  62. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. For d | n , let S d ⊆ S be the fractions with denominator d . Then | S d | = φ ( d ) since c / d ∈ S d iff 1 ≤ c ≤ d and gcd ( c , d ) = 1. Also S = ⊎ d | n S d so n = | S | Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1 � 1 � � 1 � � 1 3 , 2 � � 1 6 , 5 � S 1 = , S 2 = , S 3 = , S 6 = . 1 2 3 6

  63. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. For d | n , let S d ⊆ S be the fractions with denominator d . Then | S d | = φ ( d ) since c / d ∈ S d iff 1 ≤ c ≤ d and gcd ( c , d ) = 1. Also S = ⊎ d | n S d so � n = | S | = | S d | d | n Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1 � 1 � � 1 � � 1 3 , 2 � � 1 6 , 5 � S 1 = , S 2 = , S 3 = , S 6 = . 1 2 3 6

  64. Theorem For all n ≥ 1 : � n = φ ( d ) . d | n Proof. Consider the set S = { 1 / n , 2 / n , . . . , n / n } where the fractions have been reduced to lowest terms. For d | n , let S d ⊆ S be the fractions with denominator d . Then | S d | = φ ( d ) since c / d ∈ S d iff 1 ≤ c ≤ d and gcd ( c , d ) = 1. Also S = ⊎ d | n S d so � � n = | S | = | S d | = φ ( d ) . d | n d | n Example. If n = 6 then � 1 � � 1 � 6 , 2 6 , 3 6 , 4 6 , 5 6 , 6 6 , 1 3 , 1 2 , 2 3 , 5 6 , 1 S = = . 6 1 � 1 � � 1 � � 1 3 , 2 � � 1 6 , 5 � S 1 = , S 2 = , S 3 = , S 6 = . 1 2 3 6

  65. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives

  66. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives Corollary � φ ( n ) = µ ( d , n ) d . d | n

  67. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives Corollary � φ ( n ) = µ ( d , n ) d . d | n � � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) , g ( z ) = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . w ≤ z z ∈ P

  68. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives Corollary � φ ( n ) = µ ( d , n ) d . d | n � � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) , g ( z ) = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . w ≤ z z ∈ P Theorem (H. J. S. Smith, 1876) If M is n × n with M i , j = gcd ( i , j ) then det M = φ ( 1 ) φ ( 2 ) · · · φ ( n ) .

  69. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives Corollary � φ ( n ) = µ ( d , n ) d . d | n � � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) , g ( z ) = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . w ≤ z z ∈ P Theorem (H. J. S. Smith, 1876) If M is n × n with M i , j = gcd ( i , j ) then det M = φ ( 1 ) φ ( 2 ) · · · φ ( n ) . Proof. Let E n = { 1 , 2 . . . , n } partially ordered by i ≤ E n j iff i | j .

  70. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives Corollary � φ ( n ) = µ ( d , n ) d . d | n � � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) , g ( z ) = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . w ≤ z z ∈ P Theorem (H. J. S. Smith, 1876) If M is n × n with M i , j = gcd ( i , j ) then det M = φ ( 1 ) φ ( 2 ) · · · φ ( n ) . Proof. Let E n = { 1 , 2 . . . , n } partially ordered by i ≤ E n j iff i | j . 4 q 6 q � � Example. E 6 = . 2 q 3 q 5 q ❅ � ❅ � 1 q

  71. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives Corollary � φ ( n ) = µ ( d , n ) d . d | n � � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) , g ( z ) = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . w ≤ z z ∈ P Theorem (H. J. S. Smith, 1876) If M is n × n with M i , j = gcd ( i , j ) then det M = φ ( 1 ) φ ( 2 ) · · · φ ( n ) . Proof. Let E n = { 1 , 2 . . . , n } partially ordered by i ≤ E n j iff i | j . Define f : E n → R by f ( d ) = d . 4 q 6 q � � Example. E 6 = . 2 q 3 q 5 q ❅ � ❅ � 1 q

  72. Inverting n = � d | n φ ( d ) gives Corollary � φ ( n ) = µ ( d , n ) d . d | n � � M x , y = f ( x ∧ y ) = ⇒ det M = g ( z ) , g ( z ) = µ ( w , z ) f ( w ) . w ≤ z z ∈ P Theorem (H. J. S. Smith, 1876) If M is n × n with M i , j = gcd ( i , j ) then det M = φ ( 1 ) φ ( 2 ) · · · φ ( n ) . Proof. Let E n = { 1 , 2 . . . , n } partially ordered by i ≤ E n j iff i | j . Define f : E n → R by f ( d ) = d . Then in Wilf’s Theorem M i , j = f ( i ∧ j ) 4 q 6 q � � Example. E 6 = . 2 q 3 q 5 q ❅ � ❅ � 1 q

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend