roy l crole
play

Roy L. Crole University of Leicester, UK, 2001 Roy L. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 1 Categorical Logic and Type Theory Roy L. Crole University of Leicester, UK, 2001 Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory,


  1. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 21 Recursively Defined Functions Let I be inductively defined by a set of rules R , and A any set. A function f : I → A can be defined by − specifying an element f ( b ) ∈ A for every base rule b ∈ R ; and − specifying f ( c ) ∈ A in terms of f ( h 1 ) ∈ A and f ( h 2 ) ∈ A .... and f ( h k ) ∈ A for every inductive rule h 1 ..., h k ∈ R , c ✫ ✪

  2. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 22 Example � The factorial function F : N → N is usually defined recursively. We set − F ( 0 ) def = 1 and − ∀ n ∈ N . F ( n + 1 ) def = ( n + 1 ) ∗ F ( n ) . ✫ ✪

  3. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 23 Category Theory � Category Theory can be thought of as a “theory of functions”. A category embodies the basic ideas of a source, target, identity functions, composition, and properties of composition. � Sets and functions is an example of a category. � Structures found in a category are usually defined by stating what properties they have, rather than giving a description of how the structure can be built up. The properties define the structure “uniquely”, and are often called universal properties. ✫ ✪

  4. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 24 � Given sets A and B , we can form A × B (cartesian product), A + B (disjoint union) and A ⇒ B (function space). These sets have universal properties which define them uniquely up to bijection. We shall show that these properties can be described in any category; they will be used to model the types in a type theory. ✫ ✪

  5. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 25 Definition of a Category A category C is specified by the following data: � A collection ob C of entities called objects , written A , B , C ... � A collection mor C of entities called morphisms written f , g , h ... � For each morphism f a source src ( f ) which is an object of C and a target tar ( f ) also an object of C . We shall write f : src ( f ) − → tar ( f ) or perhaps f : A → B . ✫ ✪

  6. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 26 � Morphisms f and g are composable if tar ( f ) = src ( g ) . If f : A → B and g : B → C , then there is a morphism gf : A → C . � For each object A of C there is an identity morphism id A : A → A , where id tar ( f ) ◦ f = f f ◦ id src ( f ) = f � Composition is associative , that is given morphisms f : A → B , g : B → C and h : C → D then ( hg ) f = h ( gf ) . ✫ ✪

  7. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 27 Examples of Categories � Sets and total functions, S et . The objects are sets and morphisms are ( A , f , B ) where f ⊆ A × B is a function. Composition is given by ( B , g , C ) ◦ ( A , f , B ) = ( A , gf , C ) Finally, if A is any set, the identity is ( A , id A , A ) . � Any preordered set ( X , ≤ ) is a category. The objects are elements of X . The collection of morphisms is the set of pairs ( x , y ) where x ≤ y . Composition is ( y , z ) ◦ ( x , y ) def = ( x , z ) (because ≤ is transitive). ✫ ✪

  8. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 28 Definition of a Functor A functor F : C → D is specified by � an operation taking objects A in C to objects FA in D , and � an operation sending morphisms f : A → B in C to morphisms F f : FA → FB in D , for which F ( id A ) = id FA , and whenever the composition of morphisms gf is defined in C we have F ( gf ) = Fg ◦ F f . ✫ ✪

  9. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 29 Examples of Functors � The set [ A ] of finite lists over a set A gives a monoid via list concatenation. Hence we may define F : S et → M on by FA def = [ A ] and F f def = map ( f ) , where map ( f ) : [ A ] → [ B ] is defined by map ( f )([ a 1 ,..., a n ]) = [ f ( a 1 ) ,..., f ( a n )] , with [ a 1 ,..., a n ] any element of [ A ] . ✫ ✪

  10. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 30 f g To see that F ( gf ) = Fg ◦ F f where A − → B − → C note that def F ( gf )([ a 1 ,..., a n ]) = map ( gf )([ a 1 ,..., a n ]) = [ gf ( a 1 ) ,..., gf ( a n )] = map ( g )([ f ( a 1 ) ,..., f ( a n )]) = map ( g )( map ( f )([ a 1 ,..., a n ])) = Fg ◦ F f ([ a 1 ,..., a n ]) . � The functors between two preorders A and B are precisely the monotone functions from A to B . ✫ ✪

  11. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 31 Definition of a Natural Transformation Let F , G : C → D be functors. Then a natural transformation α from F to G , written α : F → G , is specified by giving a morphism α A : FA → GA in D for each object A in C , such that for any f : A → B in C , we have α A ✲ GA FA F f Gf ❄ ❄ ✲ GB FB α B ✫ ✪

  12. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 32 Examples of Natural Transformations � Recall F : S et → M on where FA def = [ A ] and F f def = map ( f ) and map ( f ) : [ A ] → [ B ] . We can define a natural transformation rev : F → F by rev A ([ a 1 ,..., a n ]) def = [ a n ,..., a 1 ] We check F f ◦ rev A ([ a 1 ,..., a n ]) = [ f ( a n ) ,..., f ( a 1 )] = rev B ◦ F f ([ a 1 ,..., a n ]) . � The functor category [ C , D ] has objects functors and morphisms natural transformations. ✫ ✪

  13. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 33 Isomorphisms and Equivalences � A morphism f : A → B is an isomorphism if there is some g : B → A for which fg = id B and gf = id A . � We shall say g is an inverse for f and vise versa. � We say that A is isomorphic to B , A ∼ = B , if such a mutually inverse pair of morphisms exists. � An isomorphism in a functor category is referred to as a natural isomorphism . ✫ ✪

  14. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 34 Examples � Bijections in S et are isomorphisms. � In the category determined by a partially ordered set, the only isomorphisms are the identities, and in a preorder X with x , y ∈ X we have x ∼ = y iff x ≤ y and y ≤ x . Note that in this case there can be only one pair of mutually inverse morphisms witnessing the fact that x ∼ = y . ✫ ✪

  15. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 35 Definition of Binary Products A binary product of objects A and B in a category C is specified by � an object A × B of C , together with morphisms π A : A × B → A and � two projection π B : A × B → B , for which given any object C and morphisms f : C → A , g : C → B , there is a unique morphism � f , g � : C → A × B for which π A � f , g � = f and π B � f , g � = g . ✫ ✪

  16. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 36 � The data for a binary product is more readily understood as a commutative diagram, C g f ∃ ! � f , g � ✛ ✲ ❄ ✲ B A × B A ✛ π A π B The unique morphism � f , g � : C → A × B is called the mediating morphism for f and g . � The definition can be extended to families of objects ( A i | i ∈ I ) . ✫ ✪

  17. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 37 Functors Preserving Products � The functor F : C → D preserves finite products if for any finite family of objects ( A 1 ,..., A n ) in C the morphism m def = � F π i | i ∈ I � : F ( A 1 × ... × A n ) → FA 1 × ... × FA n is an isomorphism. � We refer to m as the canonical isomorphism. � F is strict if the above isomorphisms are identities. ✫ ✪

  18. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 38 Examples � A binary product of x and y in a preordered set X is given by x ∧ y with projections x ∧ y ≤ x and x ∧ y ≤ y . � A (non-empty) finite product of ( A i | i ∈ I ) in S et is given by the cartesian product Π A i ∈ I . The product of the empty family is a terminal object 1 , with the property that there is a unique morphism ! A : A → 1 for every A . � The functor C ( C , − ) preserves finite products. ✫ ✪

  19. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 39 Definition of Binary Coproducts A binary coproduct of A and B is specified by � an object A + B , together with � two insertion morphisms ι A : A → A + B and ι B : B → A + B , such that there is a unique [ f , g ] for which ι A ι B ✲ A + B ✛ A B [ f , g ] g f ✲ ✛ ❄ C ✫ ✪

  20. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 40 Definition of Cartesian Closed Categories C is cartesian closed if it has finite products, and for any B � and C there is B ⇒ C and morphism ev : ( B ⇒ C ) × B → C such that for any f : A × B → C there is a unique morphism λ ( f ) : A → ( B ⇒ C ) such that f = ev ◦ ( λ ( f ) × id B ) . � B ⇒ C is called the exponential of B and C � λ ( f ) is the exponential mate of f . ✫ ✪

  21. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 41 Examples � The category S et . − The terminal object is { ∅ } and binary products are given by cartesian product. − B ⇒ C is the set of functions from B to C . − The function ev : ( B ⇒ C ) × B → C is given by ev ( h , b ) = h ( b ) , where b ∈ B and h : B → C is a function. − Given f : A × B → C we define λ ( f ) : A → ( B ⇒ C ) by λ ( f )( a )( b ) = f ( a , b ) . � A Heyting prelattice viewed as a category is indeed cartesian closed, with Heyting implications as exponentials. In fact such a prelattice also has finite coproducts. ✫ ✪

  22. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 42 Definition of Bicartesian Closed Categories � A category C is a bicartesian closed category if it is a cartesian closed category which has finite coproducts. � A functor F : C → D is said to be bicartesian closed if it preserves finite (co)products and exponentials. � We shall also call such a functor a morphism of bicartesian closed categories. ✫ ✪

  23. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 43 Distributive Categories A category with finite products and coproducts is said to be distributive if the mediating morphisms ∼ = [ id A × i , id A × j ] : ( A × B )+( A × C ) − → A × ( B + C ) ∼ = and ! A × 0 : 0 − → A × 0 are isomorphisms. � The category S et , and any category [ C , S et ] ; categorical structure is defined pointwise. � Any Heyting prelattice which is regarded as a category. � In fact any bicartesian closed category is automatically distributive. ✫ ✪

  24. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 44 Categorical Logic � We shall define intuitionistic propositional logic , and theories in the logic. � Working from first principles, we shall derive a semantics for the logic—we examine each of the rules for deriving theorems, and extract constraints on our semantic model which guarantee soundness. � We show how structure preserving functions can transform one model into another . . . � and use this to show how theories correspond to order theoretic structures with a universal property. ✫ ✪

  25. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 45 Logical Propositions The set of (first order) propositions Prop is inductively defined by the rules below φ ψ φ ψ φ ψ [ p ∈ Gnd ] p φ ∧ ψ φ ∨ ψ φ → ψ true false ✫ ✪

  26. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 46 Signatures and Theories � An IpL sequent takes the form ∆ ⊢ φ , where ∆ is a finite list of propositions. � An IpL -signature Sg is specified by a set of ground propositions Gnd . � An IpL -theory Th is a pair ( Sg , Ax ) where Ax is a set of sequents. Each such sequent is called an axiom of Th . � Given Th , the theorems are inductively generated by the rules on the next slide. If ∆ ⊢ φ is a theorem we shall sometimes write Th ⊲ ∆ ⊢ φ . ✫ ✪

  27. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 47 ∆ , φ , φ ′ , ∆ ′ ⊢ ψ ∆ , φ , φ , ∆ ′ ⊢ ψ [ ∆ ⊢ φ ∈ Ax ] EXCH CTRN ∆ ⊢ φ ∆ , φ ′ , φ , ∆ ′ ⊢ ψ ∆ , φ , ∆ ′ ⊢ ψ φ , ∆ ′ ⊢ ψ ∆ ⊢ φ ID CUT ∆ ′ , φ , ∆ ⊢ φ ∆ ′ , ∆ ⊢ ψ ∆ ⊢ φ ∆ ⊢ ψ OR-I l OR-I l ∆ ⊢ φ ∨ ψ ∆ ⊢ φ ∨ ψ ∆ , φ ⊢ θ ∆ , ψ ⊢ θ ∆ ⊢ φ ∨ ψ OR-E ∆ ⊢ θ ✫ ✪

  28. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 48 Deriving a Semantics – Preliminaries � ∆ ⊢ φ means that if all of the propositions in ∆ are valid, then φ is valid. Recall [ [ φ ] ] ∈ B = {⊥ , ⊤} . � We look for a mathematical “space” H in which we can model the IpL propositions. � We shall assume that H has some notion of “element”. � We model φ as an element [ [ φ ] [ φ ] ] ∈ H . We call [ ] the denotation of φ . ✫ ✪

  29. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 49 � A sequent φ ⊢ ψ is a “relationship”. So we capture this with binary relations ≤ over H . [ φ ] [ ψ ] � The minimal requirement is that [ ] ≤ [ ] whenever Th ⊲ φ ⊢ ψ . We say that the theorem is satisfied by the semantics. ] def � What about Th ⊲ ∆ ⊢ φ ? We define [ [ ∆ ] = ✷ ( ∆ ) where ∆ is the finite list of denotations of the propositions in ∆ , and there is a function [ H ] → H written L �→ ✷ ( L ) . ] . Thus we set ✷ ( h ) def � If ∆ = φ we expect [ [ ∆ ] [ φ ] ] = [ = h . ✫ ✪

  30. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 50 We return to the denotation of propositions. We define − �→ [ [ − ] ] by recursion. Write # : H × H → H for a function which gives the semantics of a logical operator # , so that ] def � [ [ true ] = ⊤ ∈ H , an element to be determined; ] def [ φ ∧ ψ ] [ ψ ] [ ψ ] � [ = [ ] ∧ [ ] ; ] def [ φ → ψ ] [ ψ ] [ ψ ] � [ = [ ] → [ ] , where the denotation [ [ p ] ] may be chosen to be any element of H . ✫ ✪

  31. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 51 Deriving a Semantics of Theories � A structure M in H for a signature is given by specifying an element [ [ p ] ] M ∈ H for each p ∈ Gnd . [ φ ] � One can then define [ ] M by recursion, and a model of Th is a structure M which satisfies each of the axioms of Th . � We shall now look for conditions on ( H , ≤ , ✷ ( − ) , # , ⊥ , ⊤ ) which ensure that for any theory Th and for any model M , the theorems are all satisfied . ✫ ✪

  32. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 52 We shall attempt to discover necessary and sufficient conditions. A typical rule for deducing theorems looks like ∆ 1 ⊢ φ 1 ∆ n ⊢ φ n ... R ∆ ⊢ φ In order to ensure that all theorems are satisfied, we want to find necessary and sufficient conditions on all such rules R to ensure that for all ∆ i , φ i , ∆ and φ ( ✷ ( ∆ 1 ) ≤ [ [ φ 1 ] ]) and ... and ( ✷ ( ∆ n ) ≤ [ [ φ n ] ]) implies ✷ ( ∆ ) ≤ [ [ φ ] ] If this holds, we shall say that the semantics is sound for the rule. ✫ ✪

  33. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 53 It is clearly sufficient to require ( ✷ ( L 1 ) ≤ h 1 ) and ... and ( ✷ ( L n ) ≤ h n ) implies ✷ ( L ) ≤ h ( ∗ ) However, ( ∗ ) is also necessary. Each sequent ∆ j ⊢ φ j can take the form Ax ⊲ p 1 ,..., p m ⊢ p The images ([ [ p 1 ] ] ,..., [ [ p m ] ] , [ [ p ] ]) must be onto [ H ] × H . Thus in fact it is necessary that ( ∗ ) holds. ✫ ✪

  34. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 54 � Note that from ID we have φ ⊢ φ . As φ could be any ground proposition, it is necessary that for any h ∈ H we have h ≤ h , that is ≤ must be reflexive . � From CUT we have δ ⊢ φ φ ⊢ ψ δ ⊢ ψ Axioms could take the form p ⊢ q . Thus it is necessary that ≤ be transitive . � Thus ( H , ≤ ) is a preordered set. ✫ ✪

  35. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 55 ID The NSC for soundness are that ✷ ( L , h , L ′ ) ≤ h for all L , L ′ ∈ [ H ] and h ∈ H . Equivalently, the NSC are that ✷ ( L ) is a lower bound of the set Set ( L ) for any L ∈ [ H ] . EXCH ✷ ( L , h , h ′ , L ′ ) ∼ = ✷ ( L , h ′ , h , L ′ ) CTRN ✷ ( L , h , h , L ′ ) ∼ = ✷ ( L , h , L ′ ) ✫ ✪

  36. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 56 CUT � The NSC are that for any L , L ′ ∈ [ H ] and k , k ′ ∈ H , if ✷ ( L ) ≤ k and ✷ ( k , L ′ ) ≤ k ′ then ✷ ( L , L ′ ) ≤ k ′ . � Taking L def = h for any h ∈ H and k ′ def = ✷ ( k , L ′ ) , we can deduce that if h ≤ k then ✷ ( h , L ′ ) ≤ ✷ ( k , L ′ ) . � Let L def = k 1 ,..., k n and for each i , h ≤ k i . Then ∼ h = ✷ ( h ) ✷ ( h ,..., h , h ) = ≤ ✷ ( k 1 ,..., k n − 1 , k n ) Hence we see that ✷ ( L ) is a greatest lower bound (meet) of the finite set Set ( L ) . ✫ ✪

  37. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 57 OR-I l and OR-I r and OR-E NSC are ✷ ( L ) ≤ h implies ✷ ( L ) ≤ h ∨ k ( 1 ) ✷ ( L ) ≤ k implies ✷ ( L ) ≤ h ∨ k ( 2 ) ( ✷ ( L , h ) ≤ l and ✷ ( L , k ) ≤ l and ✷ ( L ) ≤ h ∨ k ) implies ✷ ( L ) ≤ l ( 3 ) � By taking L to be h and k in (1) and (2) we see h ∨ k ≤ h ∨ k . � Now take L to be h ∨ k and l to be h ∨ k in (3). Note that ✷ ( h ∨ k , h ) ≤ h ≤ h ∨ k , similarly ✷ ( h ∨ k , k ) ≤ k ≤ h ∨ k , and hence h ∨ k ≤ h ∨ k . ✫ ✪

  38. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 58 This is not sufficient to ensure (3) holds. In fact the joins in H must be distributive for meets, ✷ ( L ′ , h ′ ∨ k ′ ) ≤ ✷ ( L ′ , h ′ ) ∨ ✷ ( L ′ , k ′ ) ( ∗ ) To see sufficiency for (3), note that ✷ ( L ) ≤ ✷ ( L , h ∨ k ) if ✷ ( L ) ≤ h ∨ k , and thus using ( ∗ ) we have ✷ ( L ) ≤ l ∨ l ≤ l . . . . We conclude that ( H , ≤ ) is a Heyting prelattice. ✫ ✪

  39. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 59 Semantics of Propositions Let Gnd be a set of ground propositions, and M a structure for Gnd in a Heyting prelattice H . Then the semantics is given by recursion: [ [ p ] ] is specified ( where ⊥ ∈ H is the bottom element ) ] def [ [ false ] = ⊥ [ φ ] [ ψ ] [ φ ] [ ψ ] [ φ ] [ ψ ] [ ] = h [ ] = k [ ] = h [ ] = k [ ] = h [ ] = k [ φ ∧ ψ ] [ φ ∨ ψ ] [ φ → ψ ] [ ] = h ∧ k [ ] = h ∨ k [ ] = h ⇒ k ✫ ✪

  40. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 60 Soundness The structure M satisfies a sequent ∆ ⊢ φ if ] def [ ∆ ] Set ( ∆ ) = [ δ ] ] | δ ∈ ∆ } ≤ [ [ φ ] ^ ^ [ = { [ ] Let Th = ( Sg , Ax ) be an IpL -theory and M a model of Th in a Heyting prelattice. Then M satisfies each of the theorems of Th . ✫ ✪

  41. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 61 Transporting Models � Suppose f : H → K is a homomorphism of Heyting prelattices, M a model of Th = ( Sg , Ax ) in H . We define a new model f ∗ M , of Th in K . � We can define a structure f ∗ M for Sg in K by def [ [ p ] ] f ∗ M = f ([ [ p ] ] M ) ∈ K . � In fact this is a model. First, we can prove by rule induction ∀ φ ∈ Prop . [ φ ] ] f ∗ M ∼ [ φ ] [ = f ([ ] M ) ✫ ✪

  42. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 62 Now suppose that Ax ⊲ ∆ ⊢ φ . Then def ] f ∗ M | δ ∈ ∆ } ∼ [ ∆ ] [ δ ] [ ] f ∗ M = V { [ = ] M ) | δ ∈ ∆ } ∼ [ δ ] = ′ V { f ([ [ δ ] ] M | δ ∈ ∆ } ) ≤ f ([ [ φ ] ] M ) ∼ [ φ ] f ( V { [ = [ ] f ∗ M Thus f ∗ M satisfies the axioms of Th too, and is thus a model of Th in K . ✫ ✪

  43. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 63 Classifying Prelattices A Heyting prelattice Cl ( Th ) is called the classifying prelattice of Th if there is a model G of Th in Cl ( Th ) for which given any Heyting prelattice K , and a model M of Th in K , then there is a homomorphism of Heyting prelattices m : Cl ( Th ) → K such that M ✲ K Th ✲ m ∗ G = M . G m ❄ Cl ( Th ) ✫ ✪

  44. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 64 Adjoint Rules The class of IpL theorems previously defined is exactly the same as that defined by [ ∆ ⊢ φ ∈ Ax ] ⊣ FALSE-E ⊣ TRUE-I ∆ ⊢ φ ∆ , false ⊢ φ ∆ ⊢ true ∆ ⊢ φ ∆ ⊢ ψ ∆ , φ ⊢ θ ∆ , ψ ⊢ θ = = = = = = = = = = ⊣ AND-I = = = = = = = = = = = = = ⊣ OR-E ∆ ⊢ φ ∧ ψ ∆ , φ ∨ ψ ⊢ θ ✫ ✪

  45. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 65 Constructing Classifiers Each IpL -theory Th has a classifying Heyting prelattice Cl ( Th ) . In fact we can construct a canonical classifier using the syntax of Th , where m ∗ G = M . Proof: Given Th = ( Sg , Ax ) , define a relation ≤ on propositions by φ ≤ ψ if and only if Th ⊲ φ ⊢ ψ . Then ( Prop , ≤ ) is a Heyting prelattice. ✫ ✪

  46. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 66 Categorical Type Theory � We shall define an equational type theory with products, sums, and functions. � Working from first principles, we shall derive a semantics. − First we examine the rules for deriving type assignments, and show that basic properties lead naturally to categorical models. − Second, we examine each of the rules for deriving equations, and extract constraints on our models which guarantee soundness. ✫ ✪

  47. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 67 Categorical Type Theory � We show how structure preserving functors can transform one model into another . . . � and use this to show how theories correspond to categories with a universal property. ✫ ✪

  48. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 68 Signatures A λ × + -signature , Sg , is given by : � A collection of ground types . The collection of types is inductively defined: σ τ σ τ σ τ γ σ × τ σ + τ σ ⇒ τ unit null � A collection of function symbols f : σ 1 ... σ a → σ which may be constants k : σ . ✫ ✪

  49. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 69 Raw Terms We define the raw terms generated by a λ × + -signature: ... M 1 M a M N �� x k f ( M 1 ,..., M a ) � M , N � P M S E F M F A λ x : σ . M Fst ( P ) Inl τ ( M ) Case ( S , x . E | y . F ) F A � We shall soon make use of simultaneous substitution of raw terms for free variables, T [ � U /� v ] . For example, � x , y � [ Inl ( y ) , x / x , y ] = � Inl ( y ) , x � . ✫ ✪

  50. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 70 Proved Terms � A context is a finite list of (variable, type) pairs, usually written as Γ = [ x 1 : σ 1 ,..., x n : σ n ] , where the variables are required to be distinct. � A term-in-context is a judgement of the form Γ ⊢ M : σ � Given a signature Sg , the proved terms are those terms-in-context which are inductively generated by the following rules. ✫ ✪

  51. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 71 Γ ⊢ M 1 : σ 1 Γ ⊢ M a : σ a ... Γ , x : σ , Γ ′ ⊢ x : σ Γ ⊢ k : σ Γ ⊢ f ( M 1 ,..., M a ) : τ Γ ⊢ S : σ + τ Γ , x : σ ⊢ E : δ Γ , y : τ ⊢ F : δ Γ ⊢ Case ( S , x . E | y . F ) : δ Γ , x : σ ⊢ M : τ Γ ⊢ F : σ ⇒ τ Γ ⊢ A : σ Γ ⊢ λ x : σ . M : σ ⇒ τ Γ ⊢ F A : τ ✫ ✪

  52. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 72 Admissible Properties Whenever Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ M : σ , we have Sg ⊲ πΓ ⊢ M : σ . We use rule induction. More precisely we prove ∀ Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ M : σ . Sg ⊲ πΓ ⊢ M : σ We give some examples of property closure. ✫ ✪

  53. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 73 Γ ⊢ M 1 : σ 1 Γ ⊢ M a : σ a ... ( f : σ 1 ,..., σ a → σ ) Γ ⊢ f ( M 1 ,..., M a ) : σ ( Property Closure for the inductive rule for function The inductive hypotheses are Sg ⊲ πΓ ⊢ M i : σ i symbols ): for each i , that is, there is a derivation for each term-in-context. But now we can just apply an instance of the rule to these derivations to deduce that Sg ⊲ πΓ ⊢ f ( M 1 ,..., M a ) : σ , as required. ✫ ✪

  54. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 74 Theories � A λ × + -theory , Th , is a pair ( Sg , Ax ) where Ax is a collection of equations-in-context for Sg . � An equation-in-context is a judgement Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ where Γ ⊢ M : σ and Γ ⊢ M ′ : σ are proved terms. � The theorems of Th consist of the judgements of the form Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ inductively generated by the rules on the following slides—it is a consequence of the rules that Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ M : σ and Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ M ′ : σ . ✫ ✪

  55. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 75 Ax ⊲ Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ ( where π is a permutation ) πΓ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ (where Γ ⊆ Γ ′ ) Γ ′ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ Γ , x : σ ⊢ N = N ′ : τ Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ Γ ⊢ N [ M / x ] = N ′ [ M ′ / x ] : τ ✫ ✪

  56. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 76 Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ M : unit Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ M : σ Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ N : τ Γ ⊢ M = �� : unit Γ ⊢ Fst ( � M , N � ) = M : σ Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ P : σ × τ Γ ⊢ � Fst ( P ) , Snd ( P ) � = P : σ × τ Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ S : null Sg ⊲ Γ , x : null ⊢ M : σ Γ ⊢ Emp σ ( S ) = M [ S / x ] : σ ✫ ✪

  57. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 77 Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ M : σ Sg ⊲ Γ , x : σ ⊢ E : δ Sg ⊲ Γ , y : τ ⊢ F : δ Γ ⊢ Case ( Inl τ ( M ) , x . E | y . F ) = E [ M / x ] : δ Sg ⊲ Γ , x : σ ⊢ M : τ Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ A : σ Γ ⊢ ( λ x : σ . M ) A = M [ A / x ] : τ Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ F : σ ⇒ τ (provided x �∈ fv ( F ) ) Γ ⊢ λ x : σ . ( Fx ) = F : σ ⇒ τ Γ , x : σ ⊢ M = M ′ : τ Γ ⊢ λ x : σ . M = λ x : σ . M ′ : σ ⇒ τ ✫ ✪

  58. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 78 Deriving a Semantics For Proved Terms � Suppose we model (or interpret) σ and τ by “objects” A and m B . Let us model x : σ ⊢ M : τ as a “relationship” A − → B . � We first think about the process of substitution. Let m n [ x : σ ⊢ M : τ ] [ y : τ ⊢ N : γ ] [ ] = A − → B [ ] = B − → C Then ✷ ( n , m ) [ x : σ ⊢ N [ M / y ] : γ ] [ ] = A − → C ✫ ✪

  59. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 79 � Let z : γ ⊢ L : δ be a further proved term. Note that we shall identify the semantics of the proved terms x : σ ⊢ ( L [ N / z ])[ M / y ] : δ x : σ ⊢ L [ N [ M / y ] / z ] : δ and Thus ✷ ( ✷ ( l , n ) , m ) = ✷ ( l , ✷ ( n , m )) � We will have to model x : σ ⊢ x : σ as a relationship e ⋆ A − → A . We can deduce that if E − → A , then ✷ ( ⋆ A , e ) = e A because x [ E / x ] = E . ✫ ✪

  60. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 80 We summarise our deductions, writing n ◦ m for ✷ ( n , m ) and id A for ⋆ A , which amount to the definition of a category : − Types are interpreted by “objects,” say A , B ... and proved m terms are interpreted by “relationships,” say A − → B ... − For each object A there is a relationship id A . m n − Given relationships A − → B and B − → C , there is a relationship A n ◦ m − → C . e m − Given relationships E − → A and A − → B , then we have id A ◦ e = e and m ◦ id A = m . m n l − For any A − → B , B − → C and C − → D , we have l ◦ ( n ◦ m ) = ( l ◦ n ) ◦ m . ✫ ✪

  61. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 81 Summary � We will model a proved term x 1 : σ 1 ,..., x n : σ n ⊢ M : τ in a category with finite products as a morphism of the form [ Γ ⊢ M : τ ] [ Γ ] [ τ ] [ ] : [ ] → [ ] where Γ def = x 1 : σ 1 ,..., x n : σ n and [ [ Γ ] ] stands for [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] [ ] × ... × [ ] . � Substitution of terms will be modelled by categorical composition . . . ✫ ✪

  62. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 82 Deriving a Semantics for Theories � First we consider the types of Sg . We have to give an object [ γ ] ] of C to interpret each of the ground types γ , [ [ [ unit ] ] to interpret unit , and [ [ null ] ] to interpret null . ] def [ σ × τ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] � We define [ = [ ] ✷ [ ] , etc [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] [ σ ] � We choose a morphism [ [ f ] ] : [ ] × ... × [ ] → [ ] in C for each function symbol. � Recall that the interpretation of Γ ⊢ M : σ is given by [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ ] : [ ] → [ ] . By looking at how to soundly interpret the theorems of Th we will deduce what the interpretation must be. ✫ ✪

  63. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 83 A typical rule looks like Γ ⊢ M : σ ( R ) Γ ⊢ R ( M ) : τ Now suppose that m def [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] = [ ] which is an element of [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ Γ ⊢ R ( M ) : τ ] [ Γ ] [ τ ] C ([ ] , [ ]) . How do we model [ ] ∈ C ([ ] , [ ]) ? All we can say at the moment is that this will depend on m , and we can model this idea by having a function Φ : C ([ [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ Γ ] [ τ ] ] , [ ]) − → C ([ ] , [ ]) ] def [ Γ ⊢ R ( M ) : τ ] = Φ ( m ) . and setting [ ✫ ✪

  64. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 84 Suppose that x : γ ⊢ M : σ and y : γ ′ ⊢ N : γ are any two given [ y : γ ′ ⊢ N : γ ] proved terms. If m def ] and n def [ x : γ ⊢ M : σ ] = [ = [ ] then [ y : γ ′ ⊢ M [ N / x ] : σ ] [ ] = m ◦ n . Note that there are “equal” proved terms y : γ ′ ⊢ R ( M )[ N / x ] : τ y : γ ′ ⊢ R ( M [ N / x ]) : τ . and and so Φ ( m ) ◦ n = Φ ( m ◦ n ) . ( ∗ ) ( ∗ ) will hold if there are natural transformations → C ( − , B ) : C op − Φ : C ( − , A ) − → S et . ✫ ✪

  65. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 85 Recall that the rule for introducing product terms is Γ ⊢ M : σ Γ ⊢ N : σ Γ ⊢ � M , N � : σ × τ In order to soundly interpret this rule we shall need a natural transformation Φ : C ( − , A ) × C ( − , B ) − → C ( − , A ✷ B ) for all objects A and B of C . ✫ ✪

  66. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 86 Now let m : C → A and n : C → B be morphisms of C . Applying naturality in C at the morphism � m , n � : C → A × B we deduce Then we can make the definition ] def [ Γ ⊢ � M , N � : A × B ] [ = [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] [ Γ ⊢ N : σ ] q [ ] � [ ] , [ ] � [ σ ] [ τ ] ] , [ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] ✲ [ ✲ [ [ ] × [ ] ] ✷ [ ] . ✫ ✪

  67. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 87 Γ ⊢ H : σ × τ Γ ⊢ Fst ( H ) : σ To model this rule we shall need a natural transformation Φ : C ( − , A ✷ B ) − → C ( − , A ) . Using the Yoneda lemma (see notes), the components of Φ are given by θ �→ p ◦ θ for some p : A ✷ B → A . So now we can define [ Γ ⊢ H : σ × τ ] p [ ] [ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] ] , [ ] ] def [ Γ ⊢ Fst ( H ) : σ ] [ Γ ] ✲ [ [ σ ] [ τ ] ✲ [ [ σ ] [ = [ ] ✷ [ ] ] . ✫ ✪

  68. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 88 Now we think about the equations Γ ⊢ M : σ Γ ⊢ N : τ ( 1 ) Γ ⊢ Fst ( � M , N � ) = M : σ Γ ⊢ H : σ × τ ( 3 ) Γ ⊢ � Fst ( H ) , Snd ( H ) � = H : σ × τ ✫ ✪

  69. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 89 If we put h def [ Γ ⊢ H : σ × τ ] = [ ] : C → A ✷ B , m def ] : C → A and n def [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] [ Γ ⊢ N : τ ] = [ = [ ] : C → B , and our categorical interpretation satisfies the equations-in-context, this forces p A , B ◦ q A , B ◦� m , n � = ( 1 ) m p ′ A , B ◦ q A , B ◦� m , n � = ( 2 ) n q A , B ◦� p A , B ◦ h , p ′ A , B ◦ h � = ( 3 ) h These equations imply that, up to isomorphism, A ✷ B and A × B are the same. Thus we may soundly interpret binary product types by binary categorical product . ✫ ✪

  70. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 90 To soundly interpret the rule Γ ⊢ S : null Γ ⊢ Emp σ ( S ) : σ we shall need a natural transformation Φ : C ( − , N ) − → C ( − , A ) , where N = [ [ null ] ] . The Yoneda Lemma tells us that the components of Φ are given by θ �→ n A ◦ θ where n A : N → A is a morphism, one for each A . So now we can define [ Γ ⊢ S : null ] n [ ] [ ] [ σ ] ] ] def [ Γ ⊢ Emp σ ( S ) : σ ] [ Γ ] ✲ [ [ σ ] ✲ N [ = [ ] . ✫ ✪

  71. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 91 If we write s def [ Γ ⊢ S : null ] = [ ] : C → N , and m def [ Γ , x : null ⊢ M : σ ] = [ ] : C × N → A then Γ ⊢ Emp σ ( S ) = M [ S / x ] : σ will be soundly modelled providing that n A ◦ s = m ◦� id C , s � ( † ) holds for any such morphisms. Suppose that t : N → A . Taking s to be id N and m to be t ◦ π N , then n A = t ◦ π N ◦� id N , id N � = t Thus N is an initial object in the category C . (In fact ( † ) forces N to be distributive , that is π N : C × N → N is an isomorphism for every C .) ✫ ✪

  72. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 92 Formal Semantics of Proved Terms Let C be a BCC. Then a structure , M , for some Sg in C is specified by: � For every ground type γ an object [ [ γ ] ] of C , � for every function symbol f : σ 1 ... σ n → τ a morphism [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] [ τ ] [ σ ] [ [ f ] ] : [ ] × ... × [ ] → [ ] , where we define [ ] by recursion, ] def ] def [ σ × τ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] setting [ [ unit ] = 1 , [ = [ ] × [ ] etc. Then for every proved term Γ ⊢ M : σ we specify a morphism [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ ] : [ ] → [ ] by recursion. ✫ ✪

  73. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 93 [ Γ , x : σ , Γ ′ ⊢ x : σ ] ] def = π : [ [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ Γ ′ ] [ σ ] [ ] × [ ] × [ ] → [ ] ( k : σ ) ] def [ Γ ⊢ k : σ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ = [ [ k ] ] ◦ ! : [ ] → 1 → [ ] [ Γ ⊢ M 1 : σ 1 ] [ Γ ] [ σ 1 ] [ ] = m 1 : [ ] → [ ] ... [ Γ ⊢ f ( � M ) : τ ] [ Γ ] [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] [ τ ] [ ] = [ [ f ] ] ◦� m 1 ,..., m n � : [ ] → ([ ] × ... × [ ]) → [ ] [ Γ ⊢ P : σ × τ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ ] = p : [ ] → ([ ] × [ ]) [ Γ ⊢ Fst ( P ) : σ ] ] = π 1 ◦ p : [ [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ σ ] [ ] → ([ ] × [ ]) → [ ] ✫ ✪

  74. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 94  [ Γ ⊢ S : σ + τ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ ] = s : [ ] → [ ]+[ ]     [ Γ , x : σ ⊢ E : δ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ δ ] [ ] = e : [ ] × [ ] → [ ]  [ Γ , y : σ ⊢ F : δ ] [ Γ ] [ τ ] [ δ ]  [ ] = f : [ ] × [ ] → [ ]   [ Γ ⊢ Case ( S , x . E | y . F ) : δ ] [ ] = [ e , f ] ◦ ∼ [ Γ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] = ◦� id [ ] , s � : [ ] → [ ] × ([ ]+[ ]) [ Γ ] ∼ [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ Γ ] [ τ ] [ δ ] = ([ ] × [ ])+([ ] × [ ]) → [ ] ✫ ✪

  75. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 95 [ Γ , x : σ ⊢ M : τ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ ] = m : [ ] × [ ] → [ ] [ Γ ⊢ λ x : σ . M : σ ⇒ τ ] ] = λ ( m ) : [ [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ ] → [ ] ⇒ [ ] [ Γ ⊢ F : σ ⇒ τ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ Γ ⊢ A : σ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ ] = f : [ ] → ([ ] ⇒ [ ]) [ ] = a : [ ] → [ ] ] def [ Γ ⊢ F A : τ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] [ = ev ◦� f , a � : [ ] → ([ ] ⇒ [ ]) × [ ] → [ ] ✫ ✪

  76. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 96 Soundness Let M be a structure for a λ × + -signature in a bicartesian closed category C . M satisfies the equation-in-context Γ ⊢ M = M ′ : σ if [ [ Γ ⊢ M ′ : σ ] [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] ] and [ ] are equal. We say that M is a model of a λ × + -theory Th = ( Sg , Ax ) if M satisfies the axioms. Then M satisfies any equation-in-context which is a theorem of Th . Proof: This can be shown by rule induction using the rules for deriving theorems. ✫ ✪

  77. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 97 Let m def [ Γ , x : σ ⊢ M : τ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] [ τ ] = [ ] : [ ] × [ ] → [ ] and a def [ Γ ⊢ A : σ ] [ Γ ] [ σ ] = [ ] : [ ] → [ ] . Then we have ( Property Closure for the (base) rule ): Sg ⊲ Γ , x : σ ⊢ M : τ Sg ⊲ Γ ⊢ A : σ Γ ⊢ ( λ x : σ . M ) A = M [ A / x ] : τ [ Γ ⊢ ( λ x : σ . M ) A : τ ] [ Γ ⊢ λ x : σ . M : τ ] [ Γ ⊢ A : σ ] [ ] = ev � [ ] , [ ] � ev � λ ( m ) , a � = ev ( λ ( m ) × id ) � id , a � = = m � id , a � [ Γ ⊢ M [ A / x ] : τ ] = [ ] ✫ ✪

  78. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 98 Transporting Models Suppose that we are given a morphism of bicartesian closed categories F : C → D . Let M be a model of Th in C . We shall show how to define a new model, of Th in D , denoted by F ∗ M . We shall need a lemma: def [ γ ] [ γ ] ] M where γ is a ground type of Th , If we set [ ] F ∗ M = F [ then it follows from this that there is a canonical ] F ∗ M ∼ [ σ ] [ σ ] ] M where σ is any type of Th . isomorphism [ = F [ ✫ ✪

  79. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 99 def [ γ ] [ γ ] A structure F ∗ M is given by [ ] F ∗ M = F [ ] M on ground types and [ [ f ] ] F ∗ M is given by the composition [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] ] F ∗ M ∼ [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] ] M ∼ = ′ [ ] F ∗ M × ... × [ = F [ ] M × ... × F [ F [ [ f ] ] M [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] [ τ ] ] M ∼ [ τ ] F ([ ] M × ... × [ ] M ) − → F [ = [ ] F ∗ M where f : σ 1 ,..., σ n → τ is a function symbol of Th , the = ′ arises from F isomorphims ∼ = exist because of the lemma, and ∼ preserving finite products. ✫ ✪

  80. ✬ ✩ Roy L. Crole, Categorical Logic and Type Theory, BRICS EEF Summer School 2001 100 In fact F ∗ M is a model of Th . Given a proved term Γ ⊢ M : σ one can show by induction [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] that the morphism [ ] F ∗ M is given by the composition [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] F [ ] M ] F ∗ M ∼ [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] [ σ 1 ] [ σ n ] [ σ ] [ ] F ∗ M × ... × [ = F ([ ] M × ... × [ ] M ) − → F [ ] M . If we are given proved terms Γ ⊢ M : σ and Γ ⊢ N : σ for [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] [ Γ ⊢ N : σ ] which [ ] M = [ ] M then certainly [ Γ ⊢ M : σ ] [ Γ ⊢ N : σ ] [ ] F ∗ M = [ ] F ∗ M . Thus if M is a model of Th in C then F ∗ M is a model of Th in D . ✫ ✪

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend