reminder the voting model
play

REMINDER: THE VOTING MODEL Set of voters = {1, , } Set of - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

T RUTH J USTICE A LGOS Social Choice II: Implicit Utilitarian Voting Teachers: Ariel Procaccia (this time) and Alex Psomas REMINDER: THE VOTING MODEL Set of voters = {1, , } Set of alternatives ; denote || =


  1. T RUTH J USTICE A LGOS Social Choice II: Implicit Utilitarian Voting Teachers: Ariel Procaccia (this time) and Alex Psomas

  2. REMINDER: THE VOTING MODEL โ€ข Set of voters ๐‘‚ = {1, โ€ฆ , ๐‘œ} โ€ข Set of alternatives ๐ต ; denote |๐ต| = ๐‘› โ€ข Each voter has a ranking ๐œ ๐‘— โˆˆ L over the alternatives; ๐‘ฆ โ‰ป ๐‘— ๐‘ง means that voter ๐‘— prefers ๐‘ฆ to ๐‘ง โ€ข A preference profile ๐‰ โˆˆ L ๐‘œ is a collection of all votersโ€™ rankings โ€ข A voting rule is a function ๐‘”: L ๐‘œ โ†’ ๐ต

  3. UTILITIES AND WELFARE โ€ข The voting model assumes ordinal preferences, but it is plausible that they are derived from underlying cardinal preferences โ€ข Assume that each voter ๐‘— has a utility function ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— : ๐ต โ†’ [0,1] , such that ฯƒ ๐‘ฆโˆˆ๐ต ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ฆ = 1 โ€ข Voter ๐‘— reports a ranking ๐œ ๐‘— that is consistent with his utility function, denoted ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— โŠณ ๐œ ๐‘— : ๐‘ฆ โ‰ป ๐‘— ๐‘ง โ‡’ ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ฆ โ‰ฅ ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— (๐‘ง) โ€ข As usual, the (utilitarian) social welfare of ๐‘ฆ โˆˆ ๐ต is = ฯƒ ๐‘—โˆˆ๐‘‚ ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— (๐‘ฆ) sw ๐‘ฆ, ๐’— โ€ข Our goal is choose an alternative that maximizes social welfare, even though we cannot observe the utilities directly

  4. DISTORTION โ€ข We want to quantify how much social welfare a voting rule loses due to lack of information โ€ข The distortion of voting rule ๐‘” on ๐‰ is ๐‘ฆโˆˆ๐ต sw (๐‘ฆ,๐’—) max dist ๐‘”, ๐‰ = max sw (๐‘”(๐‰),๐’—) ๐’— โŠณ ๐‰ โ€ข The distortion of voting rule ๐‘” is dist ๐‘” = max dist ๐‘”, ๐‰ ๐‰

  5. DISTORTION โ€ข Consider the preference profile 1 2 3 ๐‘ ๐‘ ๐‘ ๐‘‘ ๐‘‘ ๐‘ ๐‘ ๐‘ ๐‘‘ ? Poll 1 Distortion of Borda count on this profile? โ€ข 3/2 โ€ข 2 โ€ข 5/3 โ€ข 5/2

  6. DISTORTION โ€ข Consider the preference profile 1 2 โ€ฆ ๐‘› โˆ’ 1 ๐‘ 1 ๐‘ 2 โ€ฆ ๐‘ ๐‘›โˆ’1 ๐‘ฆ ๐‘ฆ โ€ฆ ๐‘ฆ โ‹ฎ โ‹ฎ โ€ฆ โ‹ฎ ? Poll 2 Distortion of plurality on this profile? โ€ข ฮ˜(1) โ€ข ฮ˜(๐‘›) โ€ข ฮ˜ ๐‘› 2 โ€ข ฮ˜ ๐‘›

  7. DETERMINISTIC LOWER BOUND โ€ข Theorem: Any deterministic voting rule ๐‘” has distortion at least ๐‘› โ€ข Proof: โ—ฆ Partition ๐‘‚ into two subsets with ๐‘‚ ๐‘™ = ๐‘œ/2 , and let the profile ๐‰ be such that voters in ๐‘‚ 1 rank ๐‘ 1 first, and voter in ๐‘‚ 2 rank ๐‘ 2 first โ—ฆ W.l.o.g. ๐‘” ๐‰ = ๐‘ 1 โ—ฆ Let ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ 2 = 1 , ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ ๐‘˜ = 0 for ๐‘— โˆˆ ๐‘‚ 2 , ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ ๐‘˜ = 1/๐‘› for all ๐‘— โˆˆ ๐‘‚ 1 โ—ฆ It holds that ๐‘œ 2 dist ๐‘”, ๐‰ โ‰ฅ = ๐‘› โˆŽ ๐‘œ 2๐‘›

  8. RANDOMIZED UPPER BOUND โ€ข Under the harmonic scoring rule, each voter gives 1/๐‘™ points to alternative ranked ๐‘™ -th โ€ข Denote the score of ๐‘ฆ under ๐‰ as sc ๐‘ฆ, ๐‰ โ€ข Why is this useful? Because sw ๐‘ฆ, ๐’— โ‰ค sc ๐‘ฆ, ๐‰ for any ๐ฏ โŠณ ๐‰ โ€ข Theorem [Caragiannis et al. 2015]: The randomized voting rule that, with prob. ยฝ, selects ๐‘ฆ โˆˆ ๐ต with prob. proportional to sc(๐‘ฆ, ๐‰) , and selects a uniformly random alternative with prob. ยฝ, has distortion ๐‘ƒ ๐‘› log ๐‘› โ€ข Discussion: In what sense is this result practical?

  9. PROOF OF THEOREM โ€ข Case 1: The welfare-maximizing ๐‘ฆ โˆ— satisfies sw ๐‘ฆ โˆ— , ๐’— โ‰ฅ ๐‘œ (ln ๐‘› + 1)/๐‘› โ€ข Then sc ๐‘ฆ โˆ— , ๐‰ โ‰ฅ ๐‘œ (ln ๐‘› + 1)/๐‘› ๐‘› โ€ข ฯƒ ๐‘ฆโˆˆ๐ต sc ๐‘ฆ, ๐‰ = ๐‘œ ฯƒ ๐‘™=1 1/๐‘™ โ‰ค ๐‘œ(ln ๐‘› + 1) โ€ข ๐‘ฆ โˆ— is selected with prob. at least ๐‘œ ln ๐‘› + 1 1 1 ๐‘› 2 โ‹… ๐‘œ ln ๐‘› + 1 = 2 ๐‘› (ln ๐‘› + 1) โ€ข Now, โ‰ฅ Pr ๐‘” ๐‰ = ๐‘ฆ โˆ— sw ๐‘ฆ โˆ— , ๐’— ๐”ฝ[sw ๐‘” ๐‰ , ๐’— 1 sw ๐‘ฆ โˆ— , ๐’— โ‰ฅ 2 ๐‘› (ln ๐‘› + 1)

  10. PROOF OF THEOREM โ€ข Case 2: For every ๐‘ฆ โˆˆ ๐ต it holds that sw ๐‘ฆ, ๐’— < ๐‘œ (ln ๐‘› + 1)/๐‘› โ€ข Uniformly random selection gives expected social welfare 1 1 ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ฆ = 1 1 = ๐‘œ ๐‘› เท เท ๐‘› เท เท ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— (๐‘ฆ) 2 2 2๐‘› ๐‘ฆโˆˆ๐ต ๐‘—โˆˆ๐‘‚ ๐‘—โˆˆ๐‘‚ ๐‘ฆโˆˆ๐ต โ€ข Distortion is at most ๐‘œ ln ๐‘› + 1 sw(๐‘ฆ โˆ— , ๐’—) ๐‘› โ‰ค = 2 ๐‘›(ln ๐‘› + 1) โˆŽ ๐‘œ ๐”ฝ sw ๐‘” ๐‰ , ๐’— 2๐‘›

  11. RANDOMIZED LOWER BOUND โ€ข Theorem [Caragiannis et al. 2012]: Any randomized voting rule ๐‘” has distortion ฮฉ ๐‘› โ€ข Proof: โ—ฆ Partition ๐‘‚ into subsets with ๐‘‚ ๐‘™ = ๐‘œ/ ๐‘› , and let the profile be ๐‘‚ ๐‘› ๐‘‚ 1 ๐‘‚ 2 โ€ฆ ๐‘ ๐‘› ๐‘ 1 ๐‘ 2 โ€ฆ โ‹ฎ โ‹ฎ โ‹ฎ โ‹ฎ 1 โ—ฆ W.l.o.g. ๐‘ 1 is selected with prob. โ‰ค ๐‘› โ—ฆ Let ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ 1 = 1 , ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ ๐‘˜ = 0 for ๐‘— โˆˆ ๐‘‚ 1 , ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ ๐‘˜ = 1/๐‘› otherwise โ—ฆ ๐‘œ/ ๐‘› โ‰ค sw ๐‘ 1 , ๐’— โ‰ค 2๐‘œ/ ๐‘› , whereas sw ๐‘ ๐‘˜ , ๐’— โ‰ค ๐‘œ/๐‘› for ๐‘˜ โ‰  1 โ—ฆ Distortion is at least ๐‘œ ๐‘› ๐‘› โ‰ฅ โˆŽ 1 ๐‘› โ‹… 2๐‘œ ๐‘› + 1 โˆ’ 1 ๐‘› โ‹… ๐‘œ 3 ๐‘›

  12. PARTICIPATORY BUDGETING Porto Alegre Paris Madrid New York Brazil France Spain USA Since 1989 โ‚ฌ100M (2016) โ‚ฌ24M (2016) $40M (2017)

  13. THE MODEL โ€ข The total budget is ๐ถ โ€ข Each alternative ๐‘ฆ has a cost ๐‘‘ ๐‘ฆ โ€ข For ๐‘Œ โŠ† ๐ต , the cost ๐‘‘(๐‘Œ) is additive โ€ข Utilities are also additive, that is, ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘Œ = ฯƒ ๐‘ฆโˆˆ๐‘Œ ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— (๐‘ฆ) โ€ข The goal is to find ๐‘Œ โŠ† ๐ต that maximizes the social welfare sw ๐‘Œ, ๐’— = ฯƒ ๐‘—โˆˆ๐‘‚ ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— (๐‘Œ) subject to the budget constraint ๐‘‘ ๐‘Œ โ‰ค ๐ถ

  14. INPUT FORMATS Ranking Knapsack Budget by value voting โ‰ป โ‰ป โ‰ป 9 Ranking Threshold Threshold by VFM approval โ‰ป โ‰ป โ‰ป 5 Utility 3 Utility 6 Utility 2 Utility 8 Cost 6 Cost 2 Cost 1 Cost 9

  15. DISTORTION REDUX โ€ข Distortion allows us to objectively compare input formats, by associating an input format with the distortion of the best voting rule โ€ข Theorem [Benade et al. 2017]: Any randomized voting rule has distortion at least ฮฉ(๐‘›) under knapsack votes โ€ข Proof: โ—ฆ Let ๐ถ = 1 , ๐‘‘ ๐‘ ๐‘˜ = 1 for all ๐‘ ๐‘˜ โˆˆ ๐ต โ—ฆ Define ๐‰ : For each ๐‘ ๐‘˜ โˆˆ ๐ต we have ๐‘œ/๐‘› voters ๐‘‚ ๐‘˜ who choose ๐‘ฆ โ—ฆ W.l.o.g. ๐‘ 1 is selected with prob. โ‰ค 1/๐‘› , then let ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ 1 = 1 for all ๐‘— โˆˆ ๐‘‚ 1 , and ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ ๐‘˜ = ๐‘ฃ ๐‘— ๐‘ 1 = 1/2 for all ๐‘— โˆˆ ๐‘‚ ๐‘˜ , ๐‘˜ โ‰  1 โˆŽ

  16. RANDOMIZED BOUNDS เทฉ Ranking by value ฮ˜ ๐‘› $ เทฉ Ranking by VFM ฮ˜ ๐‘› ฮ˜(๐‘›) Knapsack voting Threshold approval ๐‘ƒ(log 2 ๐‘›) [Benade et al., 2017]

  17. METRIC PREFERENCES โ€ข Assume a metric space with metric ๐‘’ on space of voters and alternatives โ€ข Preferences are defined by ๐‘’ ๐‘—, ๐‘ฆ < ๐‘’ ๐‘—, ๐‘ง โ‡’ ๐‘ฆ โ‰ป ๐‘— ๐‘ง โ€ข Now we want to minimize the social cost, defined as sc ๐‘ฆ, ๐‘’ = ฯƒ ๐‘—โˆˆ๐‘‚ ๐‘’(๐‘—, ๐‘ฆ) ๐‘ ๐‘ ๐‘ โ‰ป ๐‘ โ‰ป ๐‘‘ ๐‘‘

  18. LOWER BOUND โ€ข Theorem [Anshelevich et al. 2015]: The distortion of any deterministic rule under metric preferences is at least 3 โ€ข Proof: โ€ข Theorem [Anshelevich et al. 2015]: The distortion of Copeland under metric preferences is at most 5

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend