non uniqueness of quantization k ahler geometry and
play

Non-uniqueness of quantization, K ahler geometry and generalized - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Non-uniqueness of quantization, K ahler geometry and generalized coherent state transforms Jos e Mour ao CAMGSD, Mathematics Department, IST Jurekfest Warsaw, September 16 20 On recent work in collaboration with T Baier, C


  1. Non-uniqueness of quantization, K¨ ahler geometry and generalized coherent state transforms Jos´ e Mour˜ ao CAMGSD, Mathematics Department, IST Jurekfest Warsaw, September 16 – 20 On recent work in collaboration with T Baier, C Couto, J Hilgert, O Kaya, W Kirwin, G Matos, G Marques, JP Nunes, P Ribeiro, PM Silva, PL Silva and T Thiemann

  2. Summary I. Ambiguity of quantization and preferred observables . . . . . 2   F = ( F 1 , . . . , F n ) � ( ω, J F , γ F )   � �  H Q Ψ = ψ ( F ) e − k F , || Ψ || < ∞ ⊂ H prQ = ( M, ω ) � F   F prQ | H Q �  = F F �→  F II. Generalized Coherent State Transforms (CST) as liftings of geodesics from the space of quantizations T = { F } to the quantum bundle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 2

  3. I. Ambiguity of quantization and preferred observables I.1 Introduction With > 100 years of General Relativity and > 90 years of Quantum Mechanics it is becoming increasingly embarassing the fact that there is not a fully consistent theory of Quantum Gravity. The best candidates to succeed as e.g. Loop Quantum Gravity, String The- ory, Causal Dynamical Triangulations, continue facing conceptual and tech- nical problems. One of the problems one is faced with in Loop Quantum Gravity and the one we will address today is that of nonuniqueness of quantization of a classical system. In fact there is this whole ERC synergy grant - “Recursive and Exact New Quantum Theory” - lead by Andersen, Eynard, Kontsevich and Mari˜ no, which has set as main goal to develop a new approach to quantum field theory in general. 3

  4. The dream of the founders of quantum mechanics was to have quantization as a well defined process assigning a quantum sys- tem to every classical system and satisfying the correspondence principle Quantization Functor (?) : ( M, ω ) �→ Q � ( M, ω ) � → 0 �→ ( M, ω ) It was soon realized that this can never be the case even for the simplest systems. 4

  5. Particle in the line ( 1 dof) Classical ( R 2 , dq ∧ dp, H = 1 2 p 2 + V ( q )) , ( M, ω ) = ∂f ∂q − ∂f ∂ ∂ X H = p ∂ ∂q − V ′ ( q ) ∂ f � X f = ∂p ∂q ∂p ∂p Quantum Q Sch ( R 2 , dp ∧ dq, H ) : � H Q ( q ) ≡ H Q L 2 ( R , dq ) = Sch q Sch = q Q ( q ) � ( q ) = � q �→ p Sch = i � ∂ Q ( q ) � ( p ) = � p �→ ∂q f ( q, p ) ?? �→ H = − � 2 H = 1 ∂ 2 p 2 + V ( q ) Q ( q ) � ( H ) = � �→ ∂q 2 + V ( q ) 2 5

  6. Groenewold (1946) – van Hove (1951) no go Thm: It is impossible, even for systems with one degree of freedom, to quantize all observables exactly as Dirac hoped � Q � ( f ) = f i � Q � ( { f, g } ) [ Q � ( f ) , Q � ( h )] = and satisfy natural additional requirements like irreducibility of the quantiza- tion. In order to quantize one needs to add additional data to the classical system. eg choose a (sufficiently big but not too big ...) (Lie) subalgebra of the algebra of all observables A = Span C { 1 , q, p } Then we have to study the dependence of the quantum theory on the addi- tional data. 6

  7. I.2 Geometric Quantization Geometric quantization is mathematically perhaps the best defined quantiza- tion 1 2 π � [ ω ] ∈ H 2 ( M, Z ) • Classical data: ( M, ω ) , • Prequantum data: ( L, ∇ , h ), L → M, F ∇ = ω � • Pre-quantum Hilbert space: � � � h ( s, s ) ω n H prQ = Γ L 2 ( M, L ) = s ∈ Γ ∞ ( M, L ) : || s || 2 = n ! < ∞ M f prQ = i � ∇ X f + f • Pre-quantum observables: � f = Q prQ ( f ) = � � This almost works! But the Hilbert space is too large, the representation is reducible. We need a smaller Hilbert space: Prequantization ⇒ Quantization 7

  8. Additional Data in Geometric Quantization Generalizing what is done in the Schr¨ odinger representation, for systems with one degree of freedom, to fix a quantization one chooses (locally) a preferred observable – F ( q, p ) ∗ – and then works with wave functions of the form � � Ψ ∈ H prQ : ∇ X F Ψ = 0 , || Ψ || < ∞ H prQ � H Q = = ( F ) � � Ψ( q, p ) = ψ ( F ) e − k ( q,p ) , || Ψ || < ∞ ⊂ H prQ = on which the preferred observable F and functions of it u ( F ) act diagonally prQ ( u ( F )) = � Q ( F ) u ( F ) F = u ( F ) . | H Q � ∗ for systems with n degrees of freedom one chooses (locally) n independent observables in involution F = ( F 1 , . . . , F n ), { F j , F k } = 0. The distribution P = < X F j , j = 1 , . . . n > is called polarization associated with this choice. 8

  9. (Non–)Equivalence of different Quantizations Are all these quantizations (for different choices of F ) physically equivalent? NO! Consider the following one parameter family of observables: H λ = p 2 2 + q 2 2 + λq 4 4 , λ ≥ 0 and let Sp ( Q ( q ) � ( H λ )) denote the (discrete) spectrum of H λ in the Schr¨ odinger quantization, i.e. the spectrum of the operator � ( H λ ) = − � 2 ∂q 2 + q 2 ∂ 2 2 + λq 4 Q ( q ) 2 4 acting on H Q ( q ) = L 2 ( R , dq ). 9

  10. Now consider the 1–parameter family of quantizations with Hilbert spaces H Q H λ for which the role of preferred observable is played by H λ . Then, one finds that � � H Q = Ψ( q, p ) : ∇ X Hλ Ψ = 0 = ( H λ ) � Ψ( q, p ) = ψ ( H λ ) e i G λ ( q,p ) � = = � ∞ � � ψ n δ ( H λ − E λ n ) e iG λ ( q,p ) = , (1) n =0 where E λ n are defined by the Bohr-Sommerfeld (BS) conditions � pdq = � ( n + 1 2) . (2) H λ = E λ n Since Q ( H λ ) ( H λ ) = H λ we conclude from (1) that its spectrum in this quanti- � zation is given by (2) Sp ( Q ( H λ ) ( H λ )) = { E λ n , n ∈ N 0 } . � 10

  11. It is known that on one hand Sp ( Q ( q ) ( H 0 )) = Sp ( Q ( H 0 ) ( H 0 )) � � but on the other hand ( H λ )) � = Sp ( Q ( H λ ) Sp ( Q ( q ) ( H λ )) = BS semi-classical spectrum � � for all λ > 0 so that the two quantizations Q ( q ) and Q ( H λ ) are � � physically inequivalent if λ > 0! Wins Q ( q ) ! � 11

  12. I.3 Ambiguity of quantization and reality conditions LQG is facing a similar problem with the Ashtekar–Barbero con- nection as preferred observable A β = Γ + β K ⇒ Ψ β ( E, K ) = ψ ( A β ) e iG β ( E,K ) . Are the quantizations based on the choice of connections with different (Barbero–Immirzi) parameters equivalent? No, because they lead e.g. to different spectra of the area operator. Here it is less obvious which one is the ”correct”one. Studies of the black hole entropy formula seemed to indicate the value √ β = ln(3) / 8 π ?? 12

  13. Other, recent studies (e.g. Pranzetti, Sahlmann, Phys.Lett 2015, Ben Achour, Livine, Phys. Rev. D 2017) however seem to point back to β = √− 1. This corresponds to the Ashtekar connection √ A √− 1 = Γ + − 1 K It turns out that for some choices of complex observables quanti- zation is in fact mathematically better defined then quantization based on real observables and this may help addressing some of the technical issues faced by LQG. 13

  14. Complex observables and reality conditions: rescued by the power of complex analysis and complex geometry Let us illustrate the general situation with a one degree of free- dom system. Consider the complex observable dz f ∧ dz f = − 2 if ′ ( p ) dq ∧ dp . z f = q + if ( p ) , It turns out that if f ′ ( p ) > 0 then several remarkable simplifying facts occur: 14

  15. F f = z f = q + if ( p ) 1. Complex Structure: There is a unique global complex structure J f on R 2 for which z f is a global holomorphic coordinate: J f = i ∂ ⊗ dz f − i ∂ ⊗ d ¯ z f ∂z f ∂ ¯ z f 2. K¨ ahler Metric: The symplectic form together with the complex structure J f define on R 2 a K¨ ahler metric 1 f ′ ( p ) dq 2 + f ′ ( p ) dp 2 γ f = � � ′′ 1 R ( γ f ) = − . f ′ ( p ) 15

  16. 3. Quantum Hilbert space much better defined than in the case of quantizations based on real observables: � � H Q Ψ( q, p ) = ψ ( z f ) e − k f ( p ) , || Ψ || < ∞ ⊂ L 2 ( R 2 ) ( z f ) = where ψ is a J f –holomorphic function and � f ( p ) dp is a K¨ k f ( p ) = pf ( p ) − ahler potential. 4. The inner product is not ambiguous and it fixes the reality conditions: � R 2 ψ 1 ( z f ) ψ 2 ( z f ) e − 2 k f ( p ) dqdp . < Ψ 1 , Ψ 2 > = 16

  17. II. Generalized CST transforms as liftings of geodesics from T Kah to the quantum bundle II.1 Applications of the (very rich) geometry of the space of polarizations ( ⊂ space of quantizations) T 1. K¨ ahler geometry: Donaldson–Tian theory of stability of K¨ ahler manifolds. Finding new solutions to the geodesic equation on the space of K¨ ahler metrics. 2. Quantization: CST for comparing different quantizations. 17

  18. 3. Quantum physics of open systems: Semiclassical approxima- tion for complex Hamiltonians 4. Quantum Hall physics: Geometry dependence of Fractional Quantum Hall trial states – Laughlin states on curved surfa- ces. 5. Representation theory, algebraic geometry and quantization: Preferred basis of representations and their geometric inter- pretation (via BS fibers) and quantization with singular real and mixed polarizations 18

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend