how to describe
play

How to Describe Towards a General Case From Measurements . . . - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

How Can We Describe . . . Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . How to Describe Towards a General Case From Measurements . . . Measurement Uncertainty Main Result about f What If There Is No Bias? and Uncertainty of No-Bias Results


  1. How Can We Describe . . . Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . How to Describe Towards a General Case From Measurements . . . Measurement Uncertainty Main Result about f What If There Is No Bias? and Uncertainty of No-Bias Results Expert Estimates? Home Page Title Page Nicolas Madrid and Irina Perfilieva ◭◭ ◮◮ Institute of Research and Applications of Fuzzy Modeling University of Ostrava, Ostrava, Czech Republic ◭ ◮ nicolas.madrid@osu.cz, Irina.Perfilieva@osu.cz Page 1 of 21 Vladik Kreinovich Go Back Department of Computer Science University of Texas at El Paso Full Screen El Paso, TX 79968, USA vladik@utep.edu Close Quit

  2. How Can We Describe . . . 1. How Can We Describe Measurement Uncer- Case of Absolute . . . tainty: Formulation of the Problem Case of Relative . . . Towards a General Case • We want to know the actual values of different quanti- From Measurements . . . ties. Main Result about f • To get these values, we perform measurements. What If There Is No Bias? • Measurements are never absolutely accurate. No-Bias Results Home Page • The actual value A ( u ) of the corr. quantity is, in gen- Title Page eral, different from the measurement result M ( u ). ◭◭ ◮◮ • It is therefore desirable to describe what are the possi- ◭ ◮ ble values of A ( u ). Page 2 of 21 • This will be a perfect way to describe uncertainty: Go Back – for each measurement result M ( u ), Full Screen – we describe the set of all possible values of A ( u ). Close • How can we attain this description? Quit

  3. How Can We Describe . . . 2. In Practice, We Don’t Know Actual Values Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . • Ideally, for diff. situations u , we should compare the Towards a General Case measurement result M ( u ) with the actual value A ( u ). From Measurements . . . • The problem is that we do not know the actual value. Main Result about f What If There Is No Bias? • A usual approach is to compare No-Bias Results – the measurement result M ( u ) with Home Page – the result S ( u ) of measuring the same quantity by Title Page a much more accurate (“standard”) MI. ◭◭ ◮◮ • From this viewpoint, the above problem can be refor- ◭ ◮ mulated as follows: Page 3 of 21 – we know the measurement result M ( u ) correspond- ing to some situation u , Go Back – we want to find the set of possible values S ( u ) that Full Screen we would have obtained if we apply a standard MI. Close Quit

  4. How Can We Describe . . . 3. Case of Absolute Measurement Error Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . • In some cases, we know the upper bound ∆ on the Towards a General Case absolute value of the measurement error M ( u ) − A ( u ): From Measurements . . . | M ( u ) − A ( u ) | ≤ ∆ . Main Result about f What If There Is No Bias? • In this case, once we know the measurement result No-Bias Results M ( u ), we can conclude that Home Page M ( u ) − ∆ ≤ A ( u ) ≤ M ( u ) + ∆ . Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ • In more general terms, we can describe the correspond- ing bounds as f ( M ( u )) ≤ A ( u ) ≤ g ( M ( u )) , where ◭ ◮ Page 4 of 21 def def f ( x ) = x − ∆ and g ( x ) = x + ∆ . Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  5. How Can We Describe . . . 4. Case of Relative Measurement Error Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . • In some other cases, we know the upper bound δ on Towards a General Case the relative measurement error: From Measurements . . . | M ( u ) − A ( u ) | ≤ δ. Main Result about f | A ( u ) | What If There Is No Bias? • In this case, for positive values, No-Bias Results Home Page (1 − δ ) · A ( u ) ≤ M ( u ) ≤ (1 + δ ) · A ( u ) . Title Page • Thus, once we know the measurement result M ( u ), we ◭◭ ◮◮ can conclude that ◭ ◮ M ( u ) 1 + δ ≤ A ( u ) ≤ M ( u ) 1 − δ . Page 5 of 21 Go Back • So, we have f ( M ( u )) ≤ A ( u ) ≤ g ( M ( u )) for Full Screen x x def def f ( x ) = 1 + δ and g ( x ) = 1 − δ. Close Quit

  6. How Can We Describe . . . 5. In Some Cases, We Have Both Types of Mea- Case of Absolute . . . surement Errors Case of Relative . . . Towards a General Case • In some cases, we have both additive (absolute) and From Measurements . . . multiplicative (relative) measurement errors: Main Result about f A ( u ) − ∆ − δ · A ( u ) ≤ M ( u ) ≤ A ( u ) + ∆ + δ · A ( u ) . What If There Is No Bias? No-Bias Results • In this case: Home Page M ( u ) − ∆ ≤ A ( u ) ≤ M ( u ) + ∆ Title Page . 1 + δ 1 − δ ◭◭ ◮◮ • So, we have f ( M ( u )) ≤ A ( u ) ≤ g ( M ( u )) , where: ◭ ◮ = x − ∆ = x + ∆ def def f ( x ) 1 + δ and f ( x ) 1 − δ . Page 6 of 21 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  7. How Can We Describe . . . 6. Towards a General Case Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . • The above formulas assume that the measurement ac- Towards a General Case curacy is the same for the whole range. From Measurements . . . • In reality, measuring instruments have different accu- Main Result about f racies ∆ and δ in different ranges. What If There Is No Bias? • Hence, f ( x ) and g ( x ) are non-linear. No-Bias Results Home Page • When M ( u ) is larger, this means that the bounds on possible values of A ( u ) increase (or do not decrease). Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ • Thus, f ( x ) and g ( x ) are monotonic. ◭ ◮ • To describe the accuracy of a general measuring instru- ment, it is therefore reasonable to use: Page 7 of 21 – the largest of the monotonic functions f ( x ) for Go Back which f ( M ( u )) ≤ A ( u ) and Full Screen – the smallest of the monotonic functions g ( x ) for Close which A ( u ) ≤ g ( M ( u )). Quit

  8. How Can We Describe . . . 7. From Measurements to Expert Estimates Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . • In areas such as medicine, expert estimates are very Towards a General Case important. From Measurements . . . • Expert estimates often result in “values” from a par- Main Result about f tially ordered set. What If There Is No Bias? No-Bias Results • Examples: “somewhat probable”, “very probable”, Home Page etc. Title Page • Such possibilities are described in different generaliza- tions of the traditional [0 , 1]-based fuzzy logic. ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ • In all such extensions, there is order (sometimes par- tial) on the corresponding set of value L : Page 8 of 21 ℓ < ℓ ′ means that ℓ ′ represents a stronger expert’s Go Back degree of confidence than ℓ . Full Screen Close Quit

  9. How Can We Describe . . . 8. Need to Describe Uncertainty of Expert Esti- Case of Absolute . . . mates Case of Relative . . . Towards a General Case • Some experts are very good, in the sense that based on From Measurements . . . their estimates S ( u ), we make very effective decisions. Main Result about f • Other experts may be less accurate. What If There Is No Bias? • It is therefore desirable to gauge the uncertainty of such No-Bias Results experts in relation to the “standard” (very good) ones. Home Page • To make a good decision based on the expert’s estimate Title Page M ( u ), we need to produce bounds on S ( u ): ◭◭ ◮◮ f ( M ( u )) ≤ S ( u ) ≤ g ( M ( u )) . ◭ ◮ • It is thus desirable to find: Page 9 of 21 – the largest of the monotonic functions f ( x ) for Go Back which f ( M ( u )) ≤ S ( u ) and Full Screen – the smallest of the monotonic functions g ( x ) for Close which S ( u ) ≤ g ( M ( u )). Quit

  10. How Can We Describe . . . 9. What Is Known and What We Do in This Talk Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . • When L = [0 , 1], the existence of the largest f ( x ) and Towards a General Case smallest g ( x ) is already known. From Measurements . . . • We analyze for which partially ordered sets such largest Main Result about f f ( x ) and smallest g ( x ) exist. What If There Is No Bias? No-Bias Results • It turns out that they exist for complete lattices. Home Page • In general, they do not exist for more general partially Title Page ordered sets. ◭◭ ◮◮ • To be more precise, ◭ ◮ – the largest f ( x ) always exists only for complete Page 10 of 21 lower semi-lattices (definitions given later), while – the smallest g ( x ) always exists only for complete Go Back upper semi-lattices. Full Screen Close Quit

  11. How Can We Describe . . . 10. Main Result about f Case of Absolute . . . Case of Relative . . . • By F ( F, G ), we denote the set of all monotonic func- Towards a General Case tions f for which f ( F ( u )) ≤ G ( u ) for all u ∈ U . From Measurements . . . • An ordered set is called a complete lower semi-lattice Main Result about f if for every set S : What If There Is No Bias? No-Bias Results – among all its lower bounds, Home Page – there exists the largest one. Title Page • Theorem. For an ordered set L , the following two ◭◭ ◮◮ conditions are equivalent to each other: ◭ ◮ – L is a complete lower semi-lattice; Page 11 of 21 – for every two functions F, G : U → L , the set F ( F, G ) has the largest element. Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend