extending algorithmic
play

Extending Algorithmic New Definition of . . . Need to Extend . . . - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Physicists Usually . . . Kolmogorovs . . . New Definition of . . . Extending Algorithmic New Definition of . . . Need to Extend . . . Randomness to Natural Extension of . . . the Algebraic Approach Consistency Result: . . . Consistency:


  1. Physicists Usually . . . Kolmogorov’s . . . New Definition of . . . Extending Algorithmic New Definition of . . . Need to Extend . . . Randomness to Natural Extension of . . . the Algebraic Approach Consistency Result: . . . Consistency: Proof to Quantum Physics: Acknowledgments Title Page Kolmogorov Complexity ◭◭ ◮◮ and Quantum Logics ◭ ◮ Page 1 of 24 Vladik Kreinovich Department of Computer Science Go Back University of Texas, El Paso, TX 79968, USA Full Screen vladik@utep.edu Close Quit

  2. Physicists Usually . . . 1. Physicists Usually Assume that Events with a Very Kolmogorov’s . . . Small Probability Cannot Occur New Definition of . . . New Definition of . . . • Known phenomenon: Brownian motion. Need to Extend . . . • In principle: due to Brownian motion, a kettle placed Natural Extension of . . . on a cold stove can start boiling. Consistency Result: . . . • The probability of this event is positive but very small. Consistency: Proof Acknowledgments • A mathematician would say that this event is possible Title Page but rare. ◭◭ ◮◮ • A physicist would say that this event is simply not ◭ ◮ possible. Page 2 of 24 • It is desirable: to formalize this intuition of physicists. Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  3. Physicists Usually . . . 2. Kolmogorov’s Definition of Algorithmic Random- Kolmogorov’s . . . ness New Definition of . . . New Definition of . . . • Kolmogorov: proposed a new definition of a random Need to Extend . . . sequence, a definition that separates Natural Extension of . . . – physically random binary sequences, e.g.: Consistency Result: . . . ∗ sequences that appear in coin flipping experi- Consistency: Proof ments, Acknowledgments ∗ sequences that appear in quantum measurements Title Page – from sequence that follow some pattern. ◭◭ ◮◮ • Intuitively: if a sequence s is random, it satisfies all the ◭ ◮ probability laws. Page 3 of 24 • What is a probability law: a statement S which is true Go Back with probability 1: P ( S ) = 1. Full Screen • Conclusion: to prove that a sequence is not random, Close we must show that it does not satisfy one of these laws. Quit

  4. Physicists Usually . . . 3. Kolmogorov’s Definition of Algorithmic Random- Kolmogorov’s . . . ness (cont-d) New Definition of . . . New Definition of . . . • Reminder: a sequence s is not random if it does not Need to Extend . . . satisfy one of the probability laws S . Natural Extension of . . . • Equivalent statement: s is not random if s ∈ C for a Consistency Result: . . . (definable) set C (= − S ) with P ( C ) = 0. Consistency: Proof • Resulting definition (Kolmogorov, Martin-L¨ of): s is Acknowledgments random if s �∈ C for all definable C with P ( C ) = 0. Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ • Consistency proof: ◭ ◮ – Every definable set C is defined by a finite sequence of symbols (its definition). Page 4 of 24 – Since there are countably many sequences of sym- Go Back bols, there are countably many definable sets C . Full Screen – So, the complement −R to the class R of all ran- Close dom sequences also has probability 0. Quit

  5. Physicists Usually . . . 4. Towards a More Physically Adequate Versions of Kolmogorov’s . . . Kolmogorov Randomness New Definition of . . . New Definition of . . . • Problem: the 1960s Kolmogorov’s definition only ex- Need to Extend . . . plains why events with probability 0 do not happen. Natural Extension of . . . • What we need: formalize the physicists’ intuition that Consistency Result: . . . events with very small probability cannot happen. Consistency: Proof • Seemingly natural formalization: there exists the “small- Acknowledgments est possible probability” p 0 such that: Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ – if the computed probability p of some event is larger than p 0 , then this event can occur, while ◭ ◮ – if the computed probability p is ≤ p 0 , the event Page 5 of 24 cannot occur. Go Back • Example: a fair coin falls heads 100 times with prob. Full Screen 2 − 100 ; it is impossible if p 0 ≥ 2 − 100 . Close Quit

  6. Physicists Usually . . . 5. The Above Formalization of Randomness is Not Kolmogorov’s . . . Always Adequate New Definition of . . . New Definition of . . . • Problem: every sequence of heads and tails has exactly Need to Extend . . . the same probability. Natural Extension of . . . • Corollary: if we choose p 0 ≥ 2 − 100 , we will thus exclude Consistency Result: . . . all sequences of 100 heads and tails. Consistency: Proof • However, anyone can toss a coin 100 times. Acknowledgments Title Page • This proves that some such sequences are physically ◭◭ ◮◮ possible. ◭ ◮ • Similar situation: Kyburg’s lottery paradox: Page 6 of 24 – in a big (e.g., state-wide) lottery, the probability of winning the Grand Prize is very small; Go Back – a reasonable person should not expect to win; Full Screen – however, some people do win big prizes. Close Quit

  7. Physicists Usually . . . 6. New Definition of Randomness Kolmogorov’s . . . New Definition of . . . • Example: height: New Definition of . . . – if height is ≥ 6 ft, it is still normal; Need to Extend . . . – if instead of 6 ft, we consider 6 ft 1 in, 6 ft 2 in, etc., Natural Extension of . . . then ∃ h 0 s.t. everyone taller than h 0 is abnormal; Consistency Result: . . . – we are not sure what is h 0 , but we are sure such h 0 Consistency: Proof exists. Acknowledgments Title Page • General description: on the universal set U , we have ◭◭ ◮◮ sets A 1 ⊇ A 2 ⊇ . . . ⊇ A n ⊇ . . . s.t. P ( ∩ A n ) = 0. ◭ ◮ • Example: A 1 = people w/height ≥ 6 ft, A 2 = people w/height ≥ 6 ft 1 in, etc. Page 7 of 24 • A set R ⊆ U is called a set of random elements if Go Back Full Screen ∀ definable sequence of sets A n for which A n ⊇ A n +1 for all n and P ( ∩ A n ) = 0, ∃ N for which A N ∩ R = ∅ . Close Quit

  8. Physicists Usually . . . 7. Definable: Mathematical Comment Kolmogorov’s . . . New Definition of . . . • What is definable: New Definition of . . . – let L be a theory, Need to Extend . . . – let P ( x ) be a formula from the language of the the- Natural Extension of . . . ory L , with one free variable x Consistency Result: . . . – so that the set { x | P ( x ) } is defined in L . Consistency: Proof Acknowledgments We will then call the set { x | P ( x ) } L -definable . Title Page • How to deal with definable sets: ◭◭ ◮◮ – Our objective is to be able to make mathematical ◭ ◮ statements about L -definable sets. Page 8 of 24 – Thus, we must have a stronger theory M in which Go Back the class of all L -definable sets is a countable set. Full Screen – One can prove that such M always exists. Close Quit

  9. Physicists Usually . . . 8. Coin Example Kolmogorov’s . . . New Definition of . . . • Universal set U = { H , T } I N New Definition of . . . • Here, A n is the set of all the sequences that start with Need to Extend . . . n heads. Natural Extension of . . . • The sequence { A n } is decreasing and definable, and its Consistency Result: . . . intersection has probability 0. Consistency: Proof Acknowledgments • Therefore, for every set R of random elements of U , Title Page there exists an integer N for which A N ∩ R = ∅ . ◭◭ ◮◮ • This means that if a sequence s ∈ R is random and ◭ ◮ starts with N heads, it must consist of heads only. Page 9 of 24 • In physical terms: it means that Go Back a random sequence cannot start with N heads. Full Screen • This is exactly what we wanted to formalize. Close Quit

  10. Physicists Usually . . . 9. From Random to Typical (Not Abnormal) Kolmogorov’s . . . New Definition of . . . • Fact: not all solutions to the physical equations are New Definition of . . . physically meaningful. Need to Extend . . . • Example 1: when a cup breaks into pieces, the corre- Natural Extension of . . . sponding trajectories of molecules make physical sense. Consistency Result: . . . • Example 2: when we reverse all the velocities, we get Consistency: Proof pieces assembling themselves into a cup. Acknowledgments Title Page • Physical fact: this is physically impossible. ◭◭ ◮◮ • Mathematical fact: the reverse process satisfies all the ◭ ◮ original (T-invariant) equations. Page 10 of 24 • Physicist’s explanation: the reversed process is non- physical since its initial conditions are “degenerate”. Go Back Full Screen • Clarification: once we modify the initial conditions even slightly, the pieces will no longer get together. Close Quit

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend