mekler s construction and generalized stability
play

Meklers construction and generalized stability Artem Chernikov UCLA - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Meklers construction and generalized stability Artem Chernikov UCLA Automorphism Groups, Differential Galois Theory and Model Theory Barcelona, June 26, 2017 Joint work with Nadja Hempel (UCLA). Meklers construction Let p >


  1. Mekler’s construction and generalized stability Artem Chernikov UCLA “Automorphism Groups, Differential Galois Theory and Model Theory” Barcelona, June 26, 2017

  2. Joint work with Nadja Hempel (UCLA).

  3. Mekler’s construction ◮ Let p > 2 be prime. ◮ Let T be any theory in a finite relational language. ◮ [Mekler’81] A uniform construction of a group G ( M ) for = T , a theory T ∗ of all groups { G ( M ) : M | every M | = T } and an interpretation Γ of T in T ∗ s.t.: ◮ T ∗ is a theory of nilpotent groups of class 2 and of exponent p , ◮ if G | = T ∗ , then ∃M | = T s.t. G ( M ) ≡ G , ◮ For M , N | = T , M ≡ N ⇐ ⇒ G ( M ) ≡ G ( N ) , ◮ Γ ( G ( M )) ∼ = M . ◮ Idea: ◮ Bi-interpret M with a nice graph C . ◮ Define a group G ( C ) generated freely by the vertices of C , imposing that two generators commute ⇐ ⇒ they are connected by an edge in C . ◮ This kind of coding of graphs is known in probabilistic group theory, recursion theory, etc.

  4. What model-theoretic properties are preserved? ◮ This is not a bi-interpretation (e.g., the resulting group is never ω -categorical), however some model-theoretic tameness properties are known to be preserved. ◮ [Mekler ’81] For any cardinal κ , Th ( M ) is κ -stable ⇐ ⇒ Th ( G ( M )) is κ -stable. ◮ [Baudisch, Pentzel ’02] Th ( M ) is simple ⇐ ⇒ Th ( G ( M )) is simple. ◮ [Baudisch ’02] Assuming stability, Th ( M ) is CM-trivial ⇐ ⇒ Th ( G ( M )) is CM-trivial. ◮ We investigate what further properties from Shelah’s classification are preserved.

  5. k -dependent theories ◮ We fix a complete theory T in a language L . For k ≥ 1 we define: Definition [Shelah] ◮ A formula φ ( x ; y 1 , . . . , y k ) is k -dependent if there are no infinite sets A i = { a i , j : j ∈ ω } ⊆ M y i , i ∈ { 1 , . . . , k } in a model M of T such that A = � n i = 1 A i is shattered by φ , where “ A shattered” means: for any s ⊆ ω k , there is some b s ∈ M x s.t. M | = φ ( b s ; a 1 , j 1 , . . . , a k , j k ) ⇐ ⇒ ( j 1 , . . . , j k ) ∈ s . ◮ T is k -dependent if all formulas are k -dependent. ◮ T is strictly k -dependent if it is k -dependent, but not ( k − 1 ) -dependent. ◮ T is 1-dependent ⇐ ⇒ T is NIP. ◮ 1-dependent � 2-dependent � . . . as witnessed by e.g. the theory of the random k -hypergraph.

  6. k -dependent fields? ◮ Problem. Are there strictly k -dependent fields, for k > 1? ◮ Conjecture. There are no simple strictly k -dependent fields, for k > 1. ◮ [Hempel ’15] Let K be an infinite field. 1. If Th ( K ) is k -dependent, then K is Artin-Schreier closed. 2. If K is a PAC field which is not separably closed, then Th ( K ) is not k -dependent for any k ∈ ω . ◮ (2) is due to Parigot for k = 1, and if K is pseudofinite, by Beyarslan K interprets the random k -hypergraph for all k ∈ ω .

  7. k -dependent groups ◮ Let T be a theory and G a type-definable group (over ∅ ), and A ⊆ M a small subset. ◮ Let G 00 A be the minimal type-definable over A subgroup of G of bounded index. Fact ⇒ G 00 A = G 00 T is NIP = for all small A . ∅ Example Let G := � ω F p . Let M := ( G , F p , 0 , + , · ) with · the bilinear form ( a i ) · ( b i ) = � i a i b i from G to F p . Then G is 2-dependent and G 00 � � A = g ∈ G : � a ∈ A g · a = 0 — gets smaller when enlarging A . Fact [Shelah] Let T be 2 -dependent. Then for a suitable cardinal κ , if M ≺ M is κ -saturated and | B | < κ , then G 00 M ∪ B = G 00 M ∩ G 00 A ∪ B for some A ⊆ M , | A | < κ . ◮ This can be viewed as a trace of modularity.

  8. Mekler’s construction preserves k -dependence ◮ No examples of strictly k -dependent groups for k > 2 were known. Theorem [C., Hempel ’17] For any k ∈ ω , Th ( M ) k -dependent ⇐ ⇒ Th ( G ( M )) is k -dependent. ◮ Applying Mekler’s construction to the random k -hypergraph, we get: Corollary For every k ∈ ω , there is a strictly k -dependent pure group G k (moreover, Th ( G k ) simple by Baudisch).

  9. A proof for NIP, 1 ◮ For a complete theory T , its stability spectrum is the function f T ( κ ) := sup {| S 1 ( M ) | : M | = T , | M | = κ } . ◮ ded ( κ ) := sup {| I | : I is a linear order with a dense subset of size κ } . Fact [Shelah] Let the language of T be countable. 1. If T is NIP , then f T ( κ ) ≤ ( ded κ ) ℵ 0 for all infinite cardinals κ . 2. If T has IP , then f T ( κ ) = 2 κ for all infinite cardinals κ . ◮ Assuming GCH, ded κ = 2 κ for all κ . On the other hand: ◮ [Mitchell] For every cardinal κ with cf ( κ ) > ℵ 0 , there is a forcing extension of the model of ZFC such that ( ded κ ) ℵ 0 < 2 κ .

  10. A proof for NIP, 2 ◮ The actual result in the original paper of Mekler is: Fact f Th ( G ( M )) ( κ ) ≤ f Th ( M ) ( κ ) + ℵ 0 for all infinite cardinals κ . ◮ Hence if Th ( M ) is NIP, then f Th ( G ( M )) ( κ ) ≤ ( ded κ ) ℵ 0 for all κ , in all models of ZFC. ◮ Combining with Mitchell and using Schoenfield’s absoluteness, Th ( G ( M )) is NIP. ◮ Admittedly this is somewhat esoteric, and more importantly doesn’t generalize to k > 1.

  11. Characterization of k -dependence ◮ We want a formula-free characterization of k -dependence (in Th ( G ( M )) we understand automorphisms, but not formulas). ◮ Let κ := | T | + . Fact T is NIP ⇐ ⇒ for every ( ∅ -)indiscernible sequence ( a i : i ∈ κ ) and b of finite tuples in M , there is some α ∈ κ such that ( a i : i > α ) is indiscernible over b . ◮ What is the analogue for k -dependence?

  12. Generalized indiscernibles ◮ T is a theory in a language L , M | = T . Definition Let I be an L 0 -structure. Say that ¯ a = ( a i : i ∈ I ) , with a i a tuple in M , is I -indiscernible over C ⊆ M if for all i 1 , . . . , i n and j 1 , . . . , j n from I : qftp L 0 ( i 1 , . . . , i n ) = qftp L 0 ( j 1 , . . . , j n ) = ⇒ tp L ( a i 1 , . . . , a i n / C ) = tp L ( a j 1 , . . . , a j n / C ) . ◮ For L 0 -structures I , J , say that ( b j : j ∈ J ) is based on ( a i : i ∈ I ) over C if for any finite set ∆ of L ( C ) -formulas and any ( j 0 , . . . , j n ) from J there is some ( i 1 , . . . , i n ) from I s.t. qftp L 0 ( j 1 , . . . , j n ) = qftp L 0 ( i 1 , . . . , i n ) and tp ∆ ( b j 1 , . . . , b j n ) = tp ∆ ( a i 1 , . . . , a i n ) . ◮ We say that I -indiscernibles exist if for any ¯ a indexed by I there is an I -indiscernible based on it.

  13. Connection to structural Ramsey theory ◮ Implicitly used by Shelah already in the classification book, made explicit by Scow and others. Definition � B � Let K be a class of finite L 0 -structures. For A , B ∈ K , let be A the set of all A ′ ⊆ B s.t. A ′ ∼ = A . K is Ramsey if for any A , B ∈ K and k ∈ ω there is some C ∈ K → k , there is some B ′ ∈ � C � C � � s.t. for any coloring f : s.t. A B � B ′ � f ↾ is constant. A ◮ Classical Ramsey theorem ⇐ ⇒ the class of finite linear orders is Ramsey. Fact Let K be a Fraïssé class, and let I be its limit. If K is Ramsey, then I -indiscernibles exist.

  14. Ordered random hypergraph indiscernibles Fact [Nesétril, Rödl ’77,’83] For any k ∈ ω , the class of all finite ordered k -hypergraphs is Ramsey. ◮ Fix k ∈ ω . Modifying their proof, we have existence of G -indiscernibles for G = ( P 1 , . . . , P k , R ( x 1 , . . . , x k ) , < ) the ordered k -partite random hypergraph (where P 1 < . . . < P k ). ◮ Let O = ( P 1 , . . . , P k , < ) denote the reduct of G . ◮ Of course, ( a g : g ∈ G ) is O -indiscernible / C implies it is G -indiscernible / C . ◮ Clarifying Shelah, Fact [C., Palacin, Takeuchi ’14] TFAE: 1. T is k -dependent. 2. For any ( a g : g ∈ G ) and b , with a g , b finite tuples in M , if ( a g : g ∈ G ) is G -indiscernible over b and O -indiscernible (over ∅ ), then it is O -indiscernible over b .

  15. Mekler’s construction in more detail, 1 ◮ A graph (binary, symmetric, irreflexive relation) C is nice if: ◮ ∃ a � = b , ◮ ∀ a � = b ∃ c ( R ( a , c ) ∧ ¬ R ( b , c )) , ◮ no triangles or squares. Fact Any structure in a finite relational language is bi-interpretable with a nice graph. ◮ Let G | = Th ( G ( C )) , where G ( C ) is generated freely by the vertices of C , and two generators commute ⇐ ⇒ they are connected by an edge in C s. ◮ We consider the following ∅ -definable equivalence relations on G , each refining the previous one: ◮ g ∼ h ⇐ ⇒ C G ( g ) = C G ( h ) , ◮ g ≈ h ⇐ ⇒ ∃ r ∈ ω, c ∈ Z ( G ) s.t. g = h r c . ◮ g ≡ Z h ⇐ ⇒ gZ ( G ) = hZ ( G ) .

  16. Mekler’s construction in more detail, 2 ◮ g ∈ G is of type q if ∃ q -many ≈ -classes in [ g ] ∼ . ◮ g is isolated if [ g ] ≈ = [ g ] ≡ Z . ◮ G can be partitioned into the following ∅ -definable set: ◮ non-isolated elements of type 1 — type 1 ν , ◮ isolated elements of type 1 — type 1 ι , ◮ elements of type p , ◮ elements of type p − 1. ◮ For every g ∈ G of type p , the elements of G commuting with it are: ◮ elements ∼ -equaivalent to g , ◮ an element b of type 1 ν together with the elements ∼ -equivalent to b . ◮ Such a b is called a handle of g , and is definable from g up to ∼ -equivalence.

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend