galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries
play

Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries Dmitry - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries Dmitry Sustretov Hebrew University of Jerusalem sustretov@ma.huji.ac.il Classification Theory Workshop, Daejeon August 9, 2014 Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D.


  1. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries Dmitry Sustretov Hebrew University of Jerusalem sustretov@ma.huji.ac.il Classification Theory Workshop, Daejeon August 9, 2014

  2. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Amalgamation problems Let p 12 ( x, y ) , p 23 ( y, z ) , p 13 ( x, z ) be three types over a set of parameters K . These three types amalgamate if there exists a type p 123 ( x, y, z ) such that whenever ( a 1 , a 2 , a 3 ) realizes p 123 , ( a 1 , a 2 ) realizes p 12 , ( a 2 , a 3 ) realizes p 23 and ( a 1 , a 3 ) realizes p 13 . A theory has 3-existence if any three types amalgamate. It is customary to assume that all tuples in question enumerate algebraically closed substrucutres of the monster model. 3-uniqueness (over K = a ∅ ): the type p 123 is unique, in other words, whenever a ij | = p ij and σ ij ∈ Aut( a ij /a i a j ) tp( a 12 a 23 a 13 /K ) = tp( σ 12 ( a 12 ) σ 23 ( a 23 ) σ 13 ( a 13 )) , in other words, the restriction map Aut( a 123 /a 1 a 2 a 3 ) → Aut( a 12 /a 1 a 2 ) × Aut( a 23 /a 2 a 3 ) × Aut( a 13 /a 1 a 3 ) is surjective, and 2-uniqueness amounts to the fact that for a 2-amalgamation problem Aut( a 12 /K ) → Aut( a 1 /K ) × Aut( a 2 /K ) is surjective. 1

  3. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov How 3-uniqueness can break down In stable theories, over an algebraically closed base set, 2-uniqueness (=sta- tionarity over a.c. base) holds. Therefore, if one considers K = a 3 as the base of amalgamation, Aut( a 123 /a 3 ) → Aut( a 13 /a 3 ) × Aut( a 23 /a 3 ) is surjective. Therefore, 3-uniqueness amounts to the map r : Aut( a 12 /a 23 a 13 ) → Aut( a 12 /a 1 a 2 ) being surjective. Remark (Hrushovski) If 3-uniqueness fails then image of Im r in the Abelian- isation Aut( a 12 /a 1 a 2 ) ab is a proper subgroup. Proposition (Goodrick, Kolesnikov) A failure of 3-uniqueness is witnessed by existence of a definable over K groupoid that is not eliminable (definitions will come later). It is a classic fact that group extensions with Abelian kernel are classified by second group cohomology. So it seems natural that a groupoid witnessing non-3-uniqueness ought to be related to it too. 2

  4. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Group cohomology Let G be a group acting on an Abelian group A (it is then called a G -module). The group cohomology H n ( G, A ) is a collection of groups associated in a functorial way to A . One concrete way to define it is as follows: A ( n -) cochain is a map G n → A . It is cocycle if it satisfies a certain condition which for small n is as follows: for n = 1 h ( στ ) = h ( σ ) + σ · h ( τ ) for n = 2 h ( ασ, τ ) = h ( α, στ ) − h ( α, σ ) + α · h ( σ, τ ) It is a coboundary if for n = 1 there exists g ∈ A such that h ( σ ) = σ ( g ) − g for n = 2 there exists g : G → A such that h ( σ, τ ) = g ( σ ) − g ( στ ) + σ · g ( τ ) The n -th cohomology group is the quotient of the group of n -cocycles by the group of n -coboundaries. The definition of H 1 can be stated for non-Abelian A , but it will no longer have structure of a group. If G is a profinite group, G = lim − G/G α , and the action of G on A is continuous, ← then one defines H n ( G, A ) = lim − H n ( G/G α , A G α ) ← 3

  5. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Galois cohomology and torsors Let M be a model and let A be an Abelian definable group defined over a set of parametrs K . Then A ( M ) is naturally a G = Aut( M/K )-module. If M = acl( K ) then G has a profinite structure and the action is continuous. A prinicipal homogeneous space over A or torsor is definable set X together with a free transitive action of A . Proposition ( Pillay ) Suppose the theory we work in has elimination of imag- inaries, and A = acl( K ). The set of isomorphism classes of torsors over A definable over K is in bijective correspondence with H 1 ( G, A ( M )). In fact, the addition operation in H 1 can be defined geometrically. Pillay has also worked out a definition of Galois cohomology in the setting where M is atomic over K where the above proposition is still true. 4

  6. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Group extensions Let A, B be groups, A Abelian. Proposition Consider a group extension 1 → A → G → B → 1 with A Abelian, and pick a section ι : B → G . Then b ∈ B acts on A by conjugation by ι ( b ), the action being independent from ι . The set of isomorphism classes of group extensions with the given action of B on A is in bijective correspodence with elements of H 2 ( B, A ). Split extensions correspond to the trivial cohomology class. The cohomology class is defined as follows: h ( σ, τ ) = ι ( σ ) ι ( τ ) ι ( στ ) − 1 , which turns out to be a cocycle, and its cohomology class does not depend on ι . If one is interested in profinite groups, H 2 only classifies extensions such that G → B has a continuous section. 5

  7. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Groupoids A groupoid is a category such that all its morphisms are isomorphisms. If a groupoid is small, i.e. if its objects and its morphisms are sets, then it is defined by the following data: a tuple X • = ( X 0 , X 1 ) of sets along with maps s, t, m, i, e , where s, t maps X 1 to X 0 (source and target objects), c maps X 1 × s,X 0 ,t X 1 to X 1 (composition of arrows), i maps X 1 to itself (inverse), e : X 0 → X 1 , satisfying the natural axioms. A definable groupoid is a pair of definable sets X 0 , X 1 along with the mor- phisms s, t, m, i, e satisfying the mentioned identities. If Mor( x, x ) is isomorphic to a group A for all x ∈ X 0 then the groupoid X • is said to be bounded by A . Example : G be a definable group, · : G × X → X be a group action. action groupoid : G × X ⇒ X where s ( g, x ) = x and t ( g, x ) = g · x , and ( g, x ) · ( h, gx ) = ( gh, x ); 6

  8. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Groupoid torsors Let X • be a groupoid. A groupoid homogeneous space for X • over Y is a morphism p : P → Y together with the anchor map a : P → X 0 and action map · : P × a,X 0 ,s X 1 → P which commutes with the projection to Y . A homogeneous space is called principal (or a torsor ) if for any two f, g ∈ P such that p ( f ) = p ( g ) there exists a unique m ∈ X 1 such that f · m = g . A morphism of groupoid torsors P and Q is a map α : P → Q that commutes with the action map: α ( m · f ) = m · α ( f ) for any a ∈ Ob( X • ) and any m ∈ Mor( a, s ( f )). Let X • be a groupoid. Let E be the equivalence relation on X 0 which is the image of the map ( s, t ) : X 1 → X 0 × X 0 . The quotient X 0 /E is called the groupoid quotient and is denoted [ X • ]. A groupoid X • is called eliminable if there exists a X • -groupoid torsor over [ X • ]. In the terminology introduced by Hrushovski groupoid torsors over [ X • ] with all the relevant structure maps are generalised imaginary sorts . Threorem ( Hrushovski ) In a stable theory with elimination of imaginaries, 3-uniqueness is equivalent to the fact that all groupoids with finitely many objects are eliminable. 7

  9. � � � Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Morita equivalence A Morita morphism f • : X • → Y • is a pair of maps f 0 : X 0 → Y 0 , f 1 : X 1 → Y 1 such that the diagram X 1 X 0 × X 0 f 0 × f 0 f 1 � Y 0 × Y 0 Y 1 commutes, f 0 is surjective and for any ( x 1 , x 2 ) ∈ X 0 × X 0 the map f 1 in- duces a bijection between Mor ( x, y ) and Mor ( f 0 ( x ) , f 0 ( y )). If one looks at groupoids as small categories, then the above conditions say precisely that Morita morphism defines a fully faithful functor which is surjective on objects. Two groupoids X • and Y • are called Morita equivalent if there exists a third groupoid Z • together with two Morita morphisms Z • → X • and Z • → Y • . Proposition Morita equivalence preserves eliminability. Proposition Generalised imaginary sorts corresponding to Morita equivalent groupoids are bi-interpretable. 8

  10. Galois cohomology and finite generalised imaginaries D. Sustretov Groupoids and group cohomology Notation: G K = Aut(acl( K ) / dcl( K )), G L/K = Aut(dcl( L ) / dcl( K )). Theorem (S.) Suppose M = acl( K ). There exists a bijictive correspondence   Morita equivalence classes of     connected groupoids     � � cohomology classes in H 2 ( G K , A ) ⇔ definable over K       and bounded by a group A   Eliminable groupoids correspond to the trivial cohomology class. There is an operation (Baer sum) on groupoids that is mapped by the cor- respondence to addition in cohomology groups. One can check that the diffirence of two Morita equivalent groupoids is eliminable, and then it is left to verify the bijectivity. 9

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend