dialetheism is an empirical hypothesis
play

Dialetheism is an empirical hypothesis David Ripley University of - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1/ 33 Dialetheism is an empirical hypothesis David Ripley University of Connecticut http://davewripley.rocks Amsterdam Colloquium 2015 davewripley@gmail.com 2/ 33 Overview Vagueness Semantic paradoxes davewripley@gmail.com Overview


  1. 1/ 33 Dialetheism is an empirical hypothesis David Ripley University of Connecticut http://davewripley.rocks Amsterdam Colloquium 2015 davewripley@gmail.com

  2. 2/ 33 Overview Vagueness Semantic paradoxes davewripley@gmail.com

  3. Overview Dialetheism 3/ 33 Overview Dialetheism davewripley@gmail.com

  4. Overview Dialetheism 4/ 33 Dialetheism is the view that: • there are some true contradictions, or • some things are both true and false, or • some truths have true negations. davewripley@gmail.com

  5. Overview Dialetheism 5/ 33 It is best known as a view about the liar paradox: This sentence is not true. davewripley@gmail.com

  6. Overview Dialetheism 6/ 33 But also: • semantic paradoxes • set-theoretic paradoxes • vagueness • motion • change • boundaries • fiction • law • etc davewripley@gmail.com

  7. Overview Dialetheism 6/ 33 But also: • semantic paradoxes • set-theoretic paradoxes • vagueness • motion • change • boundaries • fiction • law • etc davewripley@gmail.com

  8. Vagueness A dialetheist take 7/ 33 Vagueness A dialetheist take davewripley@gmail.com

  9. Vagueness A dialetheist take 8/ 33 • Three Meter Tammy is tall. • If two people differ in height by only 1mm, then either both are tall or both aren’t tall. • There is a series of people that starts with Three Meter Tammy and ends with One Meter William, such that any two adjacent people in the series differ in height by only 1mm. • So One Meter William is tall. davewripley@gmail.com

  10. Vagueness A dialetheist take 9/ 33 Each step works like this: • Person A and Person A ′ are either both tall or both not tall. • But Person A is tall, so it can’t be that they’re both not tall. • So they must both be tall. • So Person A ′ is tall. davewripley@gmail.com

  11. Vagueness A dialetheist take 9/ 33 Each step works like this: • Person A and Person A ′ are either both tall or both not tall. • But Person A is tall, so it can’t be that they’re both not tall. • So they must both be tall. • So Person A ′ is tall. What if A is both tall and not tall? davewripley@gmail.com

  12. Vagueness A dialetheist take 10/ 33 Soritical reasoning gets things right until it strikes a true contradiction, and then goes wrong. These true contradictions live in the borderline area. davewripley@gmail.com

  13. Vagueness The empirical upshot 11/ 33 Vagueness The empirical upshot davewripley@gmail.com

  14. Vagueness The empirical upshot 12/ 33 Here’s a phenomenon: speakers agree to sentences like ‘Person X is both tall and not tall’, when person X is a borderline case of ‘tall’. The question is: why? davewripley@gmail.com

  15. Vagueness The empirical upshot 13/ 33 The short answer: dunno. davewripley@gmail.com

  16. Vagueness The empirical upshot 14/ 33 The long answer: there are a number of possible theories, and it’s too soon to decide. davewripley@gmail.com

  17. Vagueness The empirical upshot 15/ 33 ‘Person X is both tall and not tall’ Consider: ‘Tall’ is just like ‘here’ or ‘now’; it’s an indexical, and it picks up tallness standards from the context. If the first ‘tall’ is evaluated w/r/t a different context from the second one, nothing contradictory need be happening. davewripley@gmail.com

  18. Vagueness The empirical upshot 16/ 33 This view has a problem: ‘now’ and ‘here’ require two occurrences for this to happen: • (1) Sam is hungry now, and Sam isn’t hungry now. (2) ∗ Sam is and isn’t hungry now. • (3) It’s cold here, and it’s not cold here. (4) ∗ It both is and isn’t cold here. davewripley@gmail.com

  19. Vagueness The empirical upshot 17/ 33 Vague predicates are not like this: • The circle is near the square and it isn’t near the square. • The circle both is and isn’t near the square. Both are fine in borderline cases. davewripley@gmail.com

  20. Vagueness The empirical upshot 18/ 33 This does not rule out context-based accounts. But it does show that the way context affects ‘tall’ is different from how it affects ‘here’ and ‘now’. davewripley@gmail.com

  21. Vagueness The empirical upshot 19/ 33 Among the hypotheses we should take seriously: people are simply reporting a contradictory truth. davewripley@gmail.com

  22. Vagueness The empirical upshot 20/ 33 Not all puppies and roses: Some participants accept ‘both P and not P ’ claims while rejecting both ‘ P ’ and ‘not P ’ claims. davewripley@gmail.com

  23. Semantic paradoxes A dialetheist take 21/ 33 Semantic paradoxes A dialetheist take davewripley@gmail.com

  24. Semantic paradoxes A dialetheist take 22/ 33 (L) The sentence (L) is not true. • (L) is true iff (L) is not true. • (L) is either true or not true. • Either way, it’s both true and not true. • So it is indeed both true and not true. Some truth—the claim that (L) is true—thus has a true negation. davewripley@gmail.com

  25. Semantic paradoxes A dialetheist take 23/ 33 Look out! • (Since (L) is true), Either (L) is true or Chomsky faked the moon landings. • (Since (L) isn’t true), So Chomsky faked the moon landings. This kind of funny business needs to be stopped. davewripley@gmail.com

  26. Semantic paradoxes A dialetheist take 24/ 33 The usual place to attack is the move from A ∨ B and ¬ A to B . If A and ¬ A are both true, then these premises hold, no matter what’s up with B . This means: classical logic must go. (Well, . . . ) davewripley@gmail.com

  27. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 25/ 33 Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot davewripley@gmail.com

  28. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 26/ 33 But it has to do more than just go: it must not be reintroduc able . Priest, Doubt Truth , p 88: “If one takes it that a dialetheic solution to the semantic paradoxes is correct, one must deny the coherence of Boolean negation.” Here, ‘Boolean negation’ is understood to be ‘a negation that behaves exactly as the classical account of negation says it does’. davewripley@gmail.com

  29. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 27/ 33 The thought is this: if Boolean negation ¬ B is coherent, then there is a sentence that says of itself that it is ¬ B true. But this sentence can’t be both true and ¬ B true, since then everything would be true. So we need to treat this sentence differently from the usual liar, suggesting that the root of the phenomenon has been missed. davewripley@gmail.com

  30. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 28/ 33 When we teach classical logic, sometimes we say things like: • ¬ B φ is true in I iff φ is not true in I . Do we thereby succeed in presenting Boolean negation? As Priest points out, the crux is the highlighted negation. davewripley@gmail.com

  31. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 29/ 33 Priest, Doubt Truth , p 98, after noting that the ‘not’ had better not be Boolean: “But now recall the dialectic. The point of the argument was precisely to establish the coherence of a notion satisfying the properties of classical negation. If the only way we can do this is by appealing to such a notion, and so presupposing its coherence, then the argument is clearly question-begging.” I think it is not so clear as this. davewripley@gmail.com

  32. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 30/ 33 We may legitimately presuppose the coherence of natural-language negation, whatever it is, even if it’s Boolean. (If negation isn’t coherent, we’ve got bigger problems!) What we cannot presuppose (in this dialectical situation) is that it is Boolean. davewripley@gmail.com

  33. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 31/ 33 So: we can define ¬ B via its truth conditions, expressed using natural-language negation. Whether ¬ B is Boolean or no— and so whether dialetheism has a problem here— depends on whether natural-language negation is Boolean. But this is simply a question about which entailments hold among natural-language sentences: it is a matter of formal semantics. davewripley@gmail.com

  34. Semantic paradoxes The empirical upshot 32/ 33 If natural-language negation is Boolean, there is no need to detour through ¬ B ; the dialetheist is already in trouble. If it’s not, then ¬ B as defined above isn’t Boolean either; the dialetheist survives this round. The status of natural-language negation matters. davewripley@gmail.com

  35. Conclusion 33/ 33 Dialetheism— the view that some truths have true negations— both provides and depends on substantive empirical hypotheses about natural-language negation. davewripley@gmail.com

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend