computability and complexity
play

Computability and Complexity Lecture 6 Reductions via Computation - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Computability and Complexity Lecture 6 Reductions via Computation Histories Undecidability of Emptiness of Linear Bounded Automata Undecidability of Post Correspondence Problem given by Jiri Srba Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 1/15


  1. Computability and Complexity Lecture 6 Reductions via Computation Histories Undecidability of Emptiness of Linear Bounded Automata Undecidability of Post Correspondence Problem given by Jiri Srba Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 1/15

  2. Reduction via Computation Histories Recall Reduction from A to B A language A is reducible to language B iff a decider for B can be used to algorithmically construct a decider for problem A . If A is reducible to B and A is undecidable, then B is undecidable. Definition (Accepting/Rejecting Computation History) Let M be a TM. A computation history of M on input w is a sequence of configurations C 1 , C 2 , . . . , C ℓ such that: C 1 = q 0 w is the initial configuration, C i yields C i +1 for all 1 ≤ i < ℓ , and C ℓ is a halting configuration (in either accept or reject state). If C ℓ is accepting, then the history is called accepting. If C ℓ is rejecting, then the history is called rejecting. M accepts w iff M on w has an accepting computation history. Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 2/15

  3. Linear Bounded Automaton and the Emptiness Problem Definition Linear bounded automaton (LBA) is a restricted Turing machine M such that when M runs on any input string w , its head always stays within the first | w | cells. Theorem The language A LBA is decidable. Emptiness Problem: ”Given an LBA B , is L ( B ) = ∅ ?” def = {� B � | B is an LBA such that L ( B ) = ∅ } E LBA Theorem The language E LBA is undecidable. Proof: By reduction from A TM to E LBA via computation histories. Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 3/15

  4. Proof (Reduction for A TM to E LBA ) 1 Assume that we have a decider R for E LBA . 2 Using R , we construct a decider S for A TM : S = ” On input � M , w � : 1. From M and w build an LBA B such that L ( B ) � = ∅ if and only if M accepts w 2. Run R (decider for E LBA ) on � B � . 3. If R accepted then S rejects. If R rejected then S accepts. ” 3 We know that S cannot exist, and hence R cannot exist either. 4 Conclusion: E LBA is undecidable. TO DO (The Tricky Part) From M and w construct an LBA B s.t. L ( B ) � = ∅ iff M accepts w . Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 4/15

  5. Proof (Construction of LBA B from M and w ) Idea: We construct B such that it accepts exactly all strings of the form # C 1 # C 2 # C 3 # . . . # C ℓ # where C 1 , C 2 , C 3 , . . . , C ℓ is an accepting computation history of M on w . Now clearly L ( B ) � = ∅ if and only if M accepts w . Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 5/15

  6. Proof (Construction of LBA B from M and w ) B = ” On input x : 1. If x is not of the form # C 1 # C 2 # . . . # C ℓ # for some strings C 1 , . . . , C ℓ then B rejects. 2. Verify whether # C 1 # C 2 # . . . # C ℓ # satisfies the following three conditions: a) C 1 = q 0 w b) C ℓ is an accept configuration c) C i yields C i +1 for all i (zigzag between them) 3. If all three conditions are true, then S accepts, else S rejects. ” Notice The constructed machine B is LBA. We actually never run B , it is merely the input for R (the decider for E LBA ) in order to achieve a contradiction. Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 6/15

  7. More Undecidable Problem from Language Theory Problem: ”Given a CFG G , is L ( G ) = Σ ∗ ?” = {� G � | G is a CFG such that L ( G ) = Σ ∗ } def ALL CFG Theorem The language ALL CFG is undecidable. Proof: very interesting technique based on computation histories (optional reading in the book). def = {� G 1 , G 2 � | G 1 and G 2 are CFGs s.t. L ( G 1 ) = L ( G 2 ) } EQ CFG Theorem The language EQ CFG is undecidable. Proof: By reduction from ALL CFG . Next tutorial. Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 7/15

  8. Post Correspondence Problem (Emil Post, 1946) Instance of the Post Correspondence Problem (PCP): A PCP instance over Σ is a finite collection P of dominos � t 1 � t 2 � t k P = { � � , · · · , � } , b 1 b 2 b k where for all i , 1 ≤ i ≤ k , t i , b i ∈ Σ ∗ . Match: Assume a given PCP instance P . A match is a nonempty sequence i 1 , i 2 , . . . , i ℓ of numbers from { 1 , 2 , . . . , k } (repeating is allowed) such that t i 1 t i 2 . . . t i ℓ = b i 1 b i 2 . . . b i ℓ . Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 8/15

  9. Post Correspondence Problem (PCP) Question: Does a given PCP instance P have a match? Language formulation: PCP def = {� P � | P is a PCP instance and it has a match } Theorem The language PCP is undecidable. Proof: By reduction via computation histories from A TM . Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 9/15

  10. Proof Structure (Undecidability of PCP) The reduction will work in two steps: 1 We reduce A TM to MPCP . 2 We reduce MPCP to PCP . MPCP (Modified PCP): MPCP def = {� P � | P is a PCP instance and it has a match which starts with index 1 } In reduction from A TM we will without loss of generality assume that on input � M , w � of A TM the machine M never attempts to move its head off the left-hand end of the tape. Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 10/15

  11. Proof (Reduction from A TM to MPCP ) For input � M , w � of A TM construct a MPCP instance P such that M accepts w iff P has a match starting with domino 1. # � � 1 Add a start (first) domino . # q 0 w # � qa � 2 If δ ( q , a ) = ( r , b , R ) add the domino . br � cqa � 3 If δ ( q , a ) = ( r , b , L ) add the domino for all c ∈ Γ. rcb � a � 4 Add the domino for all a ∈ Γ. a � # � # � � 5 Add the dominos and . # ⊔ # � aq accept � q accept a � � 6 Add the dominos for all a ∈ Γ. and q accept q accept � q accept ## � 7 Finally add the domino . # Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 11/15

  12. Proof (Reduction from MPCP to PCP ) Conclusion MPCP is undecidable. Now we want to reduce MPCP to PCP : Given an instance P of MPCP we build an instance P ′ of PCP s.t. P has a match starting with domino 1 iff P ′ has a match. Let w = a 1 a 2 . . . a n be a string. We use the notation ∗ w def = ∗ a 1 ∗ a 2 ∗ . . . ∗ a n , w ∗ def = a 1 ∗ a 2 ∗ . . . ∗ a n ∗ , and ∗ w ∗ def = ∗ a 1 ∗ a 2 ∗ . . . ∗ a n ∗ . Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 12/15

  13. Proof (Reduction from MPCP to PCP ) Given an instance P of MPCP we build an instance P ′ of PCP s.t. P has a match starting with domino 1 iff P ′ has a match. Construction of P ′ from P (here ∗ and ⋄ are fresh symbols): � t 1 � ∗ t 1 � � to P ′ . For the first domino in P we add ∗ b 1 ∗ b 1 � t i � ∗ t i � � For all dominos in P we add the dominos to P ′ . b i b i ∗ � ∗⋄ � We add the domino to P ′ . ⋄ It is easy to see that if in P (where i 1 = 1) t i 1 t i 2 . . . t i ℓ = b i 1 b i 2 . . . b t ℓ then in P ′ ∗ t i 1 ∗ t i 2 ∗ . . . ∗ t i ℓ ∗ ⋄ = ∗ b i 1 ∗ b i 2 ∗ . . . ∗ b t ℓ ∗ ⋄ and vice verse. Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 13/15

  14. Conclusion Conclusion PCP is undecidable. Facts: Undecidability of PCP can be further used to show that e.g. the following problems are undecidable too: ”Is a given CGF ambiguous?” ”Given CFGs G 1 and G 2 is L ( G 1 ) ∩ L ( G 2 ) = ∅ ?” And many more ... Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 14/15

  15. Exam Questions Undecidability of emptiness for LBA. PCP and MPCP definitions and examples. Undecidability proofs of MPCP and PCP (two reductions). Lecture 6 Computability and Complexity 15/15

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend