units without degeneracy from polycategories to sequent
play

Units without degeneracy, from polycategories to sequent calculi - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Units without degeneracy, from polycategories to sequent calculi Amar Hadzihasanovic ( ) RIMS, Kyoto University Kanazawa, 6 March 2018 Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky


  1. Units without degeneracy, from polycategories to sequent calculi Amar Hadzihasanovic ( ハジハサノヴィチ · アマル ) RIMS, Kyoto University Kanazawa, 6 March 2018

  2. Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky claim: all homotopy types are equivalent to strict homotopy types.

  3. Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky claim: all homotopy types are equivalent to strict homotopy types. 1998. C. Simpson: Wrong! False for d ≥ 3.

  4. Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky claim: all homotopy types are equivalent to strict homotopy types. 1998. C. Simpson: Wrong! False for d ≥ 3. But Conjecture: All homotopy types are equivalent to ones that are strict, except for the units

  5. Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky claim: all homotopy types are equivalent to strict homotopy types. 1998. C. Simpson: Wrong! False for d ≥ 3. But Conjecture: All homotopy types are equivalent to ones that are strict, except for the units (2006. Joyal, Kock: d = 3)

  6. Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky 1989. Danos, Regnier: claim: all homotopy types proof equivalence for are equivalent to strict MLL without units homotopy types. decidable in P time, with proof nets 1998. C. Simpson: Wrong! False for d ≥ 3. But Conjecture: All homotopy types are equivalent to ones that are strict, except for the units (2006. Joyal, Kock: d = 3)

  7. Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky 1989. Danos, Regnier: claim: all homotopy types proof equivalence for are equivalent to strict MLL without units homotopy types. decidable in P time, with proof nets 1998. C. Simpson: Wrong! False for d ≥ 3. 2014. Heijltjes, Houston: proof equivalence for But Conjecture: MLL with units is All homotopy types are equivalent PSPACE-complete to ones that are strict, except for the units (2006. Joyal, Kock: d = 3)

  8. Trouble with units in topology and logic 1991. Kapranov, Voevodsky 1989. Danos, Regnier: claim: all homotopy types proof equivalence for are equivalent to strict MLL without units homotopy types. decidable in P time, with proof nets 1998. C. Simpson: Wrong! False for d ≥ 3. 2014. Heijltjes, Houston: proof equivalence for But Conjecture: MLL with units is All homotopy types are equivalent PSPACE-complete to ones that are strict, except for the units No proof nets for MLL with (2006. Joyal, Kock: d = 3) units

  9. Poly-bicategories (Cockett-Koslowski-Seely) 0-cells x , y , . . . Topology : points; Logic : a unique 0-cell (polycategory)

  10. Poly-bicategories (Cockett-Koslowski-Seely) 0-cells x , y , . . . Topology : points; Logic : a unique 0-cell (polycategory) 1-cells A , B , . . . : x → y Topology : paths; Logic : formulae

  11. Poly-bicategories (Cockett-Koslowski-Seely) 0-cells x , y , . . . Topology : points; Logic : a unique 0-cell (polycategory) 1-cells A , B , . . . : x → y Topology : paths; Logic : formulae 2-cells p , q , . . . : ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( B 1 , . . . , B m ) Topology : disks; Logic : sequents x + x + 2 m B 1 B m p x − x + A 1 A n x − x − n 2

  12. Composition (cut) ( b ) ( a ) ( c ) ( d )

  13. Composition (cut) Γ 1 ⊢ ∆ 1 , A A , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆ 2 cut b Γ 1 , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆ 1 , ∆ 2 Γ ⊢ ∆ 1 , A , ∆ 2 A ⊢ ∆ Γ ⊢ A Γ 1 , A , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆ cut a cut c Γ ⊢ ∆ 1 , ∆ , ∆ 2 Γ 1 , Γ , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆ Γ 2 ⊢ A , ∆ 2 Γ 1 , A ⊢ ∆ 1 cut d Γ 1 , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆ 1 , ∆ 2

  14. Divisible 2-cells i p := A i , ∂ + Given p : ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( B 1 , . . . , B m ), let ∂ − j p := B j

  15. Divisible 2-cells i p := A i , ∂ + Given p : ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( B 1 , . . . , B m ), let ∂ − j p := B j A 2-cell t : ( A , B ) → ( C ) is divisible at ∂ + 1 if ∆ ∆ ∀ ∃ ! ˜ p p = C Γ 1 Γ 2 Γ 1 t Γ 2 A B A B

  16. Divisible 2-cells A 2-cell t : ( A , B ) → ( C ) is divisible at ∂ − 2 if C C ∀ ∃ ! ∆ ∆ t p = p ˜ B A A Γ Γ

  17. Divisible 2-cells produce rules of sequent calculus t : ( A , B ) → ( A ⊗ B ) divisible at ∂ + 1 : ∆ ∆ ∃ ! ∀ p ˜ p A ⊗ B = Γ 1 Γ 2 Γ 1 t Γ 2 A B A B Γ 1 , A , B , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆ ⊗ L Γ 1 , A ⊗ B , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆

  18. Divisible 2-cells produce rules of sequent calculus t : ( A , B ) → ( A ⊗ B ) divisible at ∂ + 1 : A ⊗ B ∆ 1 ∆ 2 t p q A B Γ 1 Γ 2 Γ 1 ⊢ ∆ 1 , A Γ 2 ⊢ B , ∆ 2 ⊗ R Γ 1 , Γ 2 ⊢ ∆ 1 , A ⊗ B , ∆ 2

  19. Units: the usual approach 2-cells ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( A ), with n ≥ 2, divisible at ∂ + 1 , model composition of paths in topology, and n -ary tensors (or conjunctions) in logic

  20. Units: the usual approach 2-cells ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( A ), with n ≥ 2, divisible at ∂ + 1 , model composition of paths in topology, and n -ary tensors (or conjunctions) in logic Dually (self-dually in topology), ( B ) → ( B 1 , . . . , B n ) divisible at ∂ − 1 model n -ary pars or disjunctions

  21. Units: the usual approach 2-cells ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( A ), with n ≥ 2, divisible at ∂ + 1 , model composition of paths in topology, and n -ary tensors (or conjunctions) in logic Dually (self-dually in topology), ( B ) → ( B 1 , . . . , B n ) divisible at ∂ − 1 model n -ary pars or disjunctions Units /constant paths (in Cockett-Seely and Hermida) � divisible 2-cells with a degenerate boundary (0-ary tensors/pars) 1

  22. Coherence via universality Multicategory A polycategory where all 2-cells have a single output. ( � intuitionistic sequent calculi) Representable multicategory For all composable ( A 1 , . . . , A n ), n ≥ 0, there exists an “ n -ary tensor” 2-cell ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( ⊗ n i =1 A i ) divisible at ∂ + 1 .

  23. Coherence via universality Multicategory A polycategory where all 2-cells have a single output. ( � intuitionistic sequent calculi) Representable multicategory For all composable ( A 1 , . . . , A n ), n ≥ 0, there exists an “ n -ary tensor” 2-cell ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( ⊗ n i =1 A i ) divisible at ∂ + 1 . Hermida, 2000 Monoidal categories and strong monoidal functors are equivalent to representable multicategories (with a choice of divisible 2-cells) and morphisms that preserve divisibility at ∂ + 1 .

  24. Coherence via universality Representable polycategory For all composable ( A 1 , . . . , A n ), n ≥ 0, there exists an “ n -ary i =1 A i ) divisible at ∂ + tensor” 2-cell ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) → ( ⊗ n 1 , and an “ n -ary par” 2-cell ( ` n i =1 A i ) → ( A 1 , . . . , A n ) divisible at ∂ − 1 . Linearly distributive categories and strong linear functors are equivalent to representable polycategories (with a choice of divisible 2-cells) and morphisms that preserve divisibility at ∂ + 1 and ∂ − 1 .

  25. So, all’s good up to dimension 2... But: If we allow 2-cells with degenerate input or output boundary, we must allow 2-cells with overall 0-dimensional boundary. (Although in most examples these are unnatural.)

  26. So, all’s good up to dimension 2... But: If we allow 2-cells with degenerate input or output boundary, we must allow 2-cells with overall 0-dimensional boundary. (Although in most examples these are unnatural.) If we want (in topology) to model higher-dimensional homotopy types, or (in logic) the dynamics of reduction/cut elimination, we need higher-dimensional cells .

  27. So, all’s good up to dimension 2... But: If we allow 2-cells with degenerate input or output boundary, we must allow 2-cells with overall 0-dimensional boundary. (Although in most examples these are unnatural.) If we want (in topology) to model higher-dimensional homotopy types, or (in logic) the dynamics of reduction/cut elimination, we need higher-dimensional cells . Put these two together � problems, problems, problems!

  28. So, all’s good up to dimension 2... But: If we allow 2-cells with degenerate input or output boundary, we must allow 2-cells with overall 0-dimensional boundary. (Although in most examples these are unnatural.) If we want (in topology) to model higher-dimensional homotopy types, or (in logic) the dynamics of reduction/cut elimination, we need higher-dimensional cells . Put these two together � problems, problems, problems! A solution: regularity Input and output boundaries of 2-cells are 1-dimensional (in general: k -boundaries of n -cells are k -dimensional)

  29. We need a new definition for units Idea: Saavedra unit (J. Kock, 2006), reformulated Tensor unit 1 x : x → x For all A : x → y , B : z → x , there exist y x z x A B r B l A 1 x 1 x A B , x x respectively divisible at ∂ + 2 , and at ∂ + 1 and ∂ − 1 and ∂ − 1 . Induces the correct coherent structure (triangle equations, etc)

  30. But we can do better Tensor left divisible 1-cell E : x → x ′ For all A : x → y , A ′ : x ′ → y , there exist y y x x E ⊗ A ′ A e R t E , A ′ E , A E E ⊸ A E A ′ , x ′ x ′ divisible both at ∂ + 1 and ∂ − 2 .

  31. But we can do better Tensor right divisible 1-cell E : x → x ′ For all B : z → x , B ′ : z → x ′ , there exist x ′ x ′ z B ′ z B ⊗ E e L t B , E E , B ′ B ′ › E E B E , x x divisible both at ∂ + 1 and ∂ − 1 . Tensor divisible 1-cell E : x → x ′ Tensor right and left divisible 1-cell.

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend