topological applications of long 1 approximation sequences
play

Topological applications of long 1 -approximation sequences David - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Topological applications of long 1 -approximation sequences David Milovich Texas A&M International University 2015 Winter School in Abstract Analysis Hejnice, Czech Republic A long time ago, some authors used curve to denote an


  1. Topological applications of long ω 1 -approximation sequences David Milovich Texas A&M International University 2015 Winter School in Abstract Analysis Hejnice, Czech Republic

  2. A long time ago, some authors used “curve” to denote an isometric copy of a graph of a function R → R . (Continuity is not required.) If such a curve is a measurable subset of R 2 , then it is null. However, Sierpi´ nski showed (1933) that, assuming CH, the plane is a countable union of graphs of functions and their converses: • Let ⊳ order R with type ω 1 . • Let f x map ω onto { y : y � x } . • Let g n ( x ) = f x ( n ). n<ω ( g n ∪ g − 1 x ∈ R { ( x, g n ( x )) , ( g n ( x ) , x ) } = R 2 • � n ) = � � n<ω Thus, CH implies that the plane is a countable union of curves. 1

  3. Sierpi´ nski asked (1951) if CH is needed to cover the plane by count- ably many curves. Roy O. Davies answered “no” (1963) with an ingenious ZFC cov- ering. (Never underestimate the axiom of choice!) To cover the plane by countable many curves, it is enough to parti- tion the plane into countably many partial curves. Fix an ω -sequence pairwise non-parallel lines ( L n : n < ω ). (For us, identical lines are considered parallel.) n<ω C n = R 2 such that | L ∩ C n | ≤ 1 Davies constructed a partition � for all n and all lines L || L n . (Davies remarked that an argument of Sierpi´ nski implicitly shows that, given a covering of R 2 by countably many curves, there is a covering of R 2 by countably many pairwise isometric curves.) 2

  4. To a set theorist, the tastiest ingredient of Davies’ proof is his following implicit lemma. Lemma (Davies’ Lemma) . Let L be a countable first order lan- guage. Let A be an uncountable L -structure. Then there is a transfinite sequence M = ( M α ) α<η such that • every M α is a countable substructure of A , • � ran( M ) = A , and • M has the Davies property : for all α ≤ η , M <α = � β<α M β is a finite union of substructures of A . 3

  5. Davies’ partition of the plane applies his lemma to a partial Skolem- ization of ( P , L , ∈ ; L n : n < ω ) where P is the set R 2 of points in the plane and L is the set of lines in the plane. We will simply let A be a complete Skolemization of ( P , L , ∈ ; L n : n < ω ). Therefore, all substructures are elementary substructures. Let M = ( M α ) α<η be as in Davies’ Lemma. Suppose that α < η and we have constructed a partition � n<ω C n = P ∩ M <α such that | L ∩ C n | ≤ 1 for all n and all lines L || L n . n<ω C ′′′ It suffices to show that we can extend C to a partition � n = P ∩ M <α +1 such that | L ∩ C ′′′ n | ≤ 1 for all n and all lines L || L n . 4

  6. Let ν ≤ ω and let p = ( p k ) k<ν biject from ν to P ∩ M α \ M <α . n<ω C ′ Suppose that k < ν and we have extended C to a partition � n = P ∩ M <α ∪ { p j : j < k } such that | L ∩ C ′ n | ≤ 1 for all n and all lines L || L n . It suffices to show that that we can extend C ′ to a partition � n<ω C ′′ n = P ∩ M <α ∪ { p j : j < k + 1 } such that | L ∩ C ′′ n | ≤ 1 for all n and all lines L || L n . Let d < ω and N = ( N i ) i<d be such that M <α = � ran( N ) and each N i is a substructure of A . 5

  7. For each n < ω , let K n be the line through p k that is parallel to L n . It suffices to show that there exists n < ω such that K n is disjoint from M <α ∪ { p j : j < k } . For each j < k , there is at most one n < ω such that p j ∈ K n . For each i < d , there is at most one n < ω such that K n intersects P ∩ N i . Why? If m < n < ω , x ∈ K m ∩ N i , and y ∈ K n ∩ N i , then K m , K n ∈ N i ; then p k ∈ N i because K m ∩ K n = { p k } . But p �∈ N i . Thus, K n is disjoint from M <α ∪ { p j : j < k } for almost all n . � 6

  8. Davies’ Lemma apparently was not used in print again until 2002 by Jackson and Mauldin, and then by Milovich starting in 2008. Jackson and Mauldin constructed (in ZFC) a Steinhaus set, that is, a subset of R 2 that intersects every isometric copy of Z 2 at exactly one point. Without Davies’ Lemma, Jackson and Mauldin’s proof would have needed CH. We do not know if higher-dimensional analogs of Steinhaus sets exist. 7

  9. References R. O. Davies, Covering the plane with denumerably many curves , J. London Math. Soc. 38 (1963), 433–438. S. Jackson and R. D. Mauldin, On a lattice problem of H. Steinhaus , J. Amer. Math. Soc. 15 (2002), no. 4, 817–856. D. Milovich, Noetherian types of homogeneous compacta and dyadic compacta , Topology Appl. 156 (2008), 443–464. D. Milovich, The ( λ, κ ) -Freese-Nation property for Boolean algebras and compacta , Order 29 (2012), 361–379. D. Milovich, On the strong Freese-Nation property (2014), arXiv:1412.7443. 8

  10. How did Davies prove his lemma? Recall: Lemma (Davies’ Lemma) . Let L be a countable first order lan- guage. Let A be an uncountable L -structure. Then there is a transfinite sequence M = ( M α ) α<η such that • every M α is a countable substructures of A , • � ran( M ) = A , and • M has the Davies property : for all α ≤ η , M <α = � β<α M β is a finite union of substructures of A . 9

  11. Proof: The Davies tree. Recursively construct as follows a sequence ( B t : t ∈ T ) with T a subtree of O rd <ω . • B () = A . • If B t is countable, declare t to be a leaf of T . • If | B t | = κ > ℵ 0 , declare t ⌢ ( α ) ∈ T for all α < κ and choose an increasing sequence ( B t ⌢ ( α ) ) α<κ of substructures of B t with union B t such that | B t ⌢ ( α ) | < | B t | for all α . T is well-founded. Therefore, the set L of leaves of T is well ordered by its lexicographic order < lex . Moreover, � t ∈ L B t = A . Finally, if t ∈ L , then � s< lex t B s = � � α<t i B ( t ↾ i ) ⌢ ( α ) . i< dom( t ) 10

  12. Note that if | A | = ℵ n < ℵ ω , then the Davies tree has height n + 1. Therefore: Lemma. Let L be a countable first order language. Let A be an uncountable L -structure of size ℵ n < ℵ ω . Then there is a transfinite sequence M = ( M α ) α<η such that • every M α is a countable substructure of A , • � ran( M ) = A , and • for all α ≤ η , M <α is a union at most n substructures of A . 11

  13. For each cardinal κ , let H ( κ ) denote the set of all sets x with tran- � n x of cardinality less than κ . sitive closure � n<ω For each regular uncountable cardinal θ , ( H ( θ ) , ∈ ) is a model of ZFC except possibly for the power set axiom. We will always implicitly choose θ large enough to include all the sets and power sets we need for the problem at hand. The notation N ≺ H ( θ ) means that N is an elementary {∈} -substructure of H ( θ ). 12

  14. A long ω 1 -approximation sequence is a transfinite sequence M = ( M α ) α<η of countable elementary substructures of ( H ( θ ) , ∈ ) that is retrospective : for each α < η , the sequence ( M β ) β<α is an element of M α . Warning: If α is uncountable, then ( M β ) β<α , { M β : β < α } , and M <α = � β<α M β are not subsets of M α . 13

  15. If M is a long ω 1 -approximation sequence, A ∈ M 0 , and 0 < α < dom( M ), then M 0 and α are definable from ( M β ) β<α , and hence elements of M α . Recall that if X ∈ N ≺ H ( θ ) and | X | ≤ ℵ 0 , then X ⊂ N . Therefore, M 0 ⊂ M α for all α ∈ dom( M ). Also, M β ⊂ M α for all β ≤ α ∈ ω 1 ∩ dom( M ). More generally, for all α, β ∈ dom( M ), we have M β � M α ⇔ M β ∈ M α ⇔ β ∈ α ∩ M α . 14

  16. Recall that if A is a first order structure for a countable language L and A ∈ N ≺ H ( θ ), then A ∩ N ≺ L A . Therefore, assuming A ∈ M 0 , we have A ∩ M α ≺ L A for all α ∈ dom( M ). Moreover, if every M <α is a finite union of elementary substructures of H ( θ ) (and we will show that it is), then every A ∩ M <α is a finite union of L -elementary substructures of A . Choose a surjection f : | A | → A in M 0 . Assuming | A | ≤ dom( M ), we have f ( α ) ∈ M α for all α < | A | . Therefore, � α< | A | ( A ∩ M α ) = A . 15

  17. Long ω 1 -approximation sequences are canonical sequences of count- able structures that are sufficiently rich to encode Davies trees of which they are leaves. A Davies tree is built top-down, starting from a large structure. Long ω 1 -approximation sequences are more flexibly built up from count- able structures, which simplifies the construction of large structures “from scratch.” Long ω 1 -approximation sequences provide a uniformly definable ver- sion of the Davies property and additional coherence properties. 16

  18. The cardinal normal form of an ordinal α is the polynomial ω β 0 · γ 0 + ω β 1 · γ 1 + · · · + ω β m − 1 · γ m − 1 + γ m that equals α and satisfies • β 0 > · · · > β m − 1 ≥ 1, • 1 ≤ γ i < ω + β i for all i < m , and • γ m < ω 1 . An example cardinal normal form: ω ω ω 7 � � + ω 1 · ω 1 + ( ω ω + ω · 2 + 3) 3 ω ω +1 · 4 + ω ω + ω 7 · + ω 6 · ω 7 17

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend