the time slice axiom in perturbative qft on globally
play

The time slice axiom in perturbative QFT on globally hyperbolic - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

The time slice axiom in perturbative QFT on globally hyperbolic spacetimes Bruno Chilian June 7 2008 Overview Introduction: The time slice axiom in AQFT Outline of the proof First step: Wick-Polynomials Second step: Perturbation Theory


  1. The time slice axiom in perturbative QFT on globally hyperbolic spacetimes Bruno Chilian June 7 2008

  2. Overview Introduction: The time slice axiom in AQFT Outline of the proof First step: Wick-Polynomials Second step: Perturbation Theory

  3. Motivation: Predictability in Physics ◮ Requirement on physical theory: Future should be predictable from present ◮ In classical physics: Well-posed initial value problem for field equation ◮ In QFT: Initial value problem not well-posed, status of field equation unclear

  4. How is predictability implemented in AQFT?

  5. How is predictability implemented in AQFT? M A ( M ) ⊂ A ( M )

  6. How is predictability implemented in AQFT? M M ′ A ( M ) ⊃ A ( M ′ )

  7. How is predictability implemented in AQFT? M M ′ A ( M ) ⊂ A ( M ) Cauchy surface

  8. How is predictability implemented in AQFT? The time slice axiom M M ′ A ( M ) ⊂ A ( M ′ ) Cauchy surface

  9. Outline of the proof is organized as follows: First step: Wick-Polynomials 1. Review of Wick polynomial algebra 2. Time slice axiom for Wick polynomials Second step: Perturbation Theory 3. Review of perturbation theory 4. Time slice axiom for interacting theories

  10. The algebra of the free field ◮ Free scalar field ϕ satisfies ( ✷ + m 2 − ξ R ) f � � = 0 and [ ϕ ( f ) , ϕ ( g )] = � f , ∆ g � . ϕ ◮ Algebra of the free field consists of functionals N � � F ( ϕ ) = d x 1 · · · d x n ϕ ( x 1 ) · · · ϕ ( x n ) f n ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) n = 0 ◮ Initial value problem for Klein-Gordon equation is well posed on globally hyperbolic spacetimes ⇒ time slice axiom holds for the free theory.

  11. The algebra of Wick polynomials ◮ To treat interactions, nonlinear functionals in the field must be used. ◮ Smear normally ordered products with test-distributions: � φ ⊗ n ( f ) = d x 1 · · · d x n : ϕ ( x 1 ) · · · ϕ ( x n ) : f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) ◮ To get a well-defined algebra, test-distributions f must satisfy condition on their wavefront sets: WF ( f ) ∩ V n − ∪ V n + = ∅

  12. Time slice axiom in terms of smearing distributions Let T n ( M ) be the space of compactly supported distributions f on M n with WF ( f ) ∩ V n − ∪ V n + = ∅ . Proposition Let f ∈ T n ( M ) and let N be a neighborhood of a Cauchy surface in the past of supp f. Then there exists a g ∈ T n ( M ) s.th. ◮ g = f + ( ✷ + m 2 − ξ R ) h, where h ∈ T n ( M ) and ◮ supp g ⊂ N .

  13. Time slice axiom in terms of smearing distributions Let T n ( M ) be the space of compactly supported distributions f on M n with WF ( f ) ∩ V n − ∪ V n + = ∅ . Proposition Let f ∈ T n ( M ) and let N be a neighborhood of a Cauchy surface in the past of supp f. Then there exists a g ∈ T n ( M ) s.th. ◮ g = f + ( ✷ + m 2 − ξ R ) h, where h ∈ T n ( M ) and ◮ supp g ⊂ N . Proposition is equivalent to time slice axiom because Wick polynomials have the form � φ ⊗ n ( f ) = d x 1 · · · d x n : ϕ ( x 1 ) · · · ϕ ( x n ) : f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) and : ϕ ( x 1 ) · · · ϕ ( x n ) : satisfies the Klein-Gordon equation.

  14. Main idea for proof: Cauchy-Evolution of distributions Let f be a distribution with compact support. For two Cauchy surfaces in the past of supp f , let χ be a smooth function which is zero in the past and one in the future. supp f χ = 1 Now define another distribution by g = f − ( ✷ + m 2 − ξ R ) χ ∆ adv f . supp g It has compact support between the Cauchy χ = 0 surfaces.

  15. Adaption of this simple argument Generalize to n variables Use suitable partition of unity to check support property Check wavefront property Use H¨ ormanders theorem on the propagation of singularities

  16. The time slice axiom in perturbation theory ◮ Perturbation theory expresses interacting fields by free fields. ◮ Therefore: A g ( M ) ⊂ A 0 ( M ) . ◮ Using the time slice axiom for the free fields: A g ( M ) ⊂ A 0 ( N ) for a neighborhood N of some Cauchy surface. ◮ If one could express free fields in N by interacting fields in N , one would have A g ( M ) ⊂ A 0 ( N ) ⊂ A g ( N ) which is the time slice axiom for interacting fields. ◮ We need to show that A 0 ( N ) ⊂ A g ( N ) .

  17. Causal perturbation theory ◮ Interacting fields: Constructed from local S-matrices: S g ( f ) = S ( g ) − 1 S ( f + g ) ◮ S-matrices: Power series of Wick polynomials causal factorization property supp f S ( f + g + h ) = S ( f + g ) S ( g ) − 1 S ( g + h ) if supp f is in the future and supp h supp g in the past of some Cauchy surface. supp h

  18. Starting idea for the proof of A 0 ( N ) ⊂ A g ( N ) ◮ Elements S g ( f ) also possess causal factorization property: S g ( f 1 + f 2 + f 3 ) = S g ( f 1 + f 2 ) S g ( f 2 ) − 1 S g ( f 2 + f 3 ) if supp f 1 is in the future and supp f 3 in the past of some Cauchy surface. ◮ Multiply interacting fields in a clever way to cancel out interactions. ◮ Obtain some free field. ◮ Check if every free field can be obtained in this way. ◮ Then: A 0 ( N ) ⊂ A g ( N ) .

  19. Noncompact interaction regions If supp g is past compact, define the interacting field S g ( f ) def = S b ( f ) , where b must coincide with g in the past of some compact region containing supp f . This definition does not supp g depend on the choice of b. Proof uses causal supp b factorization property. supp f

  20. Prove: Definition of S g ( f ) is independent of chosen b . Let ˜ b also coincide with g in the past of the compact region containing supp f . Set c = ˜ b − b . Then supp g supp ˜ b supp b supp f b ( f ) = S (˜ b ) − 1 S (˜ b + f ) = S ( c + b ) − 1 S ( c + b + f ) S ˜ = S ( c + b ) − 1 S ( c + b ) S ( b ) − 1 S ( f + b ) = S b ( f ) .

  21. Prove: Definition of S g ( f ) is independent of chosen b . Let ˜ b also coincide with g in the past of the compact region containing supp f . Set c = ˜ b − b . Then supp g supp c supp f b ( f ) = S (˜ b ) − 1 S (˜ b + f ) = S ( c + b ) − 1 S ( c + b + f ) S ˜ = S ( c + b ) − 1 S ( c + b ) S ( b ) − 1 S ( f + b ) = S b ( f ) .

  22. Compensating interactions ◮ Consider the expression S g ( − b ′ ) − 1 S g ( − b ′ + f ) , where b ′ coincides with g in a neighborhood of supp f . ◮ Using causal factorization, it can be shown that S g ( − b ′ ) − 1 S g ( − b ′ + f ) = S ( b − ) − 1 S ( f ) S ( b − ) , where supp b − is in the past and supp f in the future of some Cauchy surface. 1st observation 2nd observation S ( b − ) − 1 S ( f ) S ( b − ) ∈ A g ( N ) S ( b − ) − 1 S ( f ) S ( b − ) ∈ A 0 ( M )

  23. ◮ The map S ( f ) �→ S g ( − b ′ ) − 1 S g ( − b ′ + f ) = S ( b − ) − 1 S ( f ) S ( b − ) defines an endomorphism of A 0 ( M ) , whose image is contained in A g ( N ) . ◮ For each relatively compact region, it is just conjugation by a certain invertible element of A 0 ( M ) . ◮ The last step is to show that this endomorphism is invertible, i.e. S ( b − ) S ( h ) S ( b − ) − 1 does not depend on the chosen b − . ◮ Place additional restriction on the choice of b − .

  24. Summary ◮ The time slice axiom holds in perturbative AQFT. ◮ One only needs the causal factorization property... ◮ and the time slice axiom for Wick polynomials.

  25. supp b supp b ′ N ′ Σ K N Σ 1 S Σ 2 Locally compensating the interaction g with b ′ : S g ( − b ′ ) − 1 S g ( − b ′ + f ) = S ( b − ) − 1 S ( f ) S ( b − )

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend