the reasons behind some classical constructions in
play

The reasons behind some classical constructions in analysis V. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

The reasons behind some classical constructions in analysis V. Milman Tel-Aviv University In the memory of a great scientist and a good friend, Aleksander (Olek) Peczyski June 2014, Bdlewo, Poland 2/25 Instead of an Introduction: some


  1. The reasons behind some classical constructions in analysis V. Milman Tel-Aviv University In the memory of a great scientist and a good friend, Aleksander (Olek) Pełczyński June 2014, Będlewo, Poland 2/25

  2. Instead of an Introduction: some geometric results What should we call “duality”? Consider the class Cvx ( R n ) of all lower-semi-continuous convex functions f : R n → R ∪ { + ∞ } . The Legendre transform is the map � � x , y � − ϕ ( y ) L ϕ ( x ) = sup � . y ∈ R n Of course, there are many “Legendre transforms”: We may select 0 of the space, a scalar product and a shift for a function. Theorem (Artstein–Milman) 1. Assume T : Cvx ( R n ) → Cvx ( R n ) satisfies: (a) T · T ϕ = ϕ (for any ϕ ∈ Cvx ( R n )) ; (b) ϕ ≤ ψ implies T ϕ ≥ T ψ . Then T is a Legendre transform. It means that Cvx ( R n ) has a unique duality structure! 3/25

  3. Let us embed K ( R n ) = { K ⊆ R n | closed convex } into Cvx ( R n ) by “convex characteristic” functions: � 0 x ∈ K , → 1 ∞ K − K = + ∞ x �∈ K . For K ∈ K 0 ( R n ) = { K ∈ K ( R n ) | 0 ∈ K } , define its gauge function (or Minkowski functional M ( 1 ∞ K ) ) – 1-homogeneous convex function � x � K , “generalized” norm, s.t. K = { x ∈ R n | � x � K ≤ 1 } . Let H 0 = {� x � K | K ∈ K 0 ( R n ) } . Define the Minkowski map M ( 1 ∞ K ) = � x � K ∈ H 0 and the support map S ( 1 ∞ K ) = sup {� x , y � | y ∈ K } ∈ H 0 . Obviously, M : K 0 ( R n ) → H 0 is an order preserving map (1-1 and onto) and S : K 0 ( R n ) → H 0 is an order reversing map. 4/25

  4. We continue the theorem: Theorem (Artstein–Milman) 2. There is a unique order reversing extension of the support map S to Cvx ( R n ) which is the Legendre transform. And what is the polarity map on K 0 ( R n ) K → K ◦ = { x ∈ R n | � x , y � ≤ 1 ∀ y ∈ K } ? K ◦ is defined if 0 ∈ K . So, let Cvx 0 ( R n ) = { f ∈ Cvx ( R n ) | f ( x ) ≥ 0 and f ( 0 ) = 0 } be the class of geometric convex functions. 3. There is a unique order reversing extension of the polarity map { 1 ∞ K → 1 ∞ K ◦ | K ∈ K 0 } to Cvx 0 ( R n ) \ 0 defined by A f = sup � x , y � − 1 , f ( y ) and A ( 0 ) : = 1 ∞ { 0 } . (By extension we mean that A 1 ∞ K = 1 ∞ K ◦ ) 5/25

  5. There are ONLY two dualities on Cvx 0 ( R n ) – L and A : Theorem (Artstein–Milman) Let n ≥ 2 . The maps L and A are (essentially) the only order reversing involutions on Cvx 0 ( R n ) . Precisely: if T : Cvx 0 → Cvx 0 is 1. involution T · T = Id. 2. order reversing: ∀ f , g ∈ Cvx 0 we have f ≤ g ⇒ Tf ≥ Tg , then ∃ C > 0 and B ∈ GL n , symmetric, s.t. either ∀ f ∈ Cvx 0 , Tf = L ( f ( Bx )) or ∀ f ∈ Cvx 0 , Tf = C A ( f ( Bx )) . (when n = 1 there are 8 such different dualities) 6/25

  6. Consider the order preserving map (involution) J = LA = AL which connects two dualities (supporting map – Legendre transform L , and geometric duality A ). J is a very interesting map Cvx 0 → Cvx 0 , order preserving. It is the gauge map: [Fact]Artstein-Milman. J is the only order preserving extension of the Minkowski map M onto Cvx 0 ( R n ) , i.e. J ( 1 ∞ K ) ≡ M ( 1 ∞ K ) = � x � K . So, on the class of convex functions we have the notion of support function, Minkowski functional and polarity! 7/25

  7. Classical constructions in analysis which appear (uniquely) from elementary (simplest) properties Now let us look into the continuation of the previous geometric ideas applied to the problems of Analysis . We start with a characterization of the classical Fourier transform F on R n : F f = � e − 2 π i � x , y � f ( y ) dy . Let S be the Schwartz class of “rapidly” decreasing (infinitely smooth) functions on R n . Theorem (Artstein, Faifman, Milman) Assume we are given a bijective transform F : S → S , s.t. ∀ f , g ∈ S we have F ( f · g ) = F f ∗ F g . Then ∃ diffeomorphism ω : R n → R n s.t. either ∀ f ∈ S, F f = F ( f ◦ ω ) or ∀ f ∈ S , F f = F ( f ◦ ω ) . 8/25

  8. Real linearity and continuity of F is the automatic consequence. Previous versions contained more conditions and were proved jointly with S. Alesker. Joining these results with the previous theorem we may state that if F : S → S s.t. ∀ f , g ∈ S F ( f · g ) = F f ∗ F g , F ( f ∗ g ) = F f · F g , then ∃ linear A ∈ GL n , | det ( A ) | = 1, s.t. either ∀ f ∈ S , F f = F ( f ◦ A ) or ∀ f ∈ S , F f = F ( f ◦ A ) . 9/25

  9. Derivative; Approach through the chain rule What algebraic property characterizes derivative on R ? Let f bounded from above or from � � C 1 f ∈ C 1 ( R ) | b ( R ) = . below (or both) write ( f ◦ g )( x ) : = f ( g ( x )) (composition). We say, T : Dom ( T ) = C 1 ( R ) → Im ( T ) ⊂ C ( R ) is non-degenerate if ∃ x 0 ∈ R , h 0 ∈ C 1 ( R ) , ( Th 0 )( x 0 ) = 0 , (1) ∃ x 2 ∈ R , h 2 ∈ C 1 b ( R ) , ( Th 2 )( x 2 ) < 0 . (2) (a very weak surjectivity type condition). 10/25

  10. Theorem (Artstein, König, Milman) Let T : D om ( T ) : = C 1 ( R ) → Im ( T ) ⊂ C ( R ) be an operation satisfying the chain rule (3) T ( f ◦ g ) = ( Tf ) ◦ g · Tg ; f , g ∈ D ( T ) . Assume that T is non-degenerate in the sense of (1)+(2). (Normalizing conditions) T ( 2 Id ) = 2 (is a constant function), then Tf = f ′ is the only solution. No linearity or any kind of continuity of T is assumed, but is the consequence (under the above conditions) of the chain rule only. 11/25

  11. Without the normalization condition the result is: ∃ strictly monotone continuously differentiable function G ( x ) and p > 0, s.t. p � d ( G ◦ f ) � · sgn ( f ′ ) . � � Tf = � � dG � � ( T : C k → C ) (and not Note: If T ( f ◦ g ) = Tf · Tg degenerate at any x ∈ R ) then Tf = 1 , ∀ f ∈ C k . So, we need ( Tf ) ◦ g · Tg to build a non-degenerate operation. The same answer may be written differently: ∃ H ∈ C ( R ) , H > 0 and p > 0 s.t. Tf = H ( f ( x )) � p sgn ( f ′ ) . � f ′ � � · H ( x ) 12/25

  12. The chain rule (3) has a natural (and unique) domain on which it acts (with the image inside C ( R ) ), and it is C 1 ( R ) . Facts from (A-K-M). Let T : L → C ( R ) satisfy (3) for f , g , f ◦ g ∈ L . If: ◮ L = C ( R ) and ∃ g 0 ∈ C and x 0 ∈ R s.t. ( Tg 0 )( x 0 ) = 0 . Then T | C b ( R ) ≡ 0 . ◮ C ∞ ( R ) ⊂ L ⊂ C 1 ( R ) = ⇒ T maybe extended to C 1 ( R ) ; So the natural Dom ( T ) is C 1 ! 13/25

  13. Rigidity of the chain rule To what extent is the standard chain rule inferred by a much weaker version? Let V : C 1 ( R ) → C ( R ) be non-degenerate, i.e. 1. For any x ∈ R there is f ∈ C 1 ( R ) such that Vf ( x ) � = 0 , and 2. For any x ∈ R there are y ∈ R and f ∈ C 1 ( R ) such that f ( y ) = x and Vf ( y ) � = 0 . 14/25

  14. Theorem (König-Milman) Assume that V , T 1 , T 2 : C 1 ( R ) → C ( R ) are operators such that the equation V ( f ◦ g ) = ( T 1 f ) ◦ g · ( T 2 g ) holds for all f , g ∈ C 1 ( R ) . Assume that V is non-degenerate. There is a solution T of the chain rule equation T ( f ◦ g ) = ( Tf ) ◦ g · Tg , s.t. ( Vf )( x ) = c 1 ( f ( x )) c 2 ( x ) · ( Tf )( x ) ( T 1 f )( x ) = c 1 ( f ( x )) · ( Tf )( x ) ( T 2 f )( x ) = c 2 ( x ) · ( Tf )( x ) , i.e. all three a priori different operators are essentially the same (a strong super rigidity). 15/25

  15. Stability of the Chain Rule T : C 1 ( R ) → C ( R ) is locally non-degenerate if ∀ open interval J ⊂ R , ∀ x ∈ J , ∃ g ∈ C 1 ( R ) , y ∈ R , s.t. g ( y ) = x , Im ( g ) ⊂ J and Tg ( y ) � = 0. Theorem (König-Milman) Fix T : C 1 ( R ) → C ( R ) and B : R 3 → R such that ∀ f , g ∈ C 1 and ∀ x ∈ R T ( f ◦ g )( x ) = Tf ◦ g ( x ) · Tg ( x ) + B ( x , f ◦ g ( x ) , g ( x )) . Assume that T is locally non-degenerate and Tf depends non-trivially on f ′ . Then B = 0 (and T satisfies the chain rule). 16/25

  16. Even more rigidity Consider the “chain rule inequality” ( ∗ ) T ( f ◦ g ) ≤ ( Tf ) ◦ g · Tg for T : C 1 ( R ) → C ( R ) , Dom ( T ) = C 1 ( R ) . Assume that T satisfies the following: ◮ non-degeneration: ∀ open interval I ⊂ R , ∀ x ∈ I , ∃ g ∈ C 1 ( R ) s.t. g ( x ) = x , Im ( g ) ⊂ I and Tg ( x ) > 1. ◮ T is pointwise continuous: ∀ f , f n ∈ C 1 ( R ) s.t f n → f , n → f ′ uniformly on compact subsets we have f ′ ( Tf n ) ( x ) → ( Tf ) ( x ) pointwise for all x ∈ R . 17/25

  17. Theorem (König-Milman) For T as above assume also ∃ x ∈ R s.t T ( − Id )( x ) < 0 . Then ∃ H ∈ C ( R ) , H > 0 , ∃ p > 0 and A ≥ 1 s.t for f ′ ≥ 0 � H | f ′ | p H ◦ f Tf = − A H ◦ f H | f ′ | p for f ′ < 0 . Note: ◮ For A = 1, T satisfies the chain rule equation: we have equality in ( ∗ ) . ◮ For both f and g non-decreasing we automatically have equality in ( ∗ ) . ◮ Actually, the same is true if for some C > 0 T ( f ◦ g ) ≤ C · ( Tf ) ◦ g · Tg and even much more generally (the answer is slightly modified). 18/25

  18. The following classically sound functional statement is used: We say that K : R → R is submultiplicative if K ( αβ ) ≤ K ( α ) K ( β ) , ∀ α , β ∈ R . Theorem (König-Milman) Let K be submultiplicative, measurable and continuous at 0 and at 1 . Assume K ( − 1 ) < 0 < K ( 1 ) . Then ∃ p > 0 s.t. � α p for α ≥ 0 K ( α ) = − A | α | p for α < 0 (and K ( − 1 ) = − A ≤ − 1 ). [every assumption in the theorem is needed] As a corollary, K must be multiplicative on R + . 19/25

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend