r is a complete ordered set density of the rationals
play

( R , < ) is a complete ordered set. Density of the rationals. - PDF document

1 5/6/2010 Dedekind Cuts ( ) A Dedekind cut (D-cut) (aka lower-D-cut ) is a nonempty set A Q so that (i) ( , a ) := { q Q : q < a } A


  1. � 1 ילרגטנאוילמסטיניפנא�ובשח �הרזח 5/6/2010 Dedekind Cuts ( �דניקדדיכתח ) A Dedekind cut (D-cut) (aka lower-D-cut ) is a nonempty set A � Q so that (i) ( −∞ , a ) := { q ∈ Q : q < a } ⊂ A ∀ a ∈ A ; (ii) ∄ maximal element in A (i.e. ∄ LUB A ∈ A ). Let R := { lower-D-cuts } and order R by inclusion (i.e. for A , B ∈ R , A < B if A � B ), then � ( R , < ) is a complete ordered set. � Density of the rationals. Suppose that A , B ∈ R and that A < B , then ∃ q ∈ Q so that A < ( −∞ , q ) < B .

  2. Decimal representation ( �תינורשעהגצה ) of lower-D-cuts Decimal representation is a map π : R → Z × D N where D := { digits } = { 0 , 1 , 2 , 3 , 4 , 5 , 6 , 7 , 8 , 9 } defined by π ( A ) = ( N ; d 1 , d 2 , . . . ) where n � d k max { a ∈ A : 10 n a ∈ Z } = N + ∀ n ≥ 1 . 10 k k =1 π : R → Z × { a ∈ D N : # { k ≥ 1 : a k ≥ 1 } = ∞} is a set • correspondence (bijection). � Cantor’s Theorem A non trivial interval in R is uncountably infinite. Addition in R Let A , B ∈ R be cuts. Define A + B := { a + b : a ∈ A , b ∈ B } , then , • A + B is a cut; neutral element for addition: 0 ∗ := ( −∞ , 0); • negative of D-cut A : − A := {− b : b ∈ A ↑ } which is is also a • cut, where; � A = ( −∞ , a ) , a ∈ Q , ( a , ∞ ) A ↑ := Q \ A A irrational ; A + ( − A ) = 0 ∗ . •

  3. Positivity and order in R A D-cut is positive if A > 0 ∗ ( i.e. A � ( −∞ , 0) or 0 ∈ A ). Let R pos := { positive D-cuts } , then , ∀ A ∈ R , either A = 0 ∗ , A ∈ R pos or − A ∈ R pos ; • if A , B ∈ R pos , then A + B ∈ R pos ; • let A , B ∈ R , then A < B iff B + ( − A ) ∈ R pos . • Absolute value The absolute value of the D-cut A is | A | ∈ R pos defined by  0 A = 0 ,   A ∈ R pos , | A | = A   − A ∈ R pos . − A In particular (!) | ( −∞ , a ) | = ( −∞ , | a | ).

  4. Multiplication We first define multiplication on R pos . Define the positive part of the positive D-cut A by A + := A ∩ (0 , ∞ ), then A = ( −∞ , 0] ∪ A + . For A , B ∈ R pos , define AB := ( −∞ , 0] ∪ { xy : x ∈ A + , y ∈ B + } and for A , B ∈ R define  0 A = 0 or B = 0 ,   A , B ∈ R pos or − A , − B ∈ R pos A · B := | A || B |   −| A || B | else . � Dedekind’s theorem ( R , + , · ) is a complete ordered field with respect to R pos . Archimedean ordered fields The ordered field ( F , + , · ) is called archimedean if ∀ x > 0 , ∃ n ∈ N such that nx := x + · · · + x > 1; � �� � n times there are no ‘‘ infinitesimals ") . (i.e. � A complete, ordered field ( F , + , · ) is archimedean.

  5. Non-archimedean ordered field Let ( F , + , · ) be the field of rational functions } on R equipped with regular addition and multiplication of functions. Define the “ positive elements ” of F by F pos := { R = P Q ∈ F : ∃ t > 0 so that Q ( x ) � = 0 & R ( x ) > 0 ∀ x ∈ (0 , t ) } . � F pos is an ordering for ( F , + , · ); � F is not archimedean with respect to F pos . The complex numbers ( ��יבכורמה�ירפסמה ) Define the complex numbers by √ √ C = R ( − 1 y : x , y ∈ R } , − 1) := { x + with addition and multiplication to satisfy the normal laws of arithmetic. � ( C , + · ) is a field; � there is no ordering for ( C , + · )

  6. General existence of real roots n √ a ∈ R pos such that( n √ a ) n = a . ∀ a ∈ R pos n ∈ N , ∃ ! Proof n √ a := LUB A where A := { x ∈ R pos : x n < a } . Limit of a sequence Suppose b n ∈ R ( n ∈ N ). We say that b n tends to ( ��ל�אוש ) B ∈ R as n → ∞ written b n → B ∈ R as n → ∞ ; or b n − → n →∞ B if ∀ ǫ > 0 , ∃ n ǫ such that | b n − B | < ǫ ∀ n ≥ n ǫ . Example If a n ≤ a n +1 and { a n : n ≥ 1 } is bounded, then a n − n →∞ LUB { a n : n ≥ 1 } . →

  7. Conditions for convergence ¶ Comparison Suppose that a n ≥ 0 , a n → 0 as n → ∞ and that M > 0 , b n ∈ R , | b n | ≤ Ma n ∀ n ≥ 1, then b n → 0 as n → ∞ . ¶ Absolute value proposition a n → L as n → ∞ iff | a n − L | → 0 as n → ∞ and in this case | a n | → | L | . ¶ Sandwich principle Suppose that a n ≤ x n ≤ b n ∀ n ≥ 1 and that a n → L , b n → L as n → ∞ , then x n − n →∞ L . → Divergence to ∞ We say that the sequence ( x 1 , x 2 , . . . ) diverges ( �תרדבתמ ) to ∞ (as n → ∞ ) if for each M > 0 , ∃ N M such that x n > M ∀ n ≥ N M (and write this x n → ∞ ). � Let ( x 1 , x 2 , . . . ) be an increasing sequence, then either ( x 1 , x 2 , . . . ) is convergent, or x n → ∞ . Examples n n � � 1 1 k − n →∞ ∞ , → 2 k − n →∞ 2 . → k =1 k =0

  8. Arithmetic of limits Suppose that a n → a and b n → b as n → ∞ , then a n + b n → a + b as n → ∞ ; (1) a n b n → ab as n → ∞ ; (2) and in case b � = 0: a n → a b as n → ∞ ; (3) b n Accumulation points Let E ⊂ R . A point x ∈ R is called an accumulation point of E if ∀ ǫ > 0 , # E ∩ ( x − ǫ, x + ǫ ) = ∞ . � The following are equivalent for E ⊂ R and x ∈ R : (i) x is an accumulation point of E ; (ii) ∀ ǫ > 0 , ∃ y ∈ E ∩ ( x − ǫ, x + ǫ ) , y � = x ; (iii) ∃ ( z 1 , z 2 , . . . ) ∈ E N such that z k � = z ℓ ∀ k � = ℓ & z n − n →∞ x . → � Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem (accumulation points) If E is an infinite, bounded set, then E ′ � = ∅ . The proof of the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem uses: � Cantor’s Lemma (or the Chinese box theorem) A nested sequence of non-empty, closed intervals in R has a non-empty intersection.

  9. Proof of the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem Suppose that E ⊂ I a closed, finite interval. For I = [ a , b ], write I − := [ a , a + b 2 ] and I + := [ a + b 2 , b ]; I = I − ∪ I + whence ∃ I 1 = I ± with # E ∩ I 1 = ∞ ; Similarly ∃ I 2 = I ± 1 with # E ∩ I 2 = ∞ ; continuing, get closed intervals I n ⊃ I n +1 so that I n +1 = I ± • n and # E ∩ I n = ∞ ∀ n ≥ 1. n →∞ 0, by Cantor’s lemma, � ∞ Since | I n | = | I | 2 n − → n =1 I n = { Z } for some Z ∈ R . Z ∈ E ′ . � � Limit points Let E ⊂ R . A point x ∈ R is called a limit point ( �לובגתדוקנ ) of E if ∃ y n ∈ E ( n ≥ 1) such that y n → x . ( �רוגס ) of E : Closure { limit points of E } =: E . � E = E ∪ E ′ A set is closed if E = E . � A closed subset of R which is bounded above (below) has a maximal (minimal) element.

  10. Subsequences An integer subsequence ( ��ימלשלשהרדיס�תת ) is an infinite subset K ⊂ N , K = { n 1 , n 2 , . . . } arranged in increasing order n 1 < n 2 < · · · → ∞ . A subsequence of the sequence { a 1 , a 2 , . . . } is a sequence of form { a n 1 , a n 2 , . . . } where n k → ∞ is an integer subsequence. � Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem (convergent subsequences) Every bounded sequence has a convergent subsequence. Partial limits of a sequence The partial limit set ( ��ייקלחהתולובגתצובק ) PL ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) of the bounded sequence ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) is PL ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) := { a ∈ R : ∃ n k → ∞ , a n k − k →∞ a } � = ∅ . → � For ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) a bounded sequence, # PL ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) = 1 ⇐ ⇒ ∃ lim n →∞ a n . � Let ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) be a bounded sequence, then PL ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) is closed and bounded.

  11. Upper and lower limits The upper limit ( ��וילעלובג ) of the bounded sequence ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) is n →∞ a n := max PL ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) lim and the lower limit ( ��ותחתלובג ) of the sequence ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) is lim a n := min PL ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) . n →∞ � ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) converges iff lim n →∞ a n = lim n →∞ a n . � Let a = ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) be a bounded sequence, then (i) ∀ α < lim n →∞ a n , ∃ N α such that a n > α ∀ n > N α ; (ii) ∀ β > lim n →∞ a n , K ≥ 1 , ∃ N > K such that a N < β ; (i) ∀ ω > lim n →∞ a n , ∃ N ω such that a n < ω ∀ n > N ω ; (ii) ∀ ξ < lim n →∞ a n , K ≥ 1 , ∃ N > K such that a N > ξ ; Cauchy sequences Or how to prove a sequence converges without knowing the limit. A sequence ( a 1 , a 2 , . . . ) is called a Cauchy sequence if ∀ ǫ > 0 , ∃ N ǫ ≥ 1 such that | a n − a n ′ | < ǫ ∀ n , n ′ ≥ N ǫ . � Cauchy’s Theorem A sequence converges ⇐ ⇒ it is a Cauchy sequence.

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend