polynomial berwald moor
play

Polynomial (Berwald-Moor) Computational . . . Finsler Metrics - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . Towards a General . . . A New Model: . . . Polynomial (Berwald-Moor) Computational . . . Finsler Metrics Euclidean Space: Proof From Euclidean to . . . and Related Partial Orders From Minkowski to


  1. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . Towards a General . . . A New Model: . . . Polynomial (Berwald-Moor) Computational . . . Finsler Metrics Euclidean Space: Proof From Euclidean to . . . and Related Partial Orders From Minkowski to . . . Discussion Beyond Space-Time: Towards Analyzing . . . Towards Applications to Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ Logic and Decision Making ◭ ◮ Olga Kosheleva and Vladik Kreinovich Page 1 of 25 University of Texas at El Paso Go Back El Paso, Texas 79968, USA emails olgak@utep.edu, vladik@utep.edu Full Screen Close Quit

  2. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 1. Objective of Science and Engineering Towards a General . . . • One of the main objectives: help people select decisions A New Model: . . . which are the most beneficial to them. Computational . . . Euclidean Space: Proof • To make these decisions, From Euclidean to . . . – we must know people’s preferences , From Minkowski to . . . – we must have the information about different events Discussion – possible consequences of different decisions, and Towards Analyzing . . . – we must also have information about the degree of Title Page certainty ◭◭ ◮◮ ∗ (since information is never absolutely accurate ◭ ◮ and precise). Page 2 of 25 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  3. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 2. Partial Orders Naturally Appear in Many Applica- tion Areas Towards a General . . . A New Model: . . . • Reminder: we need info re preferences , events , and de- Computational . . . grees of certainty . Euclidean Space: Proof From Euclidean to . . . • All these types of information naturally lead to partial orders: From Minkowski to . . . Discussion – For preferences , a < b means that b is preferable Towards Analyzing . . . to a . Title Page ∗ This relation is used in decision theory . ◭◭ ◮◮ – For events , a < b means that a can influence b . ◭ ◮ ∗ This causality relation is used in space-time physics . Page 3 of 25 – For degrees of certainty , a < b means that a is less certain than b . Go Back ∗ This relation is used in logics describing uncer- Full Screen tainty – such as fuzzy logic . Close Quit

  4. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 3. Numerical Characteristics Related to Partial Or- ders Towards a General . . . A New Model: . . . + An order is a natural way of describing a relation. Computational . . . Euclidean Space: Proof − Orders are difficult to process, since most data process- From Euclidean to . . . ing algorithms process numbers . From Minkowski to . . . • Natural idea: use numerical characteristics to describe Discussion the orders. Towards Analyzing . . . • Fact: this idea is used in all three application areas: Title Page – in decision making, utility describes preferences: ◭◭ ◮◮ a < b if and only if u ( a ) < u ( b ); ◭ ◮ – in space-time physics, metric (and time coordinates) Page 4 of 25 describes causality relation; Go Back – in logic and soft constraints, numbers from the in- Full Screen terval [0 , 1] are used to describe degrees of certainty. Close Quit

  5. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 4. Need to Combine Numerical Characteristics: Emergence of Polynomial Aggregation Formulas Towards a General . . . A New Model: . . . • In decision making, we need to combine utilities u 1 , Computational . . . . . . , u n of different participants. Euclidean Space: Proof – Nobelist Josh Nash showed that reasonable condi- From Euclidean to . . . tions lead to u = u 1 · . . . · u n . From Minkowski to . . . Discussion • In space-time geometry, we need to combine coordi- Towards Analyzing . . . nates x i into a metric. Title Page – Reasonable conditions lead to polynomial metrics ◭◭ ◮◮ s 2 = c 2 · ( x 0 − x ′ 0 ) 2 − ( x 1 − x ′ 1 ) 2 − ( x 2 − x ′ 2 ) 2 − ( x 3 − x ′ 3 ) 2 ; ◭ ◮ s 4 = ( x 1 − x ′ 1 ) · ( x 2 − x ′ 2 ) · ( x 3 − x ′ 3 ) · ( x 4 − x ′ 4 ) . Page 5 of 25 • In fuzzy logic, we must combine degrees of certainty d i Go Back in A i into a degree d for A 1 & A 2 . Full Screen – Reasonable conditions lead to polynomial functions like d = d 1 · d 2 . Close Quit

  6. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 5. Mathematical Observation: Polynomial Formulas Are Tensor-Related Towards a General . . . A New Model: . . . • Fact: in many areas, we have a general polynomial Computational . . . dependence Euclidean Space: Proof f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) = f 0 + From Euclidean to . . . n From Minkowski to . . . � f i · x i + Discussion i =1 Towards Analyzing . . . n n � � Title Page f ij · x i · x j + ◭◭ ◮◮ i =1 j =1 n n n ◭ ◮ � � � f ijk · x i · x j · x k + Page 6 of 25 i =1 j =1 k =1 . . . Go Back • In mathematical terms: to describe this dependence, Full Screen we need a finite set of tensors f 0 , f i , f ij , f ijk , . . . Close Quit

  7. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 6. Towards a General Justification of Polynomial For- mulas Towards a General . . . A New Model: . . . • Fact: similar polynomials appear in different applica- Computational . . . tion areas. Euclidean Space: Proof From Euclidean to . . . • Reasonable conclusion: there must be a common rea- son behind them. From Minkowski to . . . Discussion • What we do: we provide such a general reason. Towards Analyzing . . . Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ Page 7 of 25 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  8. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 7. Class of Functions Towards a General . . . • Objective: find a finite-parametric class F of analytical A New Model: . . . functions f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ). Computational . . . Euclidean Space: Proof • Meaning: f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) approximate the actual com- From Euclidean to . . . plex aggregation function. From Minkowski to . . . • Reasonable requirement: this class F is invariant with Discussion respect to addition and multiplication by a constant. Towards Analyzing . . . • Conclusion: the class F is a (finite-dimensional) linear Title Page space of functions. ◭◭ ◮◮ • Meaning: invariance w.r.t. multiplication by a constant ◭ ◮ corresponds to the choice of a measuring unit. Page 8 of 25 • If we replace the original measuring unit by a one which Go Back is λ times smaller, then all the numerical values · λ : Full Screen f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) is replaced with λ · f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ). Close Quit

  9. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 8. Similar Scale-Invariance for the Inputs x i Towards a General . . . • Similarly: in all three areas, the numerical values x i A New Model: . . . are defined modulo the choice of a measuring unit. Computational . . . – If we replace the original measuring unit by a one Euclidean Space: Proof which is λ times smaller, From Euclidean to . . . From Minkowski to . . . – then all the numerical values get multiplied by this factor λ : Discussion Towards Analyzing . . . x i is replaced with λ · x i . Title Page • Conclusion: it is reasonable to require that the finite- ◭◭ ◮◮ dimensional linear space F be invariant with respect to such re-scalings: ◭ ◮ – if f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) ∈ F , Page 9 of 25 – then for every λ > 0, the function Go Back def f λ ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) = f ( λ · x 1 , . . . , λ · x n ) Full Screen also belongs to the family F . Close Quit

  10. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 9. Definition and the Main Result Towards a General . . . Definition. Let n be an arbitrary integer. We say that A New Model: . . . a finite-dimensional linear space F of analytical functions Computational . . . of n variables is scale-invariant if for every f ∈ F and for Euclidean Space: Proof every λ > 0 , the function From Euclidean to . . . def From Minkowski to . . . f λ ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) = f ( λ · x 1 , . . . , λ · x n ) Discussion also belongs to the family F . Towards Analyzing . . . Title Page Main result. For every scale-invariant finite-dimensional linear space F of analytical functions, every element f ∈ F ◭◭ ◮◮ is a polynomial. ◭ ◮ Page 10 of 25 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  11. Introduction: Main . . . Symmetry of . . . 10. Proof (Part 1) Towards a General . . . • Let F be a scale-invariant finite-dimensional linear space A New Model: . . . F of analytical functions. Computational . . . Euclidean Space: Proof • Let f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) be a function from this family F . From Euclidean to . . . • By definition, an analytical function f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) is an From Minkowski to . . . infinite series consisting of monomials m ( x 1 , . . . , x n ): Discussion m ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) = a i 1 ...i n · x i 1 1 · . . . · x i n n . Towards Analyzing . . . Title Page • For each such term, by its total order , we will under- ◭◭ ◮◮ stand the sum i 1 + . . . + i n . ◭ ◮ – if we multiply each input of this monomial by λ , Page 11 of 25 – then the value of the monomial is multiplied by λ k : Go Back m ( λ · x 1 , . . . λ · x n ) = a i 1 ...i n · ( λ · x 1 ) i 1 · . . . · ( λ · x n ) i n = Full Screen n = λ k · m ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) . λ i 1 + ... + i n · a i 1 ...i n · x i 1 1 · . . . · x i n Close Quit

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend