polarized partition properties on the second level of the
play

Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of the - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of the Projective Hierarchy. Yurii Khomskii University of Amstedam Joint work with J org Brendle (Kobe University, Japan) RIMS Set Theory Workshop 2009, Kyoto, Japan Polarized Partition


  1. Polarized Partitions Polarized partition properties have been studied by Henle, Llopis, DiPrisco, Todorˇ cevi´ c and Zapletal. Easy observations: 1. In order for ( � n → � m ) to hold even for very simple partitions, � m . n ≫ � 2. Γ ( � m ) . n → � m ) = ⇒ Γ ( � ω → � Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 9/3

  2. Polarized Partitions Polarized partition properties have been studied by Henle, Llopis, DiPrisco, Todorˇ cevi´ c and Zapletal. Easy observations: 1. In order for ( � n → � m ) to hold even for very simple partitions, � m . n ≫ � 2. Γ ( � m ) . n → � m ) = ⇒ Γ ( � ω → � m ′ ) , for all m, m ′ ≥ 2 . ω → � 3. Γ ( � ω → � m ) ⇐ ⇒ Γ ( � Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 9/3

  3. Polarized Partitions Polarized partition properties have been studied by Henle, Llopis, DiPrisco, Todorˇ cevi´ c and Zapletal. Easy observations: 1. In order for ( � n → � m ) to hold even for very simple partitions, � m . n ≫ � 2. Γ ( � m ) . n → � m ) = ⇒ Γ ( � ω → � m ′ ) , for all m, m ′ ≥ 2 . ω → � 3. Γ ( � ω → � m ) ⇐ ⇒ Γ ( � m ) , then for every other � m ′ there is � n ′ such that If Γ ( � n → � Γ ( � n ′ → � m ′ ) Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 9/3

  4. Polarized Partitions Polarized partition properties have been studied by Henle, Llopis, DiPrisco, Todorˇ cevi´ c and Zapletal. Easy observations: 1. In order for ( � n → � m ) to hold even for very simple partitions, � m . n ≫ � 2. Γ ( � m ) . n → � m ) = ⇒ Γ ( � ω → � m ′ ) , for all m, m ′ ≥ 2 . ω → � 3. Γ ( � ω → � m ) ⇐ ⇒ Γ ( � m ) , then for every other � m ′ there is � n ′ such that If Γ ( � n → � Γ ( � n ′ → � m ′ ) Use coding function ϕ ( x ) := �� x (0) , . . . , x ( i 1 ) � , � x ( i 1 + 1) , . . . , x ( i 1 + i 2 ) � , . . . � . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 9/3

  5. Polarized Partitions Polarized partition properties have been studied by Henle, Llopis, DiPrisco, Todorˇ cevi´ c and Zapletal. Easy observations: 1. In order for ( � n → � m ) to hold even for very simple partitions, � m . n ≫ � 2. Γ ( � m ) . n → � m ) = ⇒ Γ ( � ω → � m ′ ) , for all m, m ′ ≥ 2 . ω → � 3. Γ ( � ω → � m ) ⇐ ⇒ Γ ( � m ) , then for every other � m ′ there is � n ′ such that If Γ ( � n → � Γ ( � n ′ → � m ′ ) Use coding function ϕ ( x ) := �� x (0) , . . . , x ( i 1 ) � , � x ( i 1 + 1) , . . . , x ( i 1 + i 2 ) � , . . . � . From now on, use generic notations ( � ω → � m ) and ( � n → � m ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 9/3

  6. Polarized Partitions In [DiPrisco & Todorˇ cevi´ c, 2003]: ( � ω → � m ) and ( � n → � m ) hold for analytic sets. Explicit bounds � n computed from � m (using Ackermann-like function). Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 10/3

  7. Polarized Partitions In [DiPrisco & Todorˇ cevi´ c, 2003]: ( � ω → � m ) and ( � n → � m ) hold for analytic sets. Explicit bounds � n computed from � m (using Ackermann-like function). On the other hand, easy to find counterexample using AC (i.e. well-ordering of ω ω ). Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 10/3

  8. Polarized Partitions In [DiPrisco & Todorˇ cevi´ c, 2003]: ( � ω → � m ) and ( � n → � m ) hold for analytic sets. Explicit bounds � n computed from � m (using Ackermann-like function). On the other hand, easy to find counterexample using AC (i.e. well-ordering of ω ω ). So, what about ∆ 1 2 / Σ 1 m ) and ∆ 1 2 / Σ 1 2 ( � ω → � 2 ( � n → � m ) ? Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 10/3

  9. Upper bound Fact. Γ ( Ramsey ) = ⇒ Γ ( � ω → � m ) . Proof. Given A , let X ∈ ω ↑ ω be homogeneous for A ∩ ω ↑ ω . Then divide ran ( X ) into X 0 , X 1 , . . . such that | X i | = m i . Now H := � X 0 , X 1 , . . . � witnesses that A satisfies ( � ω → � m ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 11/3

  10. Eventually different reals Theorem. (Brendle) If ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) then ∀ a there is an eventually different real over L[ a ] . i.e. an x such that ∀ y ∈ ω ω ∩ L[ a ] ∀ ∞ n ( x ( n ) � = y ( n )) Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 12/3

  11. Eventually different reals Theorem. (Brendle) If ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) then ∀ a there is an eventually different real over L[ a ] . i.e. an x such that ∀ y ∈ ω ω ∩ L[ a ] ∀ ∞ n ( x ( n ) � = y ( n )) Proof. • Suppose not, fix a such that ∀ x ∃ y ∈ L[ a ] s.t. ∃ ∞ n ( x ( n ) = y ( n )) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 12/3

  12. Eventually different reals Theorem. (Brendle) If ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) then ∀ a there is an eventually different real over L[ a ] . i.e. an x such that ∀ y ∈ ω ω ∩ L[ a ] ∀ ∞ n ( x ( n ) � = y ( n )) Proof. • Suppose not, fix a such that ∀ x ∃ y ∈ L[ a ] s.t. ∃ ∞ n ( x ( n ) = y ( n )) . • W.l.o.g., assume that ∀ x ∃ y ∈ L[ a ] s.t. ∃ ∞ n [ x ( n ) = y ( n ) & x ( n + 1) = y ( n + 1)] . Let y x denote the < L[ a ] -least such real. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 12/3

  13. Eventually different reals Theorem. (Brendle) If ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) then ∀ a there is an eventually different real over L[ a ] . i.e. an x such that ∀ y ∈ ω ω ∩ L[ a ] ∀ ∞ n ( x ( n ) � = y ( n )) Proof. • Suppose not, fix a such that ∀ x ∃ y ∈ L[ a ] s.t. ∃ ∞ n ( x ( n ) = y ( n )) . • W.l.o.g., assume that ∀ x ∃ y ∈ L[ a ] s.t. ∃ ∞ n [ x ( n ) = y ( n ) & x ( n + 1) = y ( n + 1)] . Let y x denote the < L[ a ] -least such real. • Let A := { x | first n at which x ( n ) = y x ( n ) is even } . This is ∆ 1 2 ( a ) using the fact that < L[ a ] is ∆ 1 2 ( a ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 12/3

  14. Eventually different reals Theorem. (Brendle) If ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) then ∀ a there is an eventually different real over L[ a ] . i.e. an x such that ∀ y ∈ ω ω ∩ L[ a ] ∀ ∞ n ( x ( n ) � = y ( n )) Proof. • Suppose not, fix a such that ∀ x ∃ y ∈ L[ a ] s.t. ∃ ∞ n ( x ( n ) = y ( n )) . • W.l.o.g., assume that ∀ x ∃ y ∈ L[ a ] s.t. ∃ ∞ n [ x ( n ) = y ( n ) & x ( n + 1) = y ( n + 1)] . Let y x denote the < L[ a ] -least such real. • Let A := { x | first n at which x ( n ) = y x ( n ) is even } . This is ∆ 1 2 ( a ) using the fact that < L[ a ] is ∆ 1 2 ( a ) . • Let H be homogeneous for A , w.l.o.g. [ H ] ⊆ A . But if x ∈ [ H ] then let us change finitely many digits of x to produce a new real x ′ , such that the first n at which x ′ ( n ) = y x ( n ) is odd but still x ′ ∈ [ H ] . It is easy to see that y x = y x ′ , hence x ′ / ∈ A : contradiction. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 12/3

  15. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 13/3

  16. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 13/3

  17. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 13/3

  18. Diagram of implications Question: which implications cannot be reversed? Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 13/3

  19. Diagram of implications Question: which implications cannot be reversed? Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 14/3

  20. Mathias model Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) Let L R ω 1 be the Mathias model , i.e., the ω 1 -iteration with countable support of Mathias forcing = ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) but ¬ ∆ 1 starting from L . Then L R ω 1 | 2 ( � n → � m ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 15/3

  21. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 16/3

  22. Mathias model Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) Let L R ω 1 be the Mathias model , i.e., the ω 1 -iteration with countable support of Mathias forcing = ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) but ¬ ∆ 1 starting from L . Then L R ω 1 | 2 ( � n → � m ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 17/3

  23. Mathias model Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) Let L R ω 1 be the Mathias model , i.e., the ω 1 -iteration with countable support of Mathias forcing = ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) but ¬ ∆ 1 starting from L . Then L R ω 1 | 2 ( � n → � m ) . Proof • Clearly ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) holds in L R ω 1 . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 17/3

  24. Mathias model Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) Let L R ω 1 be the Mathias model , i.e., the ω 1 -iteration with countable support of Mathias forcing = ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) but ¬ ∆ 1 starting from L . Then L R ω 1 | 2 ( � n → � m ) . Proof • Clearly ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) holds in L R ω 1 . → [ ω ] <ω | ∀ i | S ( i ) | ≤ 2 i } . Mathias forcing satisfies the Laver • Let C := { S : ω − property : For every y ∈ M ∩ ω ω and ˙ x s.t. � ∀ i ˙ x ( i ) ≤ y ( i ) , there is an S ∈ C ∩ M s.t. � ∀ i ˙ x ( i ) ∈ S ( i ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 17/3

  25. Mathias model Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) Let L R ω 1 be the Mathias model , i.e., the ω 1 -iteration with countable support of Mathias forcing = ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) but ¬ ∆ 1 starting from L . Then L R ω 1 | 2 ( � n → � m ) . Proof • Clearly ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) holds in L R ω 1 . → [ ω ] <ω | ∀ i | S ( i ) | ≤ 2 i } . Mathias forcing satisfies the Laver • Let C := { S : ω − property : For every y ∈ M ∩ ω ω and ˙ x s.t. � ∀ i ˙ x ( i ) ≤ y ( i ) , there is an S ∈ C ∩ M s.t. � ∀ i ˙ x ( i ) ∈ S ( i ) . 2 -well-ordering of L ∩ ω ω to define a ∆ 1 • Use the ∆ 1 2 -well-ordering of L ∩ C . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 17/3

  26. Mathias model Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) Let L R ω 1 be the Mathias model , i.e., the ω 1 -iteration with countable support of Mathias forcing = ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) but ¬ ∆ 1 starting from L . Then L R ω 1 | 2 ( � n → � m ) . Proof • Clearly ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) holds in L R ω 1 . → [ ω ] <ω | ∀ i | S ( i ) | ≤ 2 i } . Mathias forcing satisfies the Laver • Let C := { S : ω − property : For every y ∈ M ∩ ω ω and ˙ x s.t. � ∀ i ˙ x ( i ) ≤ y ( i ) , there is an S ∈ C ∩ M s.t. � ∀ i ˙ x ( i ) ∈ S ( i ) . 2 -well-ordering of L ∩ ω ω to define a ∆ 1 • Use the ∆ 1 2 -well-ordering of L ∩ C . • Use that to define a ∆ 1 2 set A which explicitly violates ( � n → � m ) , where the m i grow faster then 2 i . This set is well-defined because of the Laver property. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 17/3

  27. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 18/3

  28. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 18/3

  29. A model for ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Goal. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) is false. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 19/3

  30. A model for ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Goal. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) is false. Stronger. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Miller ) is false. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 19/3

  31. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 20/3

  32. A model for ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Goal. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) is false. Stronger. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Miller ) is false. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 21/3

  33. A model for ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Goal. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) is false. Stronger. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Miller ) is false. Which properties must such a forcing have? Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 21/3

  34. A model for ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Goal. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) is false. Stronger. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Miller ) is false. Which properties must such a forcing have? 1. Proper and ω ω -bounding. for all ˙ x there is a y in the ground model and a p s.t. p � ∀ n ˙ x ( n ) ≤ y ( n ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 21/3

  35. A model for ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Goal. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) is false. Stronger. Force a model in which ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) is true but ∆ 1 2 ( Miller ) is false. Which properties must such a forcing have? 1. Proper and ω ω -bounding. for all ˙ x there is a y in the ground model and a p s.t. p � ∀ n ˙ x ( n ) ≤ y ( n ) . 2. If ∀ a there is a generic over L[ a ] , then ∆ 1 m ) holds. 2 ( � n → � Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 21/3

  36. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  37. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Creature forcing, due to [Kellner-Shelah, 2009] and [Shelah-Zapletal, unpublished]. We shall refer to it as P KSZ . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  38. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Creature forcing, due to [Kellner-Shelah, 2009] and [Shelah-Zapletal, unpublished]. We shall refer to it as P KSZ . Construction of P KSZ : Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  39. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Creature forcing, due to [Kellner-Shelah, 2009] and [Shelah-Zapletal, unpublished]. We shall refer to it as P KSZ . Construction of P KSZ : • At each n , a small ǫ n is given, and we construct a local partial order P n as follows: Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  40. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Creature forcing, due to [Kellner-Shelah, 2009] and [Shelah-Zapletal, unpublished]. We shall refer to it as P KSZ . Construction of P KSZ : • At each n , a small ǫ n is given, and we construct a local partial order P n as follows: - Let F ( n ) ∈ ω be a ‘large’ upper bound. P n consists of ‘conditions’ or ‘creatures’ of the form ( c, k ) with c ⊆ F ( n ) and k ∈ ω such that log 2 ( | c | ) − k ≥ 1 Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  41. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Creature forcing, due to [Kellner-Shelah, 2009] and [Shelah-Zapletal, unpublished]. We shall refer to it as P KSZ . Construction of P KSZ : • At each n , a small ǫ n is given, and we construct a local partial order P n as follows: - Let F ( n ) ∈ ω be a ‘large’ upper bound. P n consists of ‘conditions’ or ‘creatures’ of the form ( c, k ) with c ⊆ F ( n ) and k ∈ ω such that log 2 ( | c | ) − k ≥ 1 - ( c ′ , k ′ ) ≤ n ( c, k ) iff c ′ ⊆ c and k ′ ≥ k . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  42. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Creature forcing, due to [Kellner-Shelah, 2009] and [Shelah-Zapletal, unpublished]. We shall refer to it as P KSZ . Construction of P KSZ : • At each n , a small ǫ n is given, and we construct a local partial order P n as follows: - Let F ( n ) ∈ ω be a ‘large’ upper bound. P n consists of ‘conditions’ or ‘creatures’ of the form ( c, k ) with c ⊆ F ( n ) and k ∈ ω such that log 2 ( | c | ) − k ≥ 1 - ( c ′ , k ′ ) ≤ n ( c, k ) iff c ′ ⊆ c and k ′ ≥ k . • Let a n := 2 1 /ǫ n . For each ( c, k ) ∈ P n , norm n ( c, k ) := log a n (log 2 ( | c | ) − k ) Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  43. Creature forcing Such a forcing notion exists! Creature forcing, due to [Kellner-Shelah, 2009] and [Shelah-Zapletal, unpublished]. We shall refer to it as P KSZ . Construction of P KSZ : • At each n , a small ǫ n is given, and we construct a local partial order P n as follows: - Let F ( n ) ∈ ω be a ‘large’ upper bound. P n consists of ‘conditions’ or ‘creatures’ of the form ( c, k ) with c ⊆ F ( n ) and k ∈ ω such that log 2 ( | c | ) − k ≥ 1 - ( c ′ , k ′ ) ≤ n ( c, k ) iff c ′ ⊆ c and k ′ ≥ k . • Let a n := 2 1 /ǫ n . For each ( c, k ) ∈ P n , norm n ( c, k ) := log a n (log 2 ( | c | ) − k ) • If F ( n ) is large enough, then ∃ ( c, k ) ∈ P n s.t. norm n ( c, k ) ≥ n . [To be precise: F ( n ) ≥ 2 ((2 1 /ǫn ) n ) ] Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 22/3

  44. Creature forcing Now let P KSZ consist of conditions p such that: Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 23/3

  45. Creature forcing Now let P KSZ consist of conditions p such that: • There is stem( p ) ∈ ω <ω , ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : p ( n ) ∈ P n and norm n ( p ( n )) → ∞ . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 23/3

  46. Creature forcing Now let P KSZ consist of conditions p such that: • There is stem( p ) ∈ ω <ω , ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : p ( n ) ∈ P n and norm n ( p ( n )) → ∞ . • p ′ ≤ p iff - stem( p ′ ) ⊇ stem( p ) - For n with | stem( p ) | ≤ n < | stem( p ′ ) | we have p ′ ( n ) ∈ first coordinate of p ( n ) - For n ≥ | stem( p ′ ) | we have p ′ ( n ) ≤ n p ( n ) Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 23/3

  47. Creature forcing Now let P KSZ consist of conditions p such that: • There is stem( p ) ∈ ω <ω , ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : p ( n ) ∈ P n and norm n ( p ( n )) → ∞ . • p ′ ≤ p iff - stem( p ′ ) ⊇ stem( p ) - For n with | stem( p ) | ≤ n < | stem( p ′ ) | we have p ′ ( n ) ∈ first coordinate of p ( n ) - For n ≥ | stem( p ′ ) | we have p ′ ( n ) ≤ n p ( n ) Remark: P KSZ adds a generic real, but the generic filter is not determined from the generic real in the usual way, and P KSZ is not in general representable as BOREL( ω ω ) /I for a σ -ideal I . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 23/3

  48. Proper and ω ω -bounding Theorem. (Kellner-Shelah, Shelah-Zapletal) If P KSZ is as above, and moreover 1 ∀ n : ǫ n ≤ n · � j<n F ( j ) then P KSZ is proper and ω ω -bounding. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 24/3

  49. Proper and ω ω -bounding Theorem. (Kellner-Shelah, Shelah-Zapletal) If P KSZ is as above, and moreover 1 ∀ n : ǫ n ≤ n · � j<n F ( j ) then P KSZ is proper and ω ω -bounding. The proof uses two properties from the general theory of creature forcings: for each n , P n satisfies “ ǫ n -bigness ” and “ ǫ n -halving ”. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 24/3

  50. Forcing ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) If for every a there is a P KSZ -generic over L[ a ] then ∆ 1 2 ( � m → � n ) holds. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 25/3

  51. Forcing ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) If for every a there is a P KSZ -generic over L[ a ] then ∆ 1 2 ( � m → � n ) holds. Proof • For p ∈ P KSZ let [ p ] := { x ∈ ω ω | stem( p ) ⊆ x and ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : x ( n ) ∈ 1 st coordinate of p ( n ) } . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 25/3

  52. Forcing ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) If for every a there is a P KSZ -generic over L[ a ] then ∆ 1 2 ( � m → � n ) holds. Proof • For p ∈ P KSZ let [ p ] := { x ∈ ω ω | stem( p ) ⊆ x and ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : x ( n ) ∈ 1 st coordinate of p ( n ) } . • P KSZ satisfies pure decision : for every φ and p ∈ P KSZ there is q ≤ p with the same stem as p s.t. q � φ or q � ¬ φ . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 25/3

  53. Forcing ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) If for every a there is a P KSZ -generic over L[ a ] then ∆ 1 2 ( � m → � n ) holds. Proof • For p ∈ P KSZ let [ p ] := { x ∈ ω ω | stem( p ) ⊆ x and ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : x ( n ) ∈ 1 st coordinate of p ( n ) } . • P KSZ satisfies pure decision : for every φ and p ∈ P KSZ there is q ≤ p with the same stem as p s.t. q � φ or q � ¬ φ . • Let A ⊆ ω ω be a ∆ 1 2 ( a ) -set, defined by Σ 1 2 ( a ) formulas φ and ψ . By downward Π 1 3 -absoluteness, the sentence “ ∀ x ( φ ( x ) ↔ ¬ ψ ( x )) ” holds in all generic extensions of L[ a ] . Using this fact and pure decision, find a condition p in L[ a ] , with empty stem, s.t. p � φ ( ˙ x gen ) or p � ψ ( ˙ x gen ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 25/3

  54. Forcing ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) If for every a there is a P KSZ -generic over L[ a ] then ∆ 1 2 ( � m → � n ) holds. Proof • For p ∈ P KSZ let [ p ] := { x ∈ ω ω | stem( p ) ⊆ x and ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : x ( n ) ∈ 1 st coordinate of p ( n ) } . • P KSZ satisfies pure decision : for every φ and p ∈ P KSZ there is q ≤ p with the same stem as p s.t. q � φ or q � ¬ φ . • Let A ⊆ ω ω be a ∆ 1 2 ( a ) -set, defined by Σ 1 2 ( a ) formulas φ and ψ . By downward Π 1 3 -absoluteness, the sentence “ ∀ x ( φ ( x ) ↔ ¬ ψ ( x )) ” holds in all generic extensions of L[ a ] . Using this fact and pure decision, find a condition p in L[ a ] , with empty stem, s.t. p � φ ( ˙ x gen ) or p � ψ ( ˙ x gen ) . • W.l.o.g. assume the former, and work in L[ a ] from now on. Let M ≺ H θ be countable and q ≤ p a ( M, P KSZ ) -Master condition. By pure decision, q has empty stem as well. Moreover, every x ∈ [ q ] is M -generic and by standard absoluteness arguments [ q ] ⊆ A follows. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 25/3

  55. Forcing ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) If for every a there is a P KSZ -generic over L[ a ] then ∆ 1 2 ( � m → � n ) holds. Proof • For p ∈ P KSZ let [ p ] := { x ∈ ω ω | stem( p ) ⊆ x and ∀ n ≥ | stem( p ) | : x ( n ) ∈ 1 st coordinate of p ( n ) } . • P KSZ satisfies pure decision : for every φ and p ∈ P KSZ there is q ≤ p with the same stem as p s.t. q � φ or q � ¬ φ . • Let A ⊆ ω ω be a ∆ 1 2 ( a ) -set, defined by Σ 1 2 ( a ) formulas φ and ψ . By downward Π 1 3 -absoluteness, the sentence “ ∀ x ( φ ( x ) ↔ ¬ ψ ( x )) ” holds in all generic extensions of L[ a ] . Using this fact and pure decision, find a condition p in L[ a ] , with empty stem, s.t. p � φ ( ˙ x gen ) or p � ψ ( ˙ x gen ) . • W.l.o.g. assume the former, and work in L[ a ] from now on. Let M ≺ H θ be countable and q ≤ p a ( M, P KSZ ) -Master condition. By pure decision, q has empty stem as well. Moreover, every x ∈ [ q ] is M -generic and by standard absoluteness arguments [ q ] ⊆ A follows. • Since q has empty stem, it witnesses that A satisfies ( � n → � m ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 25/3

  56. Forcing ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Corollary. An ω 1 -iteration of P KSZ , starting from L , gives a model in which ∆ 1 m ) holds but ∆ 1 2 ( Miller ) fails. 2 ( � n → � Notice that the bounds “ � n ” have been explicitly computed beforehand: they are the F ( n ) ’s from the definition of P KSZ . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 26/3

  57. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 27/3

  58. Other properties Definition. A real x ∈ [ ω ] ω is splitting over M if for all a ∈ [ ω ] ω ∩ M , both a ∩ x and a \ x are infinite. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 28/3

  59. Other properties Definition. A real x ∈ [ ω ] ω is splitting over M if for all a ∈ [ ω ] ω ∩ M , both a ∩ x and a \ x are infinite. Theorem. (Shelah-Zapletal) P KSZ does not add splitting reals. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 28/3

  60. Other properties Definition. A real x ∈ [ ω ] ω is splitting over M if for all a ∈ [ ω ] ω ∩ M , both a ∩ x and a \ x are infinite. Theorem. (Shelah-Zapletal) P KSZ does not add splitting reals. By another result of Zapletal, the conjunction “ ω ω -bounding and not adding splitting reals” is preserved in ω 1 -iterations, so: Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 28/3

  61. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 29/3

  62. Open questions for ∆ 1 2 Open questions 1. Is the implication ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) ⇒ ∃ ev. diff. reals strict? Conjecture: ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) fails in the Random model. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 30/3

  63. Open questions for ∆ 1 2 Open questions 1. Is the implication ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) ⇒ ∃ ev. diff. reals strict? Conjecture: ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) fails in the Random model. 2. Is there a characterization of ∆ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) and ∆ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) in terms of transcendence over L ? Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 30/3

  64. The property on the Σ 1 2 level Recall that for Ramsey, Sacks, Miller and Laver measurability, ∆ 1 2 and Σ 1 2 are equivalent. Question: Are ∆ 1 2 and Σ 1 2 equivalent for the polarized partition properties? Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 31/3

  65. What we do know Theorem. If Σ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) then ∀ a ∃ H s.t. ∀ x ∈ [ H ] : x is eventually different over L[ a ] . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 32/3

  66. What we do know Theorem. If Σ 1 2 ( � ω → � m ) then ∀ a ∃ H s.t. ∀ x ∈ [ H ] : x is eventually different over L[ a ] . Theorem. In the Mathias model, Σ 1 2 ( Ramsey ) holds while Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) fails. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 32/3

  67. Diagram of implications Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 33/3

  68. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Can we extend the result about P KSZ to Σ 1 2 ? Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 34/3

  69. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Can we extend the result about P KSZ to Σ 1 2 ? Not a priori, since P KSZ only adds one generic real. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 34/3

  70. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Can we extend the result about P KSZ to Σ 1 2 ? Not a priori, since P KSZ only adds one generic real. [DiPrisco & Todorˇ cevi´ c] use a forcing P DPT adding a whole generic product H G with the following property: For all Borel sets B in the ground model, ( ∗ ) B ∩ [ H G ] is relatively clopen in [ H G ] . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 34/3

  71. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) An ω 1 -iteration of P DPT starting from L give a model where Σ 1 m ) holds. 2 ( � n → � Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 35/3

  72. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) An ω 1 -iteration of P DPT starting from L give a model where Σ 1 m ) holds. 2 ( � n → � Proof. • Let A be Σ 1 2 ( a ) . Using Shoenfield trees, we find a partition A = � α<ω 1 A α into Borel sets with codes in L[ a ] . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 35/3

  73. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) An ω 1 -iteration of P DPT starting from L give a model where Σ 1 m ) holds. 2 ( � n → � Proof. • Let A be Σ 1 2 ( a ) . Using Shoenfield trees, we find a partition A = � α<ω 1 A α into Borel sets with codes in L[ a ] . • Since by the property ( ∗ ) of P DPT there is a product H in V s.t. every A α ∩ [ H ] is relatively clopen in [ H ] , by compactness A is a union of finitely many clopen sets (in [ H ] ) and so it is in fact Borel (in [ H ] ). Then it follows easily that A satisfies ( � n → � m ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 35/3

  74. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Theorem. (Brendle-Kh) An ω 1 -iteration of P DPT starting from L give a model where Σ 1 m ) holds. 2 ( � n → � Proof. • Let A be Σ 1 2 ( a ) . Using Shoenfield trees, we find a partition A = � α<ω 1 A α into Borel sets with codes in L[ a ] . • Since by the property ( ∗ ) of P DPT there is a product H in V s.t. every A α ∩ [ H ] is relatively clopen in [ H ] , by compactness A is a union of finitely many clopen sets (in [ H ] ) and so it is in fact Borel (in [ H ] ). Then it follows easily that A satisfies ( � n → � m ) . Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 35/3

  75. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Only problem: it is difficult to see whether P DPT is ω ω -bounding. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 36/3

  76. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Only problem: it is difficult to see whether P DPT is ω ω -bounding. So instead, we can combine elements of P DPT with P KSZ to produce a new forcing notion P which is still proper and ω ω -bounding (higher bounds but same idea) and moreover adds a product with the ( ∗ ) property. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 36/3

  77. Forcing Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) Only problem: it is difficult to see whether P DPT is ω ω -bounding. So instead, we can combine elements of P DPT with P KSZ to produce a new forcing notion P which is still proper and ω ω -bounding (higher bounds but same idea) and moreover adds a product with the ( ∗ ) property. Corollary. There is a model where Σ 1 2 ( � n → � m ) holds but Σ 1 2 ( Miller ) fails. Polarized Partition Properties on the Second Level of theProjective Hierarchy. – p. 36/3

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend