on the role of auxiliary assumptions in the production of
play

On the Role of Auxiliary Assumptions in the Production of Evidence - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References On the Role of Auxiliary Assumptions in the Production of Evidence Corey Dethier University of Notre Dame Philosophy Department corey.dethier@gmail.com Nov. 3, 2018 PSA 2018


  1. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References On the Role of Auxiliary Assumptions in the Production of Evidence Corey Dethier University of Notre Dame Philosophy Department corey.dethier@gmail.com Nov. 3, 2018 PSA 2018

  2. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Introduction

  3. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Traditional (Duhemian) view of auxiliary hypotheses No (logical) difference between an auxiliary hypothesis and the hypothesis-to-be-tested. Consequence: theories are tested as a whole. Under attacked for decades (see, e.g., Azzouni 2000; Hacking 1983; Longino 1990; J. Norton 2008). Implications for auxiliary hypotheses have been underdeveloped.

  4. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Duhem’s argument (P1) Hypotheses are (only) tested via the comparison of derived consequences with the world (Duhem 1914/1951, 180). (P2) In the derivation of consequences, there is no logical difference between the hypothesis and the auxiliary hypotheses (Duhem 1914/1951, 182). (P3) The auxiliary hypotheses relied on in actual testing scenarios are “science ... taken as a whole” (Duhem 1914/1951, 187). (C) In actual testing scenarios, the “science ... taken as a whole” is tested.

  5. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References A problem I think the Duhemian conclusion is false. Specifically, in any case in which (known) idealizations are employed in the derivation of consequences, it would be unreasonable to say that the truth of the idealization and hypothesis are both tested. – we already know the idealization is false! In the first part of the talk, I run through two such cases.

  6. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Saying something positive Diagnosis: the argument turns on a conflation between the assumptions necessary for the derivation of an empirically testable consequence from a hypothesis and the assumptions necessary to test the theory. Upshot: the role of auxiliary hypotheses in testing is more akin to that of reliability-apt tools than it is to truth-apt premises . (And then some implications.)

  7. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Counterexamples

  8. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References The shape of the earth F g e p F g p x-section of a rotating sphere If you can measure differences in acceleration by latitude, you can distinguish between different theories of gravity.

  9. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Measuring differences in acceleration Pendulum lengths ( ℓ ) and periods ( T ) can be related to acceleration by: a “ 4 ℓπ 2 T 2 According to the traditional view, the use of the pendulum as an instrument to measure acceleration requires assuming that this equation is true. Can only test universal gravity insofar as we’re simultaneously testing this relationship.

  10. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References A problem The pendulum equation isn’t actually true; it’s an idealization in that it fails to account for the effects of amplitude. Practically speaking, this effect is negligible when the amplitude is small, but it does exist. The problem: the pendulum data serves as a test of universal gravity even though the theory as a whole is false.

  11. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References HW model of allele distribution Gen 1 Gen 2 A 1 A 1 = p 2 G 1 freq( A 1 ) = p G 1 A 1 A 2 = 2 pq freq( A 2 ) = q A 2 A 2 = q 2 G 1

  12. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References HW assumptions Assumptions of the HW model include: infinite population; no mutation; no differential fitness; no organization of mating within the population; no genetic exchange with other populations; no genetic exchange between generations. Clearly, these assumptions are never literally satisfied by an actual population; at best, there’s effective approximation.

  13. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Heretozygote advantage Heterozygote advantage occurs when the heterozygote ( A 1 A 2 ) has a fitness advantage over the homozygotes. In testing, the application of the HW model is crucial: we can only measure the advantage by means of the deviation from HW equilibrium. Essentially: the HW model acts like a (“vicarious”) control population (compare S. D. Norton and Suppe 2001).

  14. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Conflation

  15. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References What’s gone wrong? Why are these two cases tests? Roughly: the observable data can be used—in combination with certain theories or models—to discriminate between two hypotheses. Clearly, we don’t need to assume that theories or models are true or “perfect” (c.f. Teller 2001) in order to use them (in this way). Instead, we must assume that the equation or model is reliable in the context of use.

  16. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Reliability What does “reliable” mean in the context of the prior slide? Roughly, a model or theory is reliable to the degree that it allows for (something like) truth-preserving inferences in the context of use: given accurate data and a model or theory that is reliable to degree x , we should correctly pick out the true hypothesis x % of the time. Obviously, truth is not necessary for reliability. And note the parallel here with instruments.

  17. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References The alleged conflation My claim, then, is that the argument given above conflates the assumptions necessary to derive consequences from a hypothesis (assumptions about truth) with those necessary to use those consequences as a test (assumptions about reliability). As such, we should reject the claim that theories are tested (only) via their derived consequences. Instead, the connection between them is secured by theories and models that allow for more-or-less reliable (in a context) use of the data.

  18. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Why not simply re-write the argument? Why not simply claim that the mistake lies in the account of which auxiliary hypotheses are employed in a derivation? – i.e., instead of the hypothesis that Newtonian theory is true, the hypothesis that it is reliable. Allows us to maintain the connection between derivation and testing. Doesn’t allow us to maintain the idea that anything even approximating the “whole theory” must be assumed to be true in each test, however.

  19. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References The role of auxiliary assumptions Traditional view: the primary role of auxiliary hypotheses in testing is as (truth-apt) premises in the derivation of consequences. My view: the primary role of auxiliary hypotheses in testing is as (reliability-apt) tools that are used in combination with empirical data to distinguish between hypotheses.

  20. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Implications

  21. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References First: Models as epistemic tools As just noted, my view is that the theories and models that we employ as auxiliary hypotheses are epistemic tools, in a sense similar to the sense in which physical instruments are. This view fits well with the position recently advocated by a number of authors (e.g., Edwards 2010; Lloyd 2012; Morrison 2015) who argue that experiments and evidence production inevitably involves both theoretical and physical aspects.

  22. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Models as epistemic tools (continued) The analysis so far suggests a further conclusion. Not only are both models and instruments involved in testing, they play essentially the same epistemic role: both are “tools” in the production of evidence in the sense that (a) their role is to secure a connection between theoretical question and world; (b) what matters is their (in-context) reliability for this task. Asking whether our pendulum equation is “true” is therefore much like asking whether a thermometer would give accurate readings on the sun—it’s completely irrelevant to determining whether the answer is a good one.

  23. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Second: Idealizations and confirmation theory Suppose we know that a model, M , is an idealization; there’s some way in which it misrepresents the phenomenon. On a straightfoward interpretation of P p M q , then, we can’t conditionalize on M : P p H | M q “ P p H q P p M | H q P p M q So even if M ( H , we cannot formally say that M supports H .

  24. Introduction Counterexamples Conflation Implications References Idealizations and confirmation theory (continued) I’ve spent this talk giving independent reasons for thinking that this is the wrong way to interpret P p M q . Instead, we should interpret P p M q as the probability that M is reliable in the context of use. No principled reason for rejecting the use of these context-sensitive judgments of reliability in confirmation given that we already need to make them when we’re using instruments.

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend