ec487 advanced microeconomics part i lecture 7
play

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 7 Leonardo Felli - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 7 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 10 November, 2017 Nash Theorem Recall that we are focussing exclusively on finite games: A i is a finite set for every i N . Theorem (Nash Theorem) Every finite


  1. EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 7 Leonardo Felli 32L.LG.04 10 November, 2017

  2. Nash Theorem Recall that we are focussing exclusively on finite games: A i is a finite set for every i ∈ N . Theorem (Nash Theorem) Every finite normal form game Γ Γ = { N ; A i , ∀ i ∈ N ; u i ( a ) , ∀ i ∈ N } has a mixed strategy Nash equilibrium. Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 2 / 59

  3. General Theorem We will prove the Nash Theorem as an immediate consequence of a somewhat more general/special existence theorem. Theorem Consider an N-players game Λ = { N ; D i , ∀ i ∈ N ; v i ( d ) , ∀ i ∈ N } where: ◮ D i is a compact, convex subset of an Euclidean space; ◮ v i ( d i , d − i ) is continuous and quasiconcave in d. Then Λ has a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 3 / 59

  4. Proof of General Theorem Recall that: Definition The function v i ( d i , d − i ) is quasiconcave if and only if the upper level set { d i | v i ( d i , d − i ) ≥ k } is a convex set for every scalar k . An alternative definition of quasiconcavity is: Definition The function v i ( d i , d − i ) is quasiconcave if and only if for every pair d i ∈ D i , ˆ d i ∈ D i and α ∈ [0 , 1] v i ( α d i + (1 − α ) ˆ d i , d − i ) ≥ min { v i ( d i , d − i ) , v i ( ˆ d i , d − i ) } . Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 4 / 59

  5. Proof of General Theorem (cont’d) The key tool we will use is. Theorem (Kakutani’s Fixed Point Theorem) Let X be a compact, convex and non-empty set in R n and F : X ⇒ X a correspondence that satisfies the following properties: ◮ non-empty; ◮ convex valued; ◮ upper-hemi-continuous. Then there exists a vector x ∗ ∈ X such that: x ∗ ∈ F ( x ∗ ) Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 5 / 59

  6. Proof of General Theorem (cont’d) For each player i ≤ N define the best reply correspondence φ i as: d i ∈ D i | v i ( d i , d − i ) ≥ v i ( d ′ i , d − i ) , ∀ d ′ � � φ i ( d ) = i ∈ D i Notice that: ◮ φ i ( d ) is nonempty since D i is compact and v i ( d ) is continuous (Weierstrass Theorem). ◮ φ i ( d ) is convex-valued since D i is compact and v i ( d ) is quasiconcave in d i . Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 6 / 59

  7. Proof of General Theorem (cont’d) ◮ φ i ( d ) is upper-hemi-continuous: Consider the sequence { d h } where d h ∈ D 1 × · · · × D N and assume that d h → d Consider also the sequence { d h i } where d h i ∈ D i and assume that d h i → d i Assume that d h i ∈ φ i ( d h ) , ∀ h ≥ 1 Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 7 / 59

  8. Proof of General Theorem (cont’d) Notice that by definition of the correspondence φ i ( · ) for every ˆ d i ∈ D i we have − i ) ≥ v i ( ˆ v i ( d h i , d h d i , d h − i ) By continuity of v i ( d ) we then have v i ( d i , d − i ) ≥ v i ( ˆ d i , d − i ) In other words d i ∈ φ i ( d ) Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 8 / 59

  9. Proof of General Theorem (cont’d) ◮ Now define the correspondence φ : D 1 × · · · × D N → D 1 × · · · × D N as φ ( d ) = φ 1 ( d ) × · · · × φ N ( d ) ◮ Notice then that φ ( d ) satisfies all the assumptions of Kakutani Fixed Point Theorem: The set D 1 × · · · × D N is a compact, convex and non-empty subset of an Euclidean space, since each D i is a compact, convex and non-empty subset of an euclidean space. Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 9 / 59

  10. Proof of General Theorem (cont’d) The correspondence φ ( d ) is non-empty, convex valued and upper-hemi-continuous since each φ i ( d ) is non-empty, convex valued and upper-hemi-continuous. ◮ Therefore there exists a fixed point d such that d ∈ φ ( d ) or there exists a strategy profile d such that each element of it is a best reply to the strategy profile itself. ◮ In other words, there exists a pure strategy Nash equilibrium of the game Λ. Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 10 / 59

  11. Proof of Nash Theorem Consider now the finite normal form game Γ: Γ = { N ; A i , ∀ i ∈ N ; u i ( a ) , ∀ i ∈ N } Its mixed extension is the game Γ ∆ : Γ ∆ = { N ; ∆( A i ) , ∀ i ∈ N ; U i ( σ ) , ∀ i ∈ N } where, if A i contains n strategies, ∆( A i ) is the ( n − 1)-dimensional simplex, σ i ∈ ∆( A i ) and � � � σ 1 ( a 1 ) · . . . · σ I ( a I ) U i ( σ ) = u i ( a 1 , . . . , a I ) a ∈ A Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 11 / 59

  12. Proof of Nash Theorem (cont’d) Notice now that the mixed extension game Γ ∆ satisfies all the assumption of the general theorem considered above. ◮ ∆( A i ) is a compact, convex subset of an Euclidean space; ◮ U i ( σ ) is a continuous and quasiconcave (linear) function. Hence by the theorem above there exists a pure strategy Nash equilibrium of the game Γ ∆ that is a mixed strategy Nash equilibrium of the game Γ. Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 12 / 59

  13. A Voluntary Contribution Game Consider an economy in which each of N individuals is allocated a share of the endowment of the private good ω = ( ω 1 , . . . , ω N ) We assume that each individual voluntarily contributes an amount z i of his private good for the (collectively run) production of the public good:   N � z j y = g   j =1 We are going to take each individual’s contribution decision to be the one predicted by the Nash equilibrium of this symultaneous move contribution game . Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 13 / 59

  14. A Voluntary Contribution Game (cont’d) In other words, the amount of the private good z i that individual i contributes is the solution to the following best reply problem for i : U i ( x i , y ) max { x i , z i } x i + z i ≤ ω i s.t.   N � z j y = g   j =1 The first order conditions of this problem leads to the following marginal condition: ∂ U i /∂ y 1 ∂ U i /∂ x i = g ′ ( z ) , ∀ i = 1 , . . . , N Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 14 / 59

  15. A Voluntary Contribution Game (cont’d) The Nash equilibrium of the voluntary contribution game is then defined by the following set of marginal conditions: ∂ U i /∂ y 1 ∀ i = 1 , . . . , N ∂ U i /∂ x i = g ′ ( z ) , Recall that the Pareto efficient allocation is the one defined by the Bowen-Lindahl-Samuelson condition: N ∂ U i /∂ y 1 � ∂ U i /∂ x i = g ′ ( z ) i =1 Clearly, the allocation generated by this contribution game is Pareto inefficient: agent i contributes up to the point where the marginal cost of the public good (MRT) is equal to i ’s marginal rate of substitution between y and z . Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 15 / 59

  16. A Voluntary Contribution Game (cont’d) To highlight the nature of the inefficiency consider the following parametric characterization: U i ( x i , y ) = x i + v ( y ) , v ′ ( · ) > 0 , v ′′ ( · ) < 0 , v (0) = 0 , v ′ (0) = + ∞ g ( z ) = z . Player i ’s best reply is then the solution to the problem: x i + v ( y ) max { x i , z i } x i + z i ≤ ω i s.t. N � z j y = j =1 Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 16 / 59

  17. A Voluntary Contribution Game (cont’d) Notice first that monotonicity of each player’s utility function implies x i + z i = ω i Player i ’s best reply is then the solution to the problem:   N ω i − z i + v � z j max   z i j =1 The first order conditions are then:   N v ′ �  = 1 z j  j =1 Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 17 / 59

  18. A Voluntary Contribution Game (cont’d) There exist potentially lots of Nash Equilibria of this game. Assume that ω i = ω and consider the symmetric Nash equilibrium such that z i = z for every i ≤ N . Each player Nash equilibrium contribution z ∗ is then such that: v ′ ( N z ∗ ) = 1 Consider now the symmetric Pareto efficient allocation in this environment. Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 18 / 59

  19. A Voluntary Contribution Game (cont’d) The general central planner problem, for λ i > 0 for all i ≤ N , is: N λ i [ x i + v ( y )] � max { x i , z i } i =1 N ( x i + z i ) ≤ N ω � s.t. i =1 N � z i y = i =1 or N � � N �� x i + v � � x i max λ i N ω − { x i } i =1 i =1 Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 19 / 59

  20. A Voluntary Contribution Game (cont’d) The first order conditions are, for every i ≤ N : N � N � � λ j v ′ � x i N ω − = λ i j =1 i =1 or � N � λ i � v ′ z i = � N j =1 λ j i =1 In the symmetric case case λ i = λ and z i = z ∗∗ the Pareto efficient allocation is such that: v ′ ( N z ∗∗ ) = 1 N of course in the case z ∗∗ is such that v ( N z ∗∗ ) − z ∗∗ ≥ 0. Leonardo Felli (LSE) EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I 10 November, 2017 20 / 59

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend