an introduction to the theory of coherent lower previsions
play

An introduction to the theory of coherent lower previsions 2nd - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

An introduction to the theory of coherent lower previsions 2nd SIPTA School on Imprecise Probabilities, Madrid, July 24-28, 2006 Enrique Miranda Rey Juan Carlos University Dep. of Statistics and O.R. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise


  1. An introduction to the theory of coherent lower previsions 2nd SIPTA School on Imprecise Probabilities, Madrid, July 24-28, 2006 Enrique Miranda Rey Juan Carlos University Dep. of Statistics and O.R. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 1/8

  2. Overview, Part I Some considerations about probability. Coherent previsions and probabilities. Coherent lower and upper previsions. Sets of desirable gambles and linear previsions. Natural extension. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 2/8

  3. Some considerations about probability History. Interpretations. Subjective probability. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 3/8

  4. Which is the goal of probability? Probability seeks to determine the plausibility of the different outcomes of an experiment when these cannot be predicted beforehand. What is the probability of guessing the 6 winning numbers in the lottery? What is the probability of arriving in 30’ from the airport to Manuel Becerra by car? What is the probability of having a sunny day tomorrow? 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 4/8

  5. A bit of history Three main steps: The first works in probability were made in the XVII century, in some letters between Pascal and Fermat. Both them and de Moivre and Bernoulli later on used probability to model games of chance. In 1812, Laplace made a mathematical formalisation of the previous works and used probability in connection with other types of problems. In 1933, Kolmogorov established an axiomatic definition. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 5/8

  6. σ -fields of events Probability is usually defined on σ -fields of events. Given a space X , an event is any subset A ⊆ X . A class A of events is called a σ -field when it satisfies: ∅ , X ∈ A . A c ∈ A for any A ∈ A . Given ( A n ) n ∈ A , their union ∪ n A n ∈ A . 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 6/8

  7. Kolmogorov’s definition of probability A probability P on X is a mapping defined on a σ -field A of subsets of X satisfying: 1. P ( A ) ≥ 0 for any A in A . 2. P ( X ) = 1 . 3. Given ( A n ) n pairwise disjoint, P ( ∪ n A n ) = � n P ( A n ) . 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 7/8

  8. Finite and σ -additive probabilities Some people only require (3) to hold for finite unions, and this produces the so-called finitely additive probabilities. Advantages: They can be defined on all events, and are easier to justify. Disadvantages: σ -additive probabilities satisfy continuity properties and limit results. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 8/8

  9. Interpretations of probability Classical. Frequentist. Subjective. . . . 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 9/8

  10. Aleatory vs. epistemic In some cases, the probability of an event A is a property of the event, meaning that it does not depend on the subject making the assessment. We talk then of aleatory probabilities. However, and specially in the framework of decision making, we may need to assess probabilities that represent our beliefs. Hence, these may vary depending on the subject or on the amount of information he possesses at the time. We talk then of subjective probabilities. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 10/8

  11. The behavioural interpretation One of the possible interpretations of subjective probability is the behavioural interpretation. We interpret the probability of an event A in terms of our betting behaviour: we are disposed to bet at most P ( A ) euros on the event A . If we consider the gamble I A where we win 1 euro if A happens and 0 if it doesn’t happen, then we accept the transaction I A − P ( A ) , because the expected gain is (1 − P ( A )) ∗ P ( A ) + (0 − P ( A ))(1 − P ( A )) = 0 . 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 11/8

  12. Gambles More generally, we can consider our betting behaviour on gambles. A gamble is a bounded real-valued variable on X , f : X → R . It represents a reward that depends on the outcome of the experiment modelled by X . We shall denote the set of all gambles by L ( X ) . 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 12/8

  13. Example Who shall win the next World Cup? Consider the outcomes a=an American team, b=an European team, c=an African/Asian team. X = { a, b, c } . Consider the gamble f ( a ) = 3 , f ( b ) = − 2 , f ( c ) = 10 . Depending on how likely I consider each of the outcomes I will accept the gamble or not. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 13/8

  14. Betting on gambles Consider now a gamble f on X . We may consider the supremum value µ such that we are disposed to pay µ for f , i.e., such that the reward f − µ is desirable: it will be the expectation E ( f ) . For any µ < E ( f ) , we expect to have a gain. For any µ > E ( f ) , we expect to have a loss. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 14/8

  15. Buying and selling prices I may also give money in order to get the reward: if I am disposed to pay x for the gamble f , then the gamble f − x is desirable to me. I may also sell a gamble f , meaning that if I am disposed to sell it at a price x then the gamble x − f is desirable to me. In the case of probabilities, the supremum buying price for a gamble f coincides with the infimum selling price. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 15/8

  16. Events or gambles? In the case of probabilities, we are indifferent between betting on event or on gambles: our betting rates on events (a probability) determine our betting rates on gambles (its expectation). Since we want to be able to express our beliefs for any event, we consider here finitely additive probabilities. What happens if we are not certain of which probability to use? 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 16/8

  17. Existence of indecision When we don’t have much information, it may be difficult (and unreasonable) to give a fair price P ( f ) : there may be some prices µ for which we would not be disposed to buy or sell the gamble f . In terms of desirable gambles, this means that we would be indifferent between two gambles. It is sometimes considered preferable to give different values P ( f ) < P ( f ) than to give a precise (and possibly wrong) value. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 17/8

  18. Lower and upper previsions The lower prevision for a gamble f , P ( f ) , is my supremum acceptable buying price for f , meaning that I am disposed to buy it for P ( f ) − ǫ (or to accept the reward f − ( P ( f ) − ǫ )) for any ǫ > 0 . The upper prevision for a gamble f , P ( f ) , is my infimum acceptable selling price for f , meaning that I am disposed to sell f for P ( f ) + ǫ (or to accept the reward P ( f ) + ǫ − f ) for any ǫ > 0 . 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 18/8

  19. Conjugacy of P, P Under this interpretation, P ( − f ) = sup { x : − f − x acceptable } = − inf { x : f + x acceptable } = − P ( f ) Hence, it suffices to work with one of these two functions. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 19/8

  20. Important remark The domain K of P : need not have any predefined structure. may contain indicators of events. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 20/8

  21. Lower probabilities of events The lower probability of A , P ( A ) = lower prevision P ( I A ) of the indicator of A . = supremum betting rate on A . = measure of the evidence supporting A . = measure of the strength of our belief in A . 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 21/8

  22. Upper probabilities of events The upper probability of A , P ( A ) = upper prevision P ( I A ) of the indicator of A . = measure of the lack of evidence against A . = measure of the plausibility of A . We have then a behavioural interpretation of upper and lower probabilities: evidence in favour of A ↑ ⇒ P ( A ) ↑ evidence against A ↑ ⇒ P ( A ) ↓ 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 22/8

  23. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 23/8

  24. Events or gambles (II) In the imprecise case, the lower and upper previsions for events do not determine the lower and upper previsions for gambles uniquely. Hence, lower and upper previsions are more informative than lower and upper probabilities. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 24/8

  25. Precise previsions If we knew the probability of each of the outcomes, then our prevision for a gamble f would be the expected value E ( f ) : for any smaller value x the gamble f − x would produce a gain in the long run (so we would be disposed to buy f for it), and for any greater value the value f − x would result in a loss in the long run (so we would accept x − f , that is, we would sell f for the price x ). In general we are not able to determine exactly the probability of each outcome, and we end up with lower and upper previsions. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 25/8

  26. Consistency requirements The assessments made by a lower prevision on a set of gambles should satisfy a number of consistency requirements: A combination of the assessments should not produce a net loss, no matter the outcome: avoiding sure loss. Our supremum buying price for a gamble f should not depend on our assessments for other gambles: coherence. 2nd SIPTA school on imprecise probabilities – p. 26/8

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend