varieties of de morgan monoids i minimality and
play

Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I : Minimality and Irreducible - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I : Minimality and Irreducible Algebras T. Moraschini, 1 J.G. Raftery 2 J.J. Wannenburg 2 and 1 Czech Academy of Sciences, Prague 2 University of Pretoria, South Africa LATD 2017. Prague, Czech Republic T.


  1. Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I : Minimality and Irreducible Algebras T. Moraschini, 1 J.G. Raftery 2 J.J. Wannenburg 2 and 1 Czech Academy of Sciences, Prague 2 University of Pretoria, South Africa LATD 2017. Prague, Czech Republic T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  2. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  3. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  4. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  5. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  6. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  7. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  8. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  9. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  10. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  11. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  12. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  13. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  14. Relevance logic began in protest at ‘paradoxes’ of material implication, e.g., the weakening axiom p → ( q → p ) . It has multiple interpretations, however, and now fits under the ideology-free umbrella of substructural logics. Relative to these, R t combines ∧ , ∨ distributivity with the contraction axiom ( p → ( p → q )) → ( p → q ) . Urquhart (1984): R t is undecidable. Algebraic effects? Less explored—philosophical equivocation over the status of t : distinguished or not? (In the absence of weakening, t is not equationally definable. The t –free reducts of De Morgan monoids don’t form a variety, as they are not closed under subalgebras. For the anti-isomorphism above, t must be distinguished.) T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  15. Relevance logic began in protest at ‘paradoxes’ of material implication, e.g., the weakening axiom p → ( q → p ) . It has multiple interpretations, however, and now fits under the ideology-free umbrella of substructural logics. Relative to these, R t combines ∧ , ∨ distributivity with the contraction axiom ( p → ( p → q )) → ( p → q ) . Urquhart (1984): R t is undecidable. Algebraic effects? Less explored—philosophical equivocation over the status of t : distinguished or not? (In the absence of weakening, t is not equationally definable. The t –free reducts of De Morgan monoids don’t form a variety, as they are not closed under subalgebras. For the anti-isomorphism above, t must be distinguished.) T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend