rewriting
play

Rewriting Part 1. Abstract Reduction Temur Kutsia RISC, JKU Linz - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Rewriting Part 1. Abstract Reduction Temur Kutsia RISC, JKU Linz Literature Franz Baader and Tobias Nipkow. Term Rewriting and All That. Cambridge University Press, 1998. Books home page:


  1. Symbolic Differentiation ▸ Rewrite rules: D X ( X ) → 1 ( R 1 ) D X ( Y ) → 0 ( R 2 ) D X ( u + v ) → D X ( u ) + D X ( v ) ( R 3 ) D X ( u ∗ v ) → ( u ∗ D X ( v )) + ( D X ( u ) ∗ v ) ( R 3 ) ▸ Differentiate D X ( X ∗ X ) : D X ( X ∗ X ) ( R 4 ) ( X ∗ D X ( X ))) + ( D X ( X ) ∗ X ) ( R 1 ) ( R 1 ) ( X ∗ 1 ) + ( D X ( X ) ∗ X ) ( X ∗ D X ( X )) + ( 1 ∗ X ) ( R 1 ) ( R 1 ) ( X ∗ 1 ) + ( 1 ∗ X )

  2. Symbolic Differentiation ▸ Rewrite rules: D X ( X ) → 1 ( R 1 ) D X ( Y ) → 0 ( R 2 ) D X ( u + v ) → D X ( u ) + D X ( v ) ( R 3 ) D X ( u ∗ v ) → ( u ∗ D X ( v )) + ( D X ( u ) ∗ v ) ( R 3 ) ▸ Differentiate D X ( X ∗ X ) : D X ( X ∗ X ) ( R 4 ) ( X ∗ D X ( X ))) + ( D X ( X ) ∗ X ) ( R 1 ) ( R 1 ) ( X ∗ 1 ) + ( D X ( X ) ∗ X ) ( X ∗ D X ( X )) + ( 1 ∗ X ) ( R 1 ) ( R 1 ) ( X ∗ 1 ) + ( 1 ∗ X )

  3. Properties of Term Rewriting Systems The symbolic differentiation example can be used to illustrate two most important properties of TRSs:

  4. Properties of Term Rewriting Systems The symbolic differentiation example can be used to illustrate two most important properties of TRSs: 1. Termination: ▸ Is it always the case that after finitely many rule applications we reach an expression to which no more rules apply (normal form)? ▸ For symbolic differentiation rules this is the case. ▸ But how to prove it? ▸ An example of non-terminating rule: u + v → v + u

  5. Properties of Term Rewriting Systems The symbolic differentiation example can be used to illustrate two most important properties of TRSs:

  6. Properties of Term Rewriting Systems The symbolic differentiation example can be used to illustrate two most important properties of TRSs: 2. Confluence: ▸ If there are different ways of applying rules to a given term t , leading to different terms t 1 and t 2 , can they be reduced by rule applications to a common term? ▸ For symbolic differentiation rules this is the case. ▸ But how to prove it?

  7. Properties of Term Rewriting Systems ▸ Adding the rule u + 0 → u ( R 5 ) destroys confluence: D X ( X + 0 ) ( R 5 ) ( R 3 ) D X ( X ) D X ( X ) + D X ( 0 ) ( R 1 ) ( R 1 ) 1 + D X ( 0 ) 1 ▸ Confluence can be regained by adding D X ( 0 ) → 0 (completion).

  8. Group Theory ▸ Terms are built over variables and the following function symbols: ▸ binary ○ , ▸ unary i , ▸ constant 0 . ▸ Examples of terms: ▸ x ○ ( y ○ i ( y )) ▸ ( 0 ○ x ) ○ i ( 0 ) ▸ i ( x ○ y ) ▸ Identities (aka group axioms), defining groups: Associativity of ○ ( x ○ y ) ○ z ≈ x ○ ( y ○ z ) ( G 1 ) e ○ x ≈ x ( G 2 ) e left unit i left inverse i ( x ) ○ x ≈ e ( G 3 )

  9. Group Theory ▸ Identities can be applied in both directions. ▸ Word problem for identities: ▸ Given a set of identities E and two terms s and t . ▸ Is it possible to transform s into t , using the identities in E as rewrite rules applied in both directions? ▸ For instance, is it possible to transform e into x ○ i ( x ) , i.e., is the left inverse also a right-inverse?

  10. Group Theory ( x ○ y ) ○ z ≈ x ○ ( y ○ z ) ( G 1 ) e ○ x ≈ x ( G 2 ) i ( x ) ○ x ≈ e ( G 3 ) Transform e into x ○ i ( x ) : e ≈ G 3 i ( x ○ i ( x )) ○ ( x ○ i ( x )) ≈ G 2 i ( x ○ i ( x )) ○ ( x ○ ( e ○ i ( x ))) ≈ G 3 i ( x ○ i ( x )) ○ ( x ○ (( i ( x ) ○ x ) ○ i ( x ))) ≈ G 1 i ( x ○ i ( x )) ○ (( x ○ ( i ( x ) ○ x )) ○ i ( x )) ≈ G 1 i ( x ○ i ( x )) ○ ((( x ○ i ( x )) ○ x ) ○ i ( x )) ≈ G 1 i ( x ○ i ( x )) ○ (( x ○ i ( x )) ○ ( x ○ i ( x ))) ≈ G 1 ( i ( x ○ i ( x )) ○ ( x ○ i ( x ))) ○ ( x ○ i ( x )) ≈ G 3 e ○ ( x ○ i ( x )) ≈ G 3 x ○ i ( x )

  11. Solving Word Problems by Rewriting? ▸ Is there a simpler way to solve word problems? ▸ Try to solve it by rewriting (uni-directional application of identities): s t ∗ ∗ ˆ s ˆ t = ▸ Reduce s and t to normal forms ˆ s and ˆ t . ▸ Check whether ˆ s = ˆ t , i.e., syntactically equal. ( = is the meta-equality.)

  12. Solving Word Problems by Rewriting? ▸ Is there a simpler way to solve word problems? ▸ Try to solve it by rewriting (uni-directional application of identities): s t ∗ ∗ ˆ s ˆ t = ▸ Reduce s and t to normal forms ˆ s and ˆ t . ▸ Check whether ˆ s = ˆ t , i.e., syntactically equal. ( = is the meta-equality.) ▸ But... it would only work if normal forms exist and are unique.

  13. Solving Word Problems by Rewriting? ▸ In the group theory example, e and x ○ i ( x ) are equivalent, but it can not be decided by (left-to-right) rewriting: Both terms are in the normal form. ▸ Uniqueness of normal forms is violated: non-confluence. ▸ Normal forms may not exist: The process of reducing a term may lead to an infinite chain of transformations: non-termination.

  14. Solving Word Problems by Rewriting? ▸ In the group theory example, e and x ○ i ( x ) are equivalent, but it can not be decided by (left-to-right) rewriting: Both terms are in the normal form. ▸ Uniqueness of normal forms is violated: non-confluence. ▸ Normal forms may not exist: The process of reducing a term may lead to an infinite chain of transformations: non-termination. ▸ Termination and confluence ensure existence and uniqueness of normal forms.

  15. Solving Word Problems by Rewriting? ▸ In the group theory example, e and x ○ i ( x ) are equivalent, but it can not be decided by (left-to-right) rewriting: Both terms are in the normal form. ▸ Uniqueness of normal forms is violated: non-confluence. ▸ Normal forms may not exist: The process of reducing a term may lead to an infinite chain of transformations: non-termination. ▸ Termination and confluence ensure existence and uniqueness of normal forms. ▸ If a given set of identities leads to non-confluent system, we will try to apply the idea of completion to extend the rewrite system to a confluent one.

  16. Motivation Abstract Reduction Systems

  17. Abstract vs Concrete Concrete rewrite formalisms: ▸ string rewriting ▸ term rewriting ▸ graph rewriting ▸ λ calculus ▸ etc. Abstract reduction: ▸ No structure on objects to be rewritten. ▸ Abstract treatment of reductions.

  18. Abstract Reduction Systems ▸ Abstract reduction system (ARS): A pair ( A, →) , where ▸ A is a set, ▸ the reduction → is a binary relation on A : → ⊆ A × A . ▸ Write a → b for ( a,b ) ∈→ .

  19. Abstract Reduction System: Example ▸ A = { a,b,c,d,e,f,g } ▸ → = { ( a,e ) , ( b,a ) , ( b,c ) , ( c,d ) , ( c,f ) } ( e,b ) , ( e,g ) , ( f,e ) , ( f,g ) a c b d e f g

  20. Equivalence and Reduction Again, two views at reductions. 1. Directed computation: Follow the reductions, trying to compute a normal form: a 0 → a 1 → ⋯ ∗ 2. View → as description of ← → . ∗ ▸ a ← → b means there is a path between a and b , with arrows traversed in both directions: a ← c → d ← b ∗ ▸ Goal: Decide whether a ← → b . ▸ Bidirectional rewriting is expensive. ▸ Unidirectional rewriting with subsequent comparison of normal form works if the reduction system is confluent and terminating. Termination, confluence: central topics.

  21. Basic notions 1. Composition of two relations. 2. Given two relations R ⊆ A × B and S ⊆ B × C , their composition is defined by R ○ S ∶= {( x,z ) ∣ ∃ y ∈ B. ( x,y ) ∈ R ∧ ( y,z ) ∈ S }

  22. Abstract Reduction System: Example a c b d e f g

  23. Abstract Reduction System: Example a c b d e f g ▸ Finite rewrite sequence: a → e → b → c → f

  24. Abstract Reduction System: Example a c b d e f g ▸ Finite rewrite sequence: a → e → b → c → f ▸ Empty rewrite sequence: a

  25. Abstract Reduction System: Example a c b b d e f g ▸ Finite rewrite sequence: a → e → b → c → f ▸ Empty rewrite sequence: a ▸ Infinite rewrite sequence: a → e → b → a → ⋯

  26. Relations Derived from → � → ∶= {( x,x ) ∣ x ∈ A } 0 identity → ∶= → ○ → ( i + 1 ) -fold composition, i ≥ 0 i + 1 i � � � → ∶= ∪ i > 0 + i � � → transitive closure → ∶= → ∪ ∗ + 0 � � � → reflexive transitive closure → ∶= → ∪ = 0 � � → reflexive closure → ∶= {( y,x ) ∣ ( x,y ) ∈ → } − 1 � inverse ← ∶= − 1 � → inverse ↔ ∶= → ∪ ← symmetric closure → ∶= ( ↔ ) + + ← transitive symmetric closure → ∶= ( ↔ ) ∗ ∗ ← reflexive transitive symmetric closure

  27. Terminology � ∗ ▸ If x → y then we say: ▸ x rewrites to y , or ▸ there is some finite path from x to y , or ▸ y is a reduct of x .

  28. Terminology � ∗ ▸ If x → y then we say: ▸ x rewrites to y , or ▸ there is some finite path from x to y , or ▸ y is a reduct of x . a c b d e f g

  29. Terminology � ∗ ▸ If x → y then we say: ▸ x rewrites to y , or ▸ there is some finite path from x to y , or ▸ y is a reduct of x . a c b d ∗ e f a � → f g

  30. Terminology ▸ x is reducible iff there exists y such that x → y .

  31. Terminology ▸ x is reducible iff there exists y such that x → y . ▸ x is in normal form (irreducible) iff x is not reducible.

  32. Terminology ▸ x is reducible iff there exists y such that x → y . ▸ x is in normal form (irreducible) iff x is not reducible. ∗ ▸ y is a normal form of x iff x � → y and y is in normal form.

  33. Terminology ▸ x is reducible iff there exists y such that x → y . ▸ x is in normal form (irreducible) iff x is not reducible. ∗ ▸ y is a normal form of x iff x � → y and y is in normal form. ! ▸ We write x � → y if y is a normal form of x . ▸ If x has a unique normal form, it is denoted by x ↓ .

  34. Terminology ▸ x is reducible iff there exists y such that x → y . ▸ x is in normal form (irreducible) iff x is not reducible. ∗ ▸ y is a normal form of x iff x � → y and y is in normal form. ! ▸ We write x � → y if y is a normal form of x . ▸ If x has a unique normal form, it is denoted by x ↓ . a c b d e f a,b,c,e,f are reducible g

  35. Terminology ▸ x is reducible iff there exists y such that x → y . ▸ x is in normal form (irreducible) iff x is not reducible. ∗ ▸ y is a normal form of x iff x � → y and y is in normal form. ! ▸ We write x � → y if y is a normal form of x . ▸ If x has a unique normal form, it is denoted by x ↓ . a c b d e f d,g are in a normal form g

  36. Terminology ▸ x is reducible iff there exists y such that x → y . ▸ x is in normal form (irreducible) iff x is not reducible. ∗ ▸ y is a normal form of x iff x � → y and y is in normal form. ! ▸ We write x � → y if y is a normal form of x . ▸ If x has a unique normal form, it is denoted by x ↓ . a c b d ! b � → d ! e f � → g b ! g � → g g

  37. Terminology ▸ y is direct successor of x iff x → y .

  38. Terminology ▸ y is direct successor of x iff x → y . + ▸ y is successor of x iff x � → y .

  39. Terminology ▸ y is direct successor of x iff x → y . + ▸ y is successor of x iff x � → y . ∗ ▸ x and y are convertible iff x ← → y .

  40. Terminology ▸ y is direct successor of x iff x → y . + ▸ y is successor of x iff x � → y . ∗ ▸ x and y are convertible iff x ← → y . ∗ ∗ ▸ x and y are joinable iff there exists z such that x � → z ← � y .

  41. Terminology ▸ y is direct successor of x iff x → y . + ▸ y is successor of x iff x � → y . ∗ ▸ x and y are convertible iff x ← → y . ∗ ∗ ▸ x and y are joinable iff there exists z such that x � → z ← � y . ▸ We write x ↓ y iff x and y are joinable.

  42. Terminology ▸ y is direct successor of x iff x → y . + ▸ y is successor of x iff x � → y . ∗ ▸ x and y are convertible iff x ← → y . ∗ ∗ ▸ x and y are joinable iff there exists z such that x � → z ← � y . ▸ We write x ↓ y iff x and y are joinable. a c b d e e ↓ f , f ↓ d , a ↓ f , not g ↓ d f g

  43. Terminology ▸ y is direct successor of x iff x → y . + ▸ y is successor of x iff x � → y . ∗ ▸ x and y are convertible iff x ← → y . ∗ ∗ ▸ x and y are joinable iff there exists z such that x � → z ← � y . ▸ We write x ↓ y iff x and y are joinable. a c b d ∗ e f ← → d g g

  44. Central Notions Definition 1.1 A reduction → is called Church-Rosser (CR) iff ∗ x ← → y implies x ↓ y.

  45. Central Notions Definition 1.1 A reduction → is called Church-Rosser (CR) iff ∗ x ← → y implies x ↓ y. Graphically: ∗ y x ∗ ∗ z Solid arrows represent universal and dashed arrows existential quantification: ∀ x,y. x → y ⇒ ∃ z. x → z ∧ y ∗ ∗ ∗ ← � � → z.

  46. Central Notions Definition 1.2 A reduction → is called confluent (C) iff ∗ ∗ ← � x � → y 2 implies y 1 ↓ y 2 . y 1

  47. Central Notions Definition 1.2 A reduction → is called confluent (C) iff ∗ ∗ ← � x � → y 2 implies y 1 ↓ y 2 . y 1 Graphically: ∗ y 1 x ∗ ∗ y 2 ∗ z Solid arrows represent universal and dashed arrows existential quantification: ∀ x,y 1 ,y 2 . y 1 → y 2 ⇒ ∃ z. y 1 ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ ← � x � � → z ← � y 2 .

  48. Central Notions Definition 1.3 A reduction → is called locally confluent (LC) iff y 1 ← x → y 2 implies y 1 ↓ y 2 .

  49. Central Notions Definition 1.3 A reduction → is called locally confluent (LC) iff y 1 ← x → y 2 implies y 1 ↓ y 2 . Graphically: y 1 x ∗ y 2 ∗ z Solid arrows represent universal and dashed arrows existential quantification: ∀ x,y 1 ,y 2 . y 1 ← x → y 2 ⇒ ∃ z. y 1 ∗ ∗ � → z ← � y 2 .

  50. Central Notions Definition 1.4 A reduction → is called ▸ terminating (T) iff there is no infinite descending chain a 0 → a 1 → ⋯ . ▸ normalizing (N) iff every element has a normal form. ▸ uniquely normalizing (UN) iff every element has at most one normal form. ▸ convergent iff it is both confluent and terminating.

  51. Central Notions Definition 1.4 A reduction → is called ▸ terminating (T) iff there is no infinite descending chain a 0 → a 1 → ⋯ . ▸ normalizing (N) iff every element has a normal form. ▸ uniquely normalizing (UN) iff every element has at most one normal form. ▸ convergent iff it is both confluent and terminating. Alternative terminology: ▸ Strongly normalizing: terminating. ▸ Weakly normalizing: normalizing.

  52. Central Notions ▸ Obviously, x ↓ y implies x ∗ ← → y . ▸ Therefore, the Church-Rosser property can be formulated as the equivalence: ▸ → is called Church-Rosser iff ∗ ← → y iff x ↓ y. x

  53. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N

  54. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � 2. T N

  55. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b

  56. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ←

  57. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ← � ⇒ 4. CR UN

  58. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ← � ⇒ 4. CR UN / 5. CR ⇐ � UN

  59. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ← � ⇒ 4. CR UN / a c 5. CR ⇐ � UN b

  60. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ← � ⇒ 4. CR UN / a c 5. CR ⇐ � UN b N ∧ UN � ⇒ 6. C

  61. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ← � ⇒ 4. CR UN / a c 5. CR ⇐ � UN b N ∧ UN � ⇒ 6. C � ⇒ 7. C LC

  62. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ← � ⇒ 4. CR UN / a c 5. CR ⇐ � UN b N ∧ UN � ⇒ 6. C � ⇒ 7. C LC / 8. C ⇐ � LC

  63. Properties � ⇒ 1. T N ⇐ / � a 2. T N b → = ↓ ⇐ ⇒ ∗ 3. CR ← � ⇒ 4. CR UN / a c 5. CR ⇐ � UN b N ∧ UN � ⇒ 6. C � ⇒ 7. C LC / 8. a c C ⇐ � LC b d

  64. Properties ▸ Recall we were looking for: ▸ Ability to check equivalence by the search of a common reduct. ▸ This is exactly the Church-Rosser property. ▸ How does it relate to confluence and termination?

  65. Church-Rosser and Confluence ▸ The Church-Rosser property and confluence coincide. ▸ CR � ⇒ C is immediate. ▸ CR ⇐ � C has a nice diagrammatic proof:

  66. Church-Rosser and Confluence Definition 1.5 A reduction → is called semi-confluent (SC) iff ∗ y 1 ← x � → y 2 implies y 1 ↓ y 2 .

  67. Church-Rosser and Confluence Definition 1.5 A reduction → is called semi-confluent (SC) iff ∗ y 1 ← x � → y 2 implies y 1 ↓ y 2 . Graphically: y 1 x ∗ ∗ y 2 ∗ z Solid arrows represent universal and dashed arrows existential quantification: ∀ x,y 1 ,y 2 . y 1 ← x → y 2 ⇒ ∃ z. y 1 ∗ ∗ ∗ � � → z ← � y 2 .

  68. Church-Rosser, Confluence, and Semi-Confluence Theorem 1.1 The following conditions are equivalent: 1. → has the Chursh-Rosser property. 2. → is confluent. 3. → is semi-confluent.

  69. Church-Rosser, Confluence, and Semi-Confluence Theorem 1.1 The following conditions are equivalent: 1. → has the Chursh-Rosser property. 2. → is confluent. 3. → is semi-confluent. Proof. ( 1 ⇒ 2 )

  70. Church-Rosser, Confluence, and Semi-Confluence Theorem 1.1 The following conditions are equivalent: 1. → has the Chursh-Rosser property. 2. → is confluent. 3. → is semi-confluent. Proof. ( 1 ⇒ 2 ) ∗ ∗ ▸ Assume → is CR and y 1 ← � x � → y 2 . Show y 1 ↓ y 2 .

  71. Church-Rosser, Confluence, and Semi-Confluence Theorem 1.1 The following conditions are equivalent: 1. → has the Chursh-Rosser property. 2. → is confluent. 3. → is semi-confluent. Proof. ( 1 ⇒ 2 ) ∗ ∗ ▸ Assume → is CR and y 1 ← � x � → y 2 . Show y 1 ↓ y 2 . ∗ ∗ ∗ ▸ y 1 ← � x � → y 2 implies y 1 ← → y 2 .

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend