quantum statistical comparison and majorization
play

Quantum Statistical Comparison and Majorization (and their - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Quantum Statistical Comparison and Majorization (and their applications to generalized resource theories) Francesco Buscemi (Nagoya University) Quantum Foundations Seminar Series, Perimeter Institute 26 February 2019 Guiding idea: generalized


  1. Quantum Statistical Comparison and Majorization (and their applications to generalized resource theories) Francesco Buscemi (Nagoya University) Quantum Foundations Seminar Series, Perimeter Institute 26 February 2019

  2. Guiding idea: generalized resource theories as order theories for stochastic (probabilistic) structures 0/31

  3. The Precursor: Majorization

  4. Lorenz Curves and Majorization Lorenz curve for probability distribution • two probability distributions, p = ( p 1 , . . . , p n ) p = ( p 1 , · · · , p n ) : and q = ( q 1 , . . . , q n ) i =1 p ↓ • truncated sums P ( k ) = � k i and i =1 q ↓ Q ( k ) = � k i , for all k = 1 , . . . , n • p majorizes q , i.e., p � q , whenever P ( k ) ≥ Q ( k ) , for all k • minimal element: uniform distribution e = n − 1 (1 , 1 , · · · , 1) Hardy, Littlewood, and P´ olya (1929) ( x k , y k ) = ( k/n, P ( k )) , 1 ≤ k ≤ n p � q ⇐ ⇒ q = M p , for some bistochastic matrix M . 1/31

  5. Blackwell’s Extensions

  6. Statistical Decision Problems experiment decision Θ − → X − → U � � � − → − → θ x u w ( x | θ ) d ( u | x ) payoff is ℓ ( θ, u ) ∈ R Definition A statistical model (or experiment ) is a triple w = � Θ , X , w � , a statistical decision problem (or game ) is a triple g = � Θ , U , ℓ � . 2/31

  7. Playing Games with Experiments experiment decision Θ − → X − → U • the experiment (model) is given , i.e., it is the “resource” � � � • the decision instead can be optimized θ − → x − → u w ( x | θ ) d ( u | x ) Definition The expected payoff of a statistical model w = � Θ , X , w � w.r.t. a decision problem g = � Θ , U , ℓ � is given by ℓ ( θ, u ) d ( u | x ) w ( x | θ ) | Θ | − 1 . � def E g [ w ] = max d ( u | x ) u,x,θ 3/31

  8. Comparing Statistical Models 1/2 Second model: w ′ = � Θ , Y , w ′ ( y | θ ) � First model: w = � Θ , X , w ( x | θ ) � experiment experiment decision decision − → X − → U − → Y − → U Θ Θ � � � � � � − → − → − → − → θ x u θ x u w ( x | θ ) d ( u | x ) w ′ ( y | θ ) d ′ ( u | y ) For a fixed decision problem g = � Θ , U , ℓ � , the expected payoffs E g [ w ] and E g [ w ′ ] can always be ordered. 4/31

  9. Comparing Statistical Models 2/2 Definition (Information Preorder) If the model w = � Θ , X , w � is better than model w ′ = � Θ , Y , w ′ � for all decision problems g = � Θ , U , ℓ � , then we say that w is more informative than w ′ , and write w � w ′ . Problem. Can we visualize the information morphism � more concretely? 5/31

  10. Information Morphism = Statistical Sufficiency Blackwell-Sherman-Stein Theorem (1948-1953) Given two experiments with the same parameter space, w = � Θ , X , w � and w ′ = � Θ , Y , w ′ � , the condition w � w ′ holds iff there exists a conditional probability ϕ ( y | x ) such that w ′ ( y | θ ) = � x ϕ ( y | x ) w ( x | θ ) . noise Θ − → Y Θ − → X − → Y � � = � � � − → − → − → θ y θ x y David H. Blackwell (1919-2010) w ′ ( y | θ ) w ( x | θ ) ϕ ( y | x ) 6/31

  11. Special Case: Dichotomies • two pairs of probability distributions, i.e., two dichotomies , ( p 1 , p 2 ) and ( q 1 , q 2 ) , of dimension m and n , respectively 2 and q j 1 /q j • relabel entries such that ratios p i 1 /p i 2 are nonincreasing • construct the truncated sums P 1 , 2 ( k ) = � k i =1 p i 1 , 2 and Q 1 , 2 ( k ) • ( p 1 , p 2 ) � ( q 1 , q 2 ) iff the relative Lorenz curve of the former is never below that of the latter Relative Lorenz curves: Blackwell’s Theorem for Dichotomies (1953) ( x k , y k ) = ( P 2 ( k ) , P 1 ( k )) ( p 1 , p 2 ) � ( q 1 , q 2 ) ⇐ ⇒ q i = M p i , for some stochastic 7/31 matrix M .

  12. The Viewpoint of Communication Theory

  13. Statistics vs Information Theory • Statistical models are mathematically equivalent to noisy channels: • However: while in statistics the input is inaccessible (Nature does not bother with coding!) • in communication theory a sender does code ! 8/31

  14. From Decision Problems to Decoding Problems Definition (Decoding Problems) Given a channel w = �X , Y , w ( y | x ) � , a decoding problem is defined by an encoding e = �M , X , e ( x | m ) � and the payoff function is the optimum guessing probability: d ( m | y ) w ( y | x ) e ( x | m ) |M| − 1 = 2 − H min ( M | Y ) � def E e [ w ] = max d ( m | y ) m,x,y

  15. Comparison of Classical Noisy Channels Consider two discrete noisy channels w and w ′ with the same input alphabet Theorem Given the following pre-orders 1. degradability: there exists ϕ ( z | y ) : w ′ ( x | z ) = � y ϕ ( z | y ) w ( y | x ) 2. noisiness: for all encodings e = �M , X , e ( x | m ) � , H ( M | Y ) ≤ H ( M | Z ) 3. ambiguity: for all encodings e = �M , X , e ( x | m ) � , H min ( M | Y ) ≤ H min ( M | Z ) ⇒ (2) (data-processing inequality), (2) � ⇒ (1) (K¨ we have: (1) = = orner and Marton, 1977), but (1) ⇐ ⇒ (3) (FB, 2016).

  16. Some Classical Channel Morphisms Output degrading: Input degrading: Full coding (Shannon’s “channel inclusion”, 1958): 11/31

  17. Extensions to the Quantum Case

  18. Some Quantum Channel Morphisms Output degrading: Input degrading: Quantum coding with forward CC: 12/31

  19. Output Degradability

  20. Comparison of Quantum Statistical Models 1/2 Quantum statistical models as cq-channels: Formulation below from: A.S. Holevo, Statistical Decision Theory for Quantum Systems , 1973. classical case quantum case • decision problems g = � Θ , U , ℓ � • decision problems g = � Θ , U , ℓ � � Θ , H S , { ρ θ � • experiments w = � Θ , X , { w ( x | θ ) }� • quantum experiments E = S } • POVMs { P u • decisions d ( u | x ) S : u ∈ U} x d ( u | x ) w ( x | θ ) | Θ | − 1 � ρ θ S P u � | Θ | − 1 • p c ( u, θ ) = � • p q ( u, θ ) = Tr S � � • E g [ w ] = max ℓ ( θ, u ) p c ( u, θ ) • E g [ E ] = max ℓ ( θ, u ) p q ( u, θ ) { P u d ( u | x ) S }

  21. Comparison of Quantum Statistical Models 2/2 What follows is from: FB, Comm. Math. Phys., 2012 � Θ , H S , { ρ θ � • consider two quantum statistical models E = S } and E ′ = � Θ , H S ′ , { σ θ � S ′ } • information ordering : E � E ′ iff E g [ E ] ≥ E g [ E ′ ] for all g • E � E ′ iff there exists a quantum statistical morphism (essentially, a PTP map) M : L ( H S ) → L ( H S ′ ) such that M ( ρ θ S ) = σ θ S ′ for all θ • complete information ordering : E � c E ′ iff E ⊗ F � E ′ ⊗ F for all ancillary models F (in fact, one informationally complete model suffices) • E � c E ′ iff there exists a CPTP map N : L ( H S ) → L ( H S ′ ) such that N ( ρ θ S ) = σ θ S ′ for all θ • if E ′ is abelian , then E � c E ′ iff E � E ′ 14/31

  22. Comparison of Quantum Channels 1/2 Definition (Quantum Decoding Problems) Given a quantum channel N : A → B , a quantum decoding problem is defined by a bipartite state ω RA and the payoff function is the optimum singlet fraction: def D � Φ + R ◦ N A → B )( ω RA ) | Φ + E ω [ N ] R | ( id R ⊗ D B → ¯ R � = max R ¯ R ¯

  23. Comparison of Quantum Channels 2/2 Theorem (FB, 2016) Given two quantum channels N : A → B and N ′ : A → B ′ , the following are equivalent: 1. output degradability : there exists CPTP map C : N ′ = C ◦ N ; 2. coherence preorder : for any bipartite state ω RA , E ω [ N ] ≥ E ω [ N ′ ] , that is, H min ( R | B ) ( id ⊗N )( ω ) ≤ H min ( R | B ′ ) ( id ⊗N ′ )( ω ) . � applications to the theory of open quantum systems dynamics and, by adding symmetry constraints, to quantum thermodynamics 16/31

  24. Application 1: Open Quantum Systems Dynamics

  25. Discrete-Time Stochastic Processes • Let x i , for i = 0 , 1 , . . . , index the state of a system at time t = t i • if the system can be initialized at time t = t 0 , the process is fully described by the conditional distribution p ( x N , . . . , x 1 | x 0 ) • if the system evolving is quantum, we only have a � � N ( i ) quantum dynamical mapping Q 0 → Q i i =1 ,...,N • the process is divisible if there exist channels D ( i ) such that N ( i +1) = D ( i ) ◦ N ( i ) for all i • problem: to provide a fully information-theoretic characterization of divisibility 17/31

  26. Divisibility as “Quantum Information Flow” Theorem (2016-2018) Given an initial open quantum system Q 0 , a quantum dynamical mapping � � N ( i ) i ≥ 1 is divisibile if and only if, for any initial state ω RQ 0 , Q 0 → Q i H min ( R | Q 1 ) ≤ H min ( R | Q 2 ) ≤ · · · ≤ H min ( R | Q N ) . 18/31

  27. Application 2: Quantum Thermodynamics

  28. Resource Theory of Athermality and Asymmetry From [FB, arXiv:1505.00535], [FB and Gour, Phys. Rev. A 95, 012110 (2017)], and [Gour, Jennings, FB, Duan, and Marvian, Nat. Comm. 9, 5352 (2018)] • idea: to characterize thermal accessibility ρ → σ by comparing the dichotomies ( ρ, γ ) and ( σ, γ ) , for γ thermal state • classically, Blackwell’s theorem implies the thermomajorization relation • in the quantum case, in order to account for coherence, symmetry constraints can also be added to the Gibbs-preserving map 19/31

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend