quantifjcational subordination as anaphora to a function
play

Quantifjcational subordination as anaphora to a function Matthew - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Quantifjcational subordination as anaphora to a function Matthew Gotham University of Oxford 24th Conference on Formal Grammar, University of Latvia 11 August 2019 1/38 Outline Background Outline of the proposal Examples Refset anaphora


  1. Quantifjcational subordination as anaphora to a function Matthew Gotham University of Oxford 24th Conference on Formal Grammar, University of Latvia 11 August 2019 1/38

  2. Outline Background Outline of the proposal Examples Refset anaphora Telescoping Discussion Comparison with TTS Conclusion 2/38

  3. Outline Background Outline of the proposal Examples Refset anaphora Telescoping Discussion Comparison with TTS Conclusion 2/38

  4. Outline Background Outline of the proposal Examples Refset anaphora Telescoping Discussion Comparison with TTS Conclusion 2/38

  5. Outline Background Outline of the proposal Examples Refset anaphora Telescoping Discussion Comparison with TTS Conclusion 2/38

  6. Background

  7. Quantifjcational subordination (QS) (1) If you give every child a present, some child will open it. (Ranta 1994) (2) Every student bought a book. Most of them read it. (3) Every player chooses a pawn. He puts it on square one. (Groenendijk & Stokhof 1991) Examples like (3) are often called ‘telescoping’. 3/38

  8. Pronouns inaccessible in fjrst-generation dynamic semantics E.g. DRT: If you give every child a present, some child will open it. x child x y present y you give x y z u child z z opens u u=? 4/38 ⇒ ⇒

  9. Pronouns inaccessible in fjrst-generation dynamic semantics Every player chooses a pawn. He puts it on square one. z u x player x y pawn y x chooses y z puts u on square one z=? u=? 5/38 ⇒

  10. Second-generation dynamic semantics h dependency, though. • It’s quite a complex and roudabout way to get to that the necessary dependency between pawns and players. H h y is a pawn chosen by h x . H therefore encodes h H is the set of players, and for every • I.e., h x 6/38 Via a generalization to using sets of assignments: � every x player chooses a y pawn � = � � F , H � | ∃ G : ( ∀ f ∈ F : ∃ g ∈ G : f ≈ x g & ∀ g ∈ G : ∃ f ∈ F : f ≈ x g ) & { g ( x ) | g ∈ G } = � player � & ( ∀ g ∈ G : ∃ h : g ≈ y h & h ( y ) ∈ � pawn � & � h ( x ) , h ( y ) � ∈ � choose � ) � & H = { h | ∃ g ∈ G : g ≈ y h & h ( y ) ∈ � pawn � & � h ( x ) , h ( y ) � ∈ � choose � }

  11. Second-generation dynamic semantics Via a generalization to using sets of assignments: the necessary dependency between pawns and players. • It’s quite a complex and roudabout way to get to that dependency, though. 6/38 � every x player chooses a y pawn � = � � F , H � | ∃ G : ( ∀ f ∈ F : ∃ g ∈ G : f ≈ x g & ∀ g ∈ G : ∃ f ∈ F : f ≈ x g ) & { g ( x ) | g ∈ G } = � player � & ( ∀ g ∈ G : ∃ h : g ≈ y h & h ( y ) ∈ � pawn � & � h ( x ) , h ( y ) � ∈ � choose � ) � & H = { h | ∃ g ∈ G : g ≈ y h & h ( y ) ∈ � pawn � & � h ( x ) , h ( y ) � ∈ � choose � } • I.e., { h ( x ) | h ∈ H } is the set of players, and for every h ∈ H , h ( y ) is a pawn chosen by h ( x ) . H therefore encodes

  12. Second-generation dynamic semantics Via a generalization to using sets of assignments: the necessary dependency between pawns and players. • It’s quite a complex and roudabout way to get to that dependency, though. 6/38 � every x player chooses a y pawn � = � � F , H � | ∃ G : ( ∀ f ∈ F : ∃ g ∈ G : f ≈ x g & ∀ g ∈ G : ∃ f ∈ F : f ≈ x g ) & { g ( x ) | g ∈ G } = � player � & ( ∀ g ∈ G : ∃ h : g ≈ y h & h ( y ) ∈ � pawn � & � h ( x ) , h ( y ) � ∈ � choose � ) � & H = { h | ∃ g ∈ G : g ≈ y h & h ( y ) ∈ � pawn � & � h ( x ) , h ( y ) � ∈ � choose � } • I.e., { h ( x ) | h ∈ H } is the set of players, and for every h ∈ H , h ( y ) is a pawn chosen by h ( x ) . H therefore encodes

  13. 1 v 1 u 1 w 1 f w Type-theoretical semantics (TTS) suggests an answer x 1 open e child z z w give you e present y y v e child x u • Propositions-as-types principle f (1) If you give every child a present, some child will open it. B a x A , f a for any a A B —the type of functions with domain A such that, x • B a x b A and A B —the type of ordered pairs a b , where a x • 7/38

  14. 1 v 1 u 1 w 1 f w Type-theoretical semantics (TTS) suggests an answer x 1 open e child z z w give you e present y y v e child x u • Propositions-as-types principle f (1) If you give every child a present, some child will open it. B a x A , f a for any a A B —the type of functions with domain A such that, x • B a x b A and A B —the type of ordered pairs a b , where a x • 7/38

  15. 1 v 1 u 1 w 1 f w Type-theoretical semantics (TTS) suggests an answer v 1 open e child z z w give you e present y y e child x • Propositions-as-types principle x u f (1) If you give every child a present, some child will open it. B a x A , f a for any a A B —the type of functions with domain A such that, x • 7/38 • (Σ x : A ) B —the type of ordered pairs � a , b � , where a : A and b : B [ a / x ]

  16. 1 v 1 u 1 w 1 f w Type-theoretical semantics (TTS) suggests an answer e present y 1 open e child z z w give you y • Propositions-as-types principle v e child x x u f (1) If you give every child a present, some child will open it. 7/38 • (Σ x : A ) B —the type of ordered pairs � a , b � , where a : A and b : B [ a / x ] • (Π x : A ) B —the type of functions with domain A such that, for any a : A , f ( a ) : B [ a / x ]

  17. Type-theoretical semantics (TTS) suggests an answer • Propositions-as-types principle (1) If you give every child a present, some child will open it. 7/38 • (Σ x : A ) B —the type of ordered pairs � a , b � , where a : A and b : B [ a / x ] • (Π x : A ) B —the type of functions with domain A such that, for any a : A , f ( a ) : B [ a / x ] � � � Π f : Π u : (Σ x : e ) child ( x ) � (Σ v : (Σ y : e ) present ( y )) give ( you ′ , π 1 ( v ) , π 1 ( u )) (Σ w : (Σ z : e ) child ( z )) open ( π 1 ( w ) , π 1 ( π 1 ( f ( w ))))

  18. Using the function every child to a present you give him/her. the function is overtly present in the second sentence. • BUT it is actually crucial that an appropriate argument to makes this kind of dependency possible. • The fact that the fjrst sentence expresses a function open f z . a child z and a proof that you • some child will open it a function f mapping • you give every child a present 8/38 � � � Π f : Π u : (Σ x : e ) child ( x ) � (Σ v : (Σ y : e ) present ( y )) give ( you ′ , π 1 ( v ) , π 1 ( u )) (Σ w : (Σ z : e ) child ( z )) open ( π 1 ( w ) , π 1 ( π 1 ( f ( w ))))

  19. Using the function every child to a present you give him/her. the function is overtly present in the second sentence. • BUT it is actually crucial that an appropriate argument to makes this kind of dependency possible. • The fact that the fjrst sentence expresses a function 8/38 � � � Π f : Π u : (Σ x : e ) child ( x ) � (Σ v : (Σ y : e ) present ( y )) give ( you ′ , π 1 ( v ) , π 1 ( u )) (Σ w : (Σ z : e ) child ( z )) open ( π 1 ( w ) , π 1 ( π 1 ( f ( w )))) • you give every child a present � a function f mapping • some child will open it � a child z and a proof that you open f ( z ) .

  20. Using the function every child to a present you give him/her. the function is overtly present in the second sentence. • BUT it is actually crucial that an appropriate argument to makes this kind of dependency possible. • The fact that the fjrst sentence expresses a function 8/38 � � � Π f : Π u : (Σ x : e ) child ( x ) � (Σ v : (Σ y : e ) present ( y )) give ( you ′ , π 1 ( v ) , π 1 ( u )) (Σ w : (Σ z : e ) child ( z )) open ( π 1 ( w ) , π 1 ( π 1 ( f ( w )))) • you give every child a present � a function f mapping • some child will open it � a child z and a proof that you open f ( z ) .

  21. Using the function every child to a present you give him/her. the function is overtly present in the second sentence. • BUT it is actually crucial that an appropriate argument to makes this kind of dependency possible. • The fact that the fjrst sentence expresses a function 8/38 � � � Π f : Π u : (Σ x : e ) child ( x ) � (Σ v : (Σ y : e ) present ( y )) give ( you ′ , π 1 ( v ) , π 1 ( u )) (Σ w : (Σ z : e ) child ( z )) open ( π 1 ( w ) , π 1 ( π 1 ( f ( w )))) • you give every child a present � a function f mapping • some child will open it � a child z and a proof that you open f ( z ) .

  22. Limitations (3) Every player chooses a pawn. He puts it on square one. Ranta (1994: 73): the only way to interpret the text […] is by treating the pronoun ‘he’ as an abbreviation of ‘every player’ Obviously, this ‘abbreviation’ strategy is unsatisfactory. (2) Every student bought a book. Most of them read it. No mechanism for plural anaphora (yet). 9/38

  23. Limitations (3) Every player chooses a pawn. He puts it on square one. Ranta (1994: 73): the only way to interpret the text […] is by treating the pronoun ‘he’ as an abbreviation of ‘every player’ Obviously, this ‘abbreviation’ strategy is unsatisfactory. (2) Every student bought a book. Most of them read it. No mechanism for plural anaphora (yet). 9/38

  24. Outline of the proposal

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend