proofs computations and analysis
play

Proofs, computations and analysis Helmut Schwichtenberg (j.w.w. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Proofs, computations and analysis Helmut Schwichtenberg (j.w.w. Kenji Miyamoto) Mathematisches Institut, LMU, M unchen Computability Theory and Foundations of Mathematics, Tokyo, 19. February 2013 Motivation Algorithms are viewed as one


  1. Proofs, computations and analysis Helmut Schwichtenberg (j.w.w. Kenji Miyamoto) Mathematisches Institut, LMU, M¨ unchen Computability Theory and Foundations of Mathematics, Tokyo, 19. February 2013

  2. Motivation Algorithms are viewed as one aspect of proofs in (constructive) analysis. A corresponding program (i.e., a term t in the underlying language) can be extracted from a proof of A , and a proof that t “realizes” A can be generated ( ⇒ automatic verification). Data: From free algebras, given by their constructors. Examples: ◮ finite or infinite lists of signed digits − 1, 0, 1 (i.e., reals as streams), ◮ possibly non well-founded alternating read-write trees (representing uniformly continuous functions).

  3. Tools ◮ Decorations: → c , ∀ c (short: → , ∀ ) and → nc , ∀ nc for removal of abstract data, and fine-tuning. ◮ Nested inductive/coinductive definitions of predicates. Their clauses give rise to free algebras. Only here computational content arises.

  4. Computable functionals ◮ Types: ι | ρ → σ . Base types ι : free algebras (e.g., N ), given by their signature. ◮ Functionals seen as limits of finite approximations: ideals (Kreisel, Scott, Ershov). ◮ Computable functionals are r.e. sets of finite approximations (example: fixed point functional). ◮ Functionals are partial. Total functionals are defined (by induction over the types).

  5. Information systems C ρ for partial continuous functionals ◮ Types ρ, σ, τ : from algebras ι by ρ → σ . ◮ C ρ := ( C ρ , Con ρ , ⊢ ρ ). ◮ Tokens a ∈ C ρ (= atomic pieces of information): constructor trees C a ∗ 1 , . . . a ∗ n with a ∗ i a token or ∗ . Example: S ( S ∗ ). ◮ Formal neighborhoods U ∈ Con ρ : { a 1 , . . . , a n } , consistent. ◮ Entailment U ⊢ ρ a . Ideals x ∈ | C ρ | (“points”, here: partial continuous functionals): consistent deductively closed sets of tokens.

  6. Flat or non flat algebras? ◮ Flat: { 0 } { 1 } { 2 } ... • • • ✟ ✟✟✟✟ � � � • ∅ ◮ Non flat: ... S ( S ( S 0)) • ❅ � ❅ � ❅ � S ( S 0) • • S ( S ( S ∗ )) ❅ � ❅ � ❅ � • • S ( S ∗ ) S 0 ❅ � ❅ � ❅ � • • 0 S ∗

  7. Non flat! ◮ Every constructor C generates an ideal in the function space: r C := { ( U , C a ∗ ) | U ⊢ a ∗ } . Associated continuous map: | r C | ( x ) = { C a ∗ | ∃ U ⊆ x ( U ⊢ a ∗ ) } . ◮ Constructors are injective and have disjoint ranges: | r C | ( � x ) ⊆ | r C | ( � y ) ↔ � x ⊆ � y , | r C 1 | ( � x ) ∩ | r C 2 | ( � y ) = ∅ . ◮ Both properties are false for flat information systems (for them, by monotonicity, constructors need to be strict). | r C | ( ∅ , y ) = ∅ = | r C | ( x , ∅ ) , | r C 1 | ( ∅ ) = ∅ = | r C 2 | ( ∅ ) .

  8. A theory of computable functionals, TCF ◮ A variant of HA ω . ◮ Variables range over arbitrary partial continuous functionals. ◮ Constants for (partial) computable functionals, defined by equations. ◮ Inductively and coinductively defined predicates. Totality for ground types inductively defined. ◮ Induction := elimination (or least-fixed-point) axiom for a totality predicate. ◮ Coinduction := greatest-fixed-point axiom for a coinductively defined predicate.

  9. Relation to type theory ◮ Main difference: partial functionals are first class citizens. ◮ Minimal logic: → , ∀ only. = (Leibniz), ∃ , ∨ , ∧ (Martin-L¨ of) inductively defined. ◮ ⊥ := ( False = True ). Ex-falso-quodlibet: ⊥ → A provable. ◮ Classical logic as a fragment: ˜ ∃ x A defined by ¬∀ x ¬ A .

  10. Realizability interpretation ◮ Define a formula t r A , for A a formula and t a term in T + . ◮ From a proof M we can extract its computational content, a term et ( M ). ◮ Soundness theorem: If M proves A , then et ( M ) r A can be proved. ◮ Decorations: → c , ∀ c (short: → , ∀ ) and → nc , ∀ nc for removal of abstract data, and fine-tuning: t r ( A → c B ) := ∀ x ( x r A → tx r B ) , t r ( A → nc B ) := ∀ x ( x r A → t r B ) , t r ( ∀ c x A ) := ∀ x ( tx r A ) , t r ( ∀ nc := ∀ x ( t r A ) . x A )

  11. Example: decorating the existential quantifier ◮ ∃ x A is inductively defined by the clause ∀ x ( A → ∃ x A ) with least-fixed-point axiom ∃ x A → ∀ x ( A → P ) → P . ◮ Decoration leads to variants ∃ d , ∃ l , ∃ r , ∃ u (d for “double”, l for “left”, r for “right” and u for “uniform”). x ( A → c ∃ d x A → c ∀ c x ( A → c P ) → c P , ∀ c ∃ d x A ) , x ( A → c ∃ r x A → c ∀ nc x ( A → c P ) → c P . ∀ nc ∃ r x A ) ,

  12. Practical aspects ◮ We need formalized proofs, to allow machine extraction. ◮ Can’t take a proof assistant from the shelf: none fits TCF . Minlog ( http://www.minlog-system.de ) ◮ Natural deduction for → , ∀ , plus inductively and coinductively defined predicates. ◮ Partial functionals are first class citizens. ◮ Allows type and predicate parameters (for abstract developments: groups, fields, reals, . . . ).

  13. Uniformly continuous functions Based on work of Ulrich Berger (2009). ◮ Extraction from a proof dealing with abstract uniformly continuous functions. ◮ Data representing uniformly continuous functions: base type cototal ideals. ◮ The extracted term will involve corecursion.

  14. Type-1 representation of uniformly continuous functions For contrast: a type-1 represented function f : [ − 1 , 1] → [ − 1 , 1] is given by ◮ an approximating map h : [ − 1 , 1] ∩ Q → N → Q , ◮ bounds N , M ∈ N with ∀ a ∈ [ − 1 , 1] ∀ n ( N ≤ h ( a , n ) ≤ M ), and ◮ a weakly increasing map α : N → N such that ( h ( a , n )) n is a Cauchy sequence with (uniform) modulus α , i.e., ∀ a ∈ [ − 1 , 1] ∀ k ∀ n , m ≥ α ( k ) ( | h ( a , n ) − h ( a , m ) | ≤ 2 − k ) . f is (uniformly) continuous if we have a weakly increasing modulus ω : N → N such that ∀ k ∀ a , b ∈ [ − 1 , 1] ∀ n ≥ α ( k ) ( | a − b | ≤ 2 − ω ( k )+1 → | h ( a , n ) − h ( b , n ) | ≤ 2 − k ) .

  15. Application f ( x ) Application of f given by h , α and modulus ω to x := (( a n ) n , M ): f ( x ) := ( h ( a n , n )) n with Cauchy modulus max( α ( k + 2) , M ( ω ( k + 1) − 1)).

  16. Intermediate value theorem Let a < b be rationals. If f : [ a , b ] → R is continuous with f ( a ) ≤ 0 ≤ f ( b ), and with a uniform lower bound on its slope, then we can find x ∈ [ a , b ] such that f ( x ) = 0. Proof sketch. 1. Approximate Splitting Principle. Let x , y , z be given with x < y . Then z ≤ y or x ≤ z . 2. IVTAux. Assume a ≤ c < d ≤ b , say 2 − n < d − c , and f ( c ) ≤ 0 ≤ f ( d ). Construct c 1 , d 1 with d 1 − c 1 = 2 3 ( d − c ), such that a ≤ c ≤ c 1 < d 1 ≤ d ≤ b and f ( c 1 ) ≤ 0 ≤ f ( d 1 ). 3. IVTcds. Iterate the step c , d �→ c 1 , d 1 in IVTAux. Let x = ( c n ) n and y = ( d n ) n with the obvious modulus. As f is continuous, f ( x ) = 0 = f ( y ) for the real number x = y .

  17. Extracted term [k0] left((cDC rat@@rat)(1@2) ([n1] (cId rat@@rat=>rat@@rat) ([cd3] [let cd4 ((2#3)*left cd3+(1#3)*right cd3@ (1#3)*left cd3+(2#3)*right cd3) [if (0<=(left cd4*left cd4-2+ (right cd4*right cd4-2))/2) (left cd3@right cd4) (left cd4@right cd3)]])) (IntToNat(2*k0))) where cDC is a from of the recursion operator.

  18. Free algebra J of intervals ◮ SD := {− 1 , 0 , 1 } signed digits (or { L , M , R } ). ◮ J free algebra of intervals. Constructors the interval [ − 1 , 1] , I C : SD → J → J left, middle, right half . Write C d x for C dx . ◮ C 1 I denotes [0 , 1]. ◮ C 0 I denotes [ − 1 2 , 1 2 ]. ◮ C 0 ( C − 1 I ) denotes [ − 1 2 , 0]. C d 0 ( C d 1 . . . ( C d k − 1 I ) . . . ) denotes the interval in [ − 1 , 1] whose reals have a signed digit representation starting with d 0 d 1 . . . d k − 1 . ◮ We consider ideals x ∈ | C J | .

  19. Total and cototal ideals of base type Generally: ◮ Cototal ideals x : every token (i.e., constructor tree) P ( ∗ ) ∈ x has a “ ≻ 1 -successor” P ( C � ∗ ) ∈ x . ◮ Total ideals: the cototal ones with ≻ 1 well-founded. Examples: ◮ Total ideals of J : 2 k − 1 2 k + 1 2 k , k := [ i 2 k , i for − 2 k < i < 2 k . I i 2 k ] ◮ Cototal ideals of J : reals in [ − 1 , 1], in (non-unique) stream representation using signed digits − 1 , 0 , 1.

  20. Corecursion ◮ The conversion rules for R with total ideals as recursion arguments work from the leaves towards the root, and terminate because total ideals are well-founded. ◮ For cototal ideals (streams) a similar operator is available to define functions with cototal ideals as values: corecursion. ◮ co R τ J : τ → ( τ → U + SD × ( J + τ )) → J ( U unit type). ◮ Conversion rule J NM �→ [ case ( MN ) U + SD × ( J + τ ) of co R τ inl �→ I | inr � d , z � �→ C d [ case z J + τ of �→ I | inl inr u τ �→ co R τ J uM ]] .

  21. W and continuous real functions ◮ Consider a well-founded “read tree”, i.e., a constructor tree built from R (ternary) with R d at its leaves. ◮ The digit d at a leaf means that, after reading all input digits on the path leading to the leaf, the output d is written. ◮ Let R d 1 , . . . , R d n be all leaves. At a leaf R d i continue with W (i.e., write d i ), and continue reading. ◮ Result: a “nested R ( W )-total W -cototal” ideal, representing a uniformly continuous real function f : I → I .

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend