on the mathematical and foundational significance of the
play

On the mathematical and foundational significance of the uncountable - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

On the mathematical and foundational significance of the uncountable Sam Sanders (jww Dag Normann) Kanazawa, March 2018 Center for Advanced Studies, LMU Munich Reverse Mathematics Reverse Mathematics Reverse Mathematics (RM), as


  1. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory Cousin proved ‘Cousin’s lemma’ before 1893, dealing with R 2 : Define a connected space S bounded by a simple or complex closed contour; if to each point of S there corresponds a circle of finite radius, then the region can be divided into a finite number of subregions such that each subregion is interior to a circle of the given set having its center in the subregion. This is just Heine-Borel compactness for uncountable open covers. Pincherle’s theorem (1882) has Cousin’s lemma as a special case. Lindel¨ of proved the related ‘Lindel¨ of lemma’ (1903): an uncountable open cover of E ⊂ R n has a countable sub-cover.

  2. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory Cousin proved ‘Cousin’s lemma’ before 1893, dealing with R 2 : Define a connected space S bounded by a simple or complex closed contour; if to each point of S there corresponds a circle of finite radius, then the region can be divided into a finite number of subregions such that each subregion is interior to a circle of the given set having its center in the subregion. This is just Heine-Borel compactness for uncountable open covers. Pincherle’s theorem (1882) has Cousin’s lemma as a special case. Lindel¨ of proved the related ‘Lindel¨ of lemma’ (1903): an uncountable open cover of E ⊂ R n has a countable sub-cover. The Cousin and Lindel¨ of lemmas cannot be formalised in second-order arithmetic.

  3. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory

  4. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory Dirichlet mentions ‘Dirichlet’s function’, i.e. the characteristic function of Q , for the first time in 1829.

  5. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory Dirichlet mentions ‘Dirichlet’s function’, i.e. the characteristic function of Q , for the first time in 1829. Riemann defines a function with countably many discontinuities via a series in his Habilitationsschrift in 1855

  6. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory Dirichlet mentions ‘Dirichlet’s function’, i.e. the characteristic function of Q , for the first time in 1829. Riemann defines a function with countably many discontinuities via a series in his Habilitationsschrift in 1855 Discontinuous functions cannot be represented via codes in general.

  7. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory Dirichlet mentions ‘Dirichlet’s function’, i.e. the characteristic function of Q , for the first time in 1829. Riemann defines a function with countably many discontinuities via a series in his Habilitationsschrift in 1855 Discontinuous functions cannot be represented via codes in general. Do we really need discontinuous functions and/or Cousin’s lemma?

  8. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory Dirichlet mentions ‘Dirichlet’s function’, i.e. the characteristic function of Q , for the first time in 1829. Riemann defines a function with countably many discontinuities via a series in his Habilitationsschrift in 1855 Discontinuous functions cannot be represented via codes in general. Do we really need discontinuous functions and/or Cousin’s lemma? YES; even in scientifically applicable math!

  9. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory

  10. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory The gauge integral was introduced in 1912 by Denjoy (in a different form) and generalises Lebesgue’s integral (1904).

  11. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory The gauge integral was introduced in 1912 by Denjoy (in a different form) and generalises Lebesgue’s integral (1904). The gauge integral (directly) formalises the Feynman path integral from physics.

  12. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory The gauge integral was introduced in 1912 by Denjoy (in a different form) and generalises Lebesgue’s integral (1904). The gauge integral (directly) formalises the Feynman path integral from physics. Gefundenes Fressen!

  13. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory The gauge integral was introduced in 1912 by Denjoy (in a different form) and generalises Lebesgue’s integral (1904). The gauge integral (directly) formalises the Feynman path integral from physics. Gefundenes Fressen! As we will see below, the very definition of the gauge integral requires higher-order theorems and objects, namely (full) Cousin’s lemma and discontinuous functions on R .

  14. Step 1: ordinary mathematics requiring higher types Ordinary mathematics = prior to or independent of abstract set theory The gauge integral was introduced in 1912 by Denjoy (in a different form) and generalises Lebesgue’s integral (1904). The gauge integral (directly) formalises the Feynman path integral from physics. Gefundenes Fressen! As we will see below, the very definition of the gauge integral requires higher-order theorems and objects, namely (full) Cousin’s lemma and discontinuous functions on R . The development of the gauge integral: Denjoy-Luzin-Perron-Henstock-Kurzweil

  15. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM

  16. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω 0 ATR ω 0 ACA ω 0 WKL ω 0 RCA ω 0 / RCA 0

  17. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω 0 ATR ω 0 ACA ω 0 WKL ω 0 RCA ω 0 / RCA 0 All the second-order systems have higher-order counterparts!

  18. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM ✻ ( ∃ 3 ): there is a functional ∃ 3 deciding ‘( ∃ f ∈ N N )( F ( f ) = 0)’ for any F 2 Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω 0 ATR ω 0 ACA ω 0 WKL ω 0 RCA ω 0 / RCA 0 All the second-order systems have higher-order counterparts!

  19. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM ✻ ( ∃ 3 ): there is a functional ∃ 3 deciding ‘( ∃ f ∈ N N )( F ( f ) = 0)’ for any F 2 Z ω 2 Π 1 ( S 2 k ): there is a functional S 2 k which decides Π 1 k -CA ω k -formulas 0 ATR ω 0 ACA ω 0 WKL ω 0 RCA ω 0 / RCA 0 All the second-order systems have higher-order counterparts!

  20. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM ✻ ( ∃ 3 ): there is a functional ∃ 3 deciding ‘( ∃ f ∈ N N )( F ( f ) = 0)’ for any F 2 Z ω 2 Π 1 ( S 2 k ): there is a functional S 2 k which decides Π 1 k -CA ω k -formulas 0 ATR ω (UATR): ‘there is a functional expressing transfinite recursion’ 0 ACA ω 0 WKL ω 0 RCA ω 0 / RCA 0 All the second-order systems have higher-order counterparts!

  21. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM ✻ ( ∃ 3 ): there is a functional ∃ 3 deciding ‘( ∃ f ∈ N N )( F ( f ) = 0)’ for any F 2 Z ω 2 Π 1 ( S 2 k ): there is a functional S 2 k which decides Π 1 k -CA ω k -formulas 0 ATR ω (UATR): ‘there is a functional expressing transfinite recursion’ 0 ( ∃ 2 ): there is a functional ∃ 2 deciding arithm. formulas ACA ω 0 WKL ω 0 RCA ω 0 / RCA 0 All the second-order systems have higher-order counterparts!

  22. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and Higher-order RM ✻ ( ∃ 3 ): there is a functional ∃ 3 deciding ‘( ∃ f ∈ N N )( F ( f ) = 0)’ for any F 2 Z ω 2 Π 1 ( S 2 k ): there is a functional S 2 k which decides Π 1 k -CA ω k -formulas 0 ATR ω (UATR): ‘there is a functional expressing transfinite recursion’ 0 ( ∃ 2 ): there is a functional ∃ 2 deciding arithm. formulas ACA ω 0 WKL ω (FF): the fan functional computes a modulus of uniform 0 continuity for any continuous functional on 2 N RCA ω 0 / RCA 0 All the second-order systems have higher-order counterparts!

  23. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893)

  24. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover.

  25. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover. Any functional Ψ : I → R + yields a ‘canonical’ cover ∪ x ∈ I I Ψ x of I , where I Ψ x ≡ ( x − Ψ( x ) , x + Ψ( x )).

  26. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover. Any functional Ψ : I → R + yields a ‘canonical’ cover ∪ x ∈ I I Ψ x of I , where I Ψ x ≡ ( x − Ψ( x ) , x + Ψ( x )). Hence, we have: ( ∀ Ψ : I → R + )( ∃ y 1 , . . . , y k ∈ [0 , 1])([0 , 1] ⊂ ∪ i ≤ k I Ψ y i ) (HBU)

  27. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover. Any functional Ψ : I → R + yields a ‘canonical’ cover ∪ x ∈ I I Ψ x of I , where I Ψ x ≡ ( x − Ψ( x ) , x + Ψ( x )). Hence, we have: ( ∀ Ψ : I → R + )( ∃ y 1 , . . . , y k ∈ [0 , 1])([0 , 1] ⊂ ∪ i ≤ k I Ψ y i ) (HBU) The reals y 1 , . . . , y k yield a finite sub-cover; NO conditions on Ψ.

  28. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover. Any functional Ψ : I → R + yields a ‘canonical’ cover ∪ x ∈ I I Ψ x of I , where I Ψ x ≡ ( x − Ψ( x ) , x + Ψ( x )). Hence, we have: ( ∀ Ψ : I → R + )( ∃ y 1 , . . . , y k ∈ [0 , 1])([0 , 1] ⊂ ∪ i ≤ k I Ψ y i ) (HBU) The reals y 1 , . . . , y k yield a finite sub-cover; NO conditions on Ψ. special fan functional Θ computes y 1 , . . . , y k from Ψ, i.e realiser for HBU.

  29. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover. Any functional Ψ : I → R + yields a ‘canonical’ cover ∪ x ∈ I I Ψ x of I , where I Ψ x ≡ ( x − Ψ( x ) , x + Ψ( x )). Hence, we have: ( ∀ Ψ : I → R + )( ∃ y 1 , . . . , y k ∈ [0 , 1])([0 , 1] ⊂ ∪ i ≤ k I Ψ y i ) (HBU) The reals y 1 , . . . , y k yield a finite sub-cover; NO conditions on Ψ. special fan functional Θ computes y 1 , . . . , y k from Ψ, i.e realiser for HBU. Where does HBU fit in RM?

  30. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover. Any functional Ψ : I → R + yields a ‘canonical’ cover ∪ x ∈ I I Ψ x of I , where I Ψ x ≡ ( x − Ψ( x ) , x + Ψ( x )). Hence, we have: ( ∀ Ψ : I → R + )( ∃ y 1 , . . . , y k ∈ [0 , 1])([0 , 1] ⊂ ∪ i ≤ k I Ψ y i ) (HBU) The reals y 1 , . . . , y k yield a finite sub-cover; NO conditions on Ψ. special fan functional Θ computes y 1 , . . . , y k from Ψ, i.e realiser for HBU. Where does HBU fit in RM? Almost equivalent question: How hard is it to compute Θ (in the sense of Kleene’s S1-S9)?

  31. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: Cousin’s lemma in higher-order RM Cousin’s lemma (1893) implies that ANY open cover of I ≡ [0 , 1] has a finite sub-cover. Any functional Ψ : I → R + yields a ‘canonical’ cover ∪ x ∈ I I Ψ x of I , where I Ψ x ≡ ( x − Ψ( x ) , x + Ψ( x )). Hence, we have: ( ∀ Ψ : I → R + )( ∃ y 1 , . . . , y k ∈ [0 , 1])([0 , 1] ⊂ ∪ i ≤ k I Ψ y i ) (HBU) The reals y 1 , . . . , y k yield a finite sub-cover; NO conditions on Ψ. special fan functional Θ computes y 1 , . . . , y k from Ψ, i.e realiser for HBU. Where does HBU fit in RM? Almost equivalent question: How hard is it to compute Θ (in the sense of Kleene’s S1-S9)? PS: Borel’s proof of HBU ( ≈ 1900) makes no use of the axiom of choice. With minimal adaption, Borel’s proof yields a realiser Θ for HBU.

  32. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU

  33. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω 0 ATR ω 0 ACA ω 0 WKL 0 RCA ω 0

  34. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω 0 ATR ω 0 ACA ω 0 ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0

  35. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω 0 ATR ω 0 ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0

  36. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω 0 ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ❄ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0

  37. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω ❅ 0 ❅ ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ❄ ❄ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0

  38. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 Π 1 k -CA ω ❅ 0 ❅ ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ❄ ❄ ✠ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0

  39. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 FULL SOA as in Z ω 2 is needed to prove HBU! Π 1 k -CA ω ❅ 0 ❅ ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ❄ ❄ ✠ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0

  40. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 FULL SOA as in Z ω 2 is needed to prove HBU! Π 1 k -CA ω ❅ 0 ❅ HBU falls FAR outside of the Big Five! ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❘ ❅ ❄ ❄ ✠ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0

  41. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 FULL SOA as in Z ω 2 is needed to prove HBU! Π 1 k -CA ω ❅ 0 ❅ HBU falls FAR outside of the Big Five! ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ❄ ❄ ✠ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0 In fact: NO type 2 functional computes (S1-S9) a realiser Θ for HBU.

  42. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 FULL SOA as in Z ω 2 is needed to prove HBU! Π 1 k -CA ω ❅ 0 ❅ HBU falls FAR outside of the Big Five! ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ❄ ❄ ✠ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0 In fact: NO type 2 functional computes (S1-S9) a realiser Θ for HBU. hence: NO Big Five system implies HBU;

  43. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 2: The Big Five and HBU ✻ Z ω 2 FULL SOA as in Z ω 2 is needed to prove HBU! Π 1 k -CA ω ❅ 0 ❅ HBU falls FAR outside of the Big Five! ATR ω ❅ 0 ❅ ❅ ❅ ACA ω 0 ❅ ❘ ❄ ❄ ✠ ✛ WKL 0 HBU: Heine-Borel thm for uncountable covers on [0 , 1] RCA ω 0 In fact: NO type 2 functional computes (S1-S9) a realiser Θ for HBU. k -CA ω hence: NO Big Five system implies HBU; same for Π 1 0

  44. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU:

  45. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1

  46. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1 If a function is Riemann int., it is gauge int. with the same integral. 2

  47. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1 If a function is Riemann int., it is gauge int. with the same integral. 2 There is a non-gauge integrable function. 3

  48. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1 If a function is Riemann int., it is gauge int. with the same integral. 2 There is a non-gauge integrable function. 3 There is a gauge integrable function which is not Lebesgue int. 4

  49. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1 If a function is Riemann int., it is gauge int. with the same integral. 2 There is a non-gauge integrable function. 3 There is a gauge integrable function which is not Lebesgue int. 4 a version of Hake’s theorem (about improper gauge integrals) 5

  50. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1 If a function is Riemann int., it is gauge int. with the same integral. 2 There is a non-gauge integrable function. 3 There is a gauge integrable function which is not Lebesgue int. 4 a version of Hake’s theorem (about improper gauge integrals) 5 The gauge integral provides a simpler generalisation of Lebesgue’s integral and a partial/direct formalisation for Feynman’s path integral.

  51. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1 If a function is Riemann int., it is gauge int. with the same integral. 2 There is a non-gauge integrable function. 3 There is a gauge integrable function which is not Lebesgue int. 4 a version of Hake’s theorem (about improper gauge integrals) 5 The gauge integral provides a simpler generalisation of Lebesgue’s integral and a partial/direct formalisation for Feynman’s path integral. f : R → R is Riemann integrable on I ≡ [0 , 1] with integral A ∈ R : ( ∀ ε > 0)( ∃ δ > 0 )( ∀ P )( � P � < δ → | S ( P , f ) − A | < ε ) � �� � � �� � constant P is ‘finer’ than δ P = (0 , t 1 , x 1 , . . . x k , t k , 1) partition of I ; mesh � P � := max i ≤ k ( x i +1 − x i ); Riemann sum S ( P , f ) = � k i =0 f ( t i )( x i +1 − x i ).

  52. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: Some mathematical friends for HBU The following properties of the gauge integral are equivalent to HBU: If a function is gauge integrable, the associated integral is unique. 1 If a function is Riemann int., it is gauge int. with the same integral. 2 There is a non-gauge integrable function. 3 There is a gauge integrable function which is not Lebesgue int. 4 a version of Hake’s theorem (about improper gauge integrals) 5 The gauge integral provides a simpler generalisation of Lebesgue’s integral and a partial/direct formalisation for Feynman’s path integral. f : R → R is gauge integrable on I ≡ [0 , 1] with integral A ∈ R : ( ∀ ε > 0)( ∃ δ : I → R + )( ∀ P )(every I δ t i covers [ x i , x i +1 ] → | S ( P , f ) − A | < ε ) � �� � � �� � ‘gauge’ function P is ‘finer’ than δ P = (0 , t 1 , x 1 , . . . x k , t k , 1) partition of I ; mesh � P � := max i ≤ k ( x i +1 − x i ); Riemann sum S ( P , f ) = � k i =0 f ( t i )( x i +1 − x i ).

  53. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU

  54. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’.

  55. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’. RCA ω 0 + LIND is conservative over RCA 0 and HBU ↔ [WKL + LIND] (splitting).

  56. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’. RCA ω 0 + LIND is conservative over RCA 0 and HBU ↔ [WKL + LIND] (splitting). The existence of Lebesgue numbers for any open cover of [0 , 1] implies HBU.

  57. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’. RCA ω 0 + LIND is conservative over RCA 0 and HBU ↔ [WKL + LIND] (splitting). The existence of Lebesgue numbers for any open cover of [0 , 1] implies HBU. Marcone and Guisto (1998) write: the restriction [on Lebesgue numbers] imposed by the expressive power of the language of [Z 2 ] on the spaces we study consists solely of forsaking non separable spaces.

  58. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’. RCA ω 0 + LIND is conservative over RCA 0 and HBU ↔ [WKL + LIND] (splitting). The existence of Lebesgue numbers for any open cover of [0 , 1] implies HBU. Marcone and Guisto (1998) write: the restriction [on Lebesgue numbers] imposed by the expressive power of the language of [Z 2 ] on the spaces we study consists solely of forsaking non separable spaces. Lebesgue numbers for countable covers of [0 , 1] exists in ACA 0 ; HBU is k -CA ω not provable in any fragment of second-order arithmetic Π 1 0 .

  59. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’. RCA ω 0 + LIND is conservative over RCA 0 and HBU ↔ [WKL + LIND] (splitting). The existence of Lebesgue numbers for any open cover of [0 , 1] implies HBU. Marcone and Guisto (1998) write: the restriction [on Lebesgue numbers] imposed by the expressive power of the language of [Z 2 ] on the spaces we study consists solely of forsaking non separable spaces. Lebesgue numbers for countable covers of [0 , 1] exists in ACA 0 ; HBU is k -CA ω not provable in any fragment of second-order arithmetic Π 1 0 . Many ‘covering lemmas’ imply LIND or HBU: Vitali, Besicovitsch, Banach-Alaoglu, paracompactness, Young-Young, Rademacher, . . . .

  60. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’. RCA ω 0 + LIND is conservative over RCA 0 and HBU ↔ [WKL + LIND] (splitting). The existence of Lebesgue numbers for any open cover of [0 , 1] implies HBU. Marcone and Guisto (1998) write: the restriction [on Lebesgue numbers] imposed by the expressive power of the language of [Z 2 ] on the spaces we study consists solely of forsaking non separable spaces. Lebesgue numbers for countable covers of [0 , 1] exists in ACA 0 ; HBU is k -CA ω not provable in any fragment of second-order arithmetic Π 1 0 . Many ‘covering lemmas’ imply LIND or HBU: Vitali, Besicovitsch, Banach-Alaoglu, paracompactness, Young-Young, Rademacher, . . . . Vitali (1907) expresses his surprise about the uncountable case of the Vitali covering theorem;

  61. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 3: More mathematical friends for HBU The Lindel¨ of lemma LIND is HBU with the weaker conclusion ‘there is a countable sub-cover’. RCA ω 0 + LIND is conservative over RCA 0 and HBU ↔ [WKL + LIND] (splitting). The existence of Lebesgue numbers for any open cover of [0 , 1] implies HBU. Marcone and Guisto (1998) write: the restriction [on Lebesgue numbers] imposed by the expressive power of the language of [Z 2 ] on the spaces we study consists solely of forsaking non separable spaces. Lebesgue numbers for countable covers of [0 , 1] exists in ACA 0 ; HBU is k -CA ω not provable in any fragment of second-order arithmetic Π 1 0 . Many ‘covering lemmas’ imply LIND or HBU: Vitali, Besicovitsch, Banach-Alaoglu, paracompactness, Young-Young, Rademacher, . . . . Vitali (1907) expresses his surprise about the uncountable case of the Vitali covering theorem; Diener & Hedin (2012) however. . .

  62. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND

  63. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND NON-LINEARITY: By itself, HBU (and same for Θ) is weak:

  64. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND NON-LINEARITY: By itself, HBU (and same for Θ) is weak: RCA ω 0 + HBU is conservative over WKL 0

  65. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND NON-LINEARITY: By itself, HBU (and same for Θ) is weak: RCA ω 0 + HBU is conservative over WKL 0 With other axioms, HBU is powerful and jumps all over the place: ACA ω 0 + HBU proves ATR 0

  66. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND NON-LINEARITY: By itself, HBU (and same for Θ) is weak: RCA ω 0 + HBU is conservative over WKL 0 With other axioms, HBU is powerful and jumps all over the place: ACA ω 0 + HBU proves ATR 0 Π 1 0 + HBU proves ∆ 1 2 -CA 0 and the Π 1 3 -consequences of Π 1 1 -CA ω 2 -CA 0

  67. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND NON-LINEARITY: By itself, HBU (and same for Θ) is weak: RCA ω 0 + HBU is conservative over WKL 0 With other axioms, HBU is powerful and jumps all over the place: ACA ω 0 + HBU proves ATR 0 Π 1 0 + HBU proves ∆ 1 2 -CA 0 and the Π 1 3 -consequences of Π 1 1 -CA ω 2 -CA 0 Theorems of second-order arithmetic NEVER jump anywhere!

  68. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND

  69. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND COLLAPSE: RCA ω 0 + HBU proves [ACA ω 0 ↔ ATR ω 0 ]

  70. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND COLLAPSE: RCA ω 0 + HBU proves [ACA ω 0 ↔ ATR ω 0 ] The 3rd and 4th Big Five are equivalent; the linear order of RM collapses!

  71. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND COLLAPSE: RCA ω 0 + HBU proves [ACA ω 0 ↔ ATR ω 0 ] The 3rd and 4th Big Five are equivalent; the linear order of RM collapses! MORE COLLAPSE: LIND 0 , the Lindel¨ of lemma for Baire space N N , follows from Lindel¨ of’s original lemma (1903).

  72. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND COLLAPSE: RCA ω 0 + HBU proves [ACA ω 0 ↔ ATR ω 0 ] The 3rd and 4th Big Five are equivalent; the linear order of RM collapses! MORE COLLAPSE: LIND 0 , the Lindel¨ of lemma for Baire space N N , follows from Lindel¨ of’s original lemma (1903). 0 ↔ Π 1 RCA ω 0 + ‘There is a realiser for LIND 0 ’ proves ACA ω 1 -CA ω 0 � �� � weak: not stronger than RCA 0

  73. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND COLLAPSE: RCA ω 0 + HBU proves [ACA ω 0 ↔ ATR ω 0 ] The 3rd and 4th Big Five are equivalent; the linear order of RM collapses! MORE COLLAPSE: LIND 0 , the Lindel¨ of lemma for Baire space N N , follows from Lindel¨ of’s original lemma (1903). 0 ↔ Π 1 RCA ω 0 + ‘There is a realiser for LIND 0 ’ proves ACA ω 1 -CA ω 0 � �� � weak: not stronger than RCA 0 The 3rd and 5th Big Five are equivalent: almost total collapse!

  74. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: Some conceptual results for HBU and LIND COLLAPSE: RCA ω 0 + HBU proves [ACA ω 0 ↔ ATR ω 0 ] The 3rd and 4th Big Five are equivalent; the linear order of RM collapses! MORE COLLAPSE: LIND 0 , the Lindel¨ of lemma for Baire space N N , follows from Lindel¨ of’s original lemma (1903). 0 ↔ Π 1 RCA ω 0 + ‘There is a realiser for LIND 0 ’ proves ACA ω 1 -CA ω 0 � �� � weak: not stronger than RCA 0 The 3rd and 5th Big Five are equivalent: almost total collapse! Anil Nerode: That’s not reverse math, that’s topsy turvy math!

  75. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: conceptual results for HBU DISJUNCTIONS as in A ↔ [ B ∨ C ] are rare in RM.

  76. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: conceptual results for HBU DISJUNCTIONS as in A ↔ [ B ∨ C ] are rare in RM. However, there are loads of those in higher-order RM:

  77. Introduction Shin-Reverse Mathematics Some philosophy and history Step 4: conceptual results for HBU DISJUNCTIONS as in A ↔ [ B ∨ C ] are rare in RM. However, there are loads of those in higher-order RM: If ACA 0 → X → WKL 0 , then RCA ω 0 proves WKL ↔ [ X ∨ HBU]. If ACA 0 → Y , then RCA ω 0 proves Y ∨ LIND. If ACA 0 → Z , then RCA ω 0 + WKL proves that Z ∨ HBU.

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend