on the commitment value and commitment optimal strategies
play

On the commitment value and commitment optimal strategies in - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

On the commitment value and commitment optimal strategies in bimatrix games Stefanos Leonardos 1 and Costis Melolidakis National and Kapodistrian University of Athens Department of Mathematics, Division of Statistics & Operations Research


  1. On the commitment value and commitment optimal strategies in bimatrix games Stefanos Leonardos 1 and Costis Melolidakis National and Kapodistrian University of Athens Department of Mathematics, Division of Statistics & Operations Research January 9, 2018 1Supported by the Alexander S. Onassis Public Benefit Foundation. 1/24

  2. Overview Motivation 1 Definitions – Existing results 2 Results 3 2 × 2 bimatrix games Weakly unilaterally competitive games General bimatrix games: pure & completely mixed equilibria Future Research 4 2/24

  3. Outline Motivation 1 Definitions – Existing results 2 Results 3 2 × 2 bimatrix games Weakly unilaterally competitive games General bimatrix games: pure & completely mixed equilibria Future Research 4 3/24

  4. Motivation I � J. von Neumann & O. Morgenstern (1944): used 2 auxiliary games to present the solution of 2-person, 0-sum games. Minorant game: player I in disadvantage. I chooses his mixed strategy x first, and then II , in full knowledge of x (but not of its realization) chooses his strategy y . Majorant game: player I in advantage (order reversed). � Payoffs of player I Minorant game: α L = max x ∈ X min y ∈ Y α ( x , y ) Majorant game: α F = min y ∈ Y max x ∈ X α ( x , y ) Simultaneous game: any solution v A must satisfy α L ≤ v A ≤ α F . � Minimax theorem: α L = α F in mixed strategies = ⇒ v A unique solution. 4/24

  5. Motivation II � Generalize to 2-person, non 0-sum games: not straightforward. � Reason: 3 different points of view Matrix values v A : optimize against the worst possible Equilibrium α N : optimize simultaneously Optimization α L : optimize sequentially � In 0-sum games: v A = α N = α L . In non 0-sum? � Our aim is to study the relation between the three notions matrix values & max-min strategies Nash equilibria payoffs & strategies commitment values & optimal strategies in the associated sequential games. 5/24

  6. Outline Motivation 1 Definitions – Existing results 2 Results 3 2 × 2 bimatrix games Weakly unilaterally competitive games General bimatrix games: pure & completely mixed equilibria Future Research 4 6/24

  7. Existing results I � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Theorem (1) In a (degenerate) bimatrix game, the subgame perfect equilibria payoffs of the leader form an interval [ α L , α H ]. The lowest leader equilibrium payoff α L is given by α L = max j ∈ D max x ∈ X ( j ) min k ∈E ( j ) α ( x , k ) and the highest leader equilibrium payoff α H is given by α H = max j ∈ BR II ( x ) α ( x , j ) = max max j ∈ N max x ∈ X ( j ) α ( x , j ) x ∈ X If the game is non-degenerate, then α L = α H is the unique commitment value of the leader. 7/24

  8. Existing results II � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Example � a b c d e � a b c d e � � 2 6 9 1 7 4 4 0 2 4 T T A = B = 8 0 3 1 0 4 4 6 5 0 B B 7/24

  9. Existing results II � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Example � a b c d e � a b c d e � � 2 6 9 1 7 4 4 0 2 4 T T A = B = 8 0 3 1 0 4 4 6 5 0 B B Nash equilibria: (many) Nash payoffs: Player I from 1 to 7, Player II 4 7/24

  10. Existing results II � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Example � a b c d e � a b c d e � � 2 6 9 1 7 4 4 0 2 4 T T A = B = 8 0 3 1 0 4 4 6 5 0 B B Equivalent strategies: b ∈ E ( a ) 7/24

  11. Existing results II � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Example � a b c d e � a b c d e � � 2 6 9 1 7 4 4 0 2 4 T T A = B = 8 0 3 1 0 4 4 6 5 0 B B Equivalent strategies: b ∈ E ( a ) Weakly dominated strategy: e by a (or b ). 7/24

  12. Existing results II � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Example a b c d e a b c d e     2 6 9 1 7 4 4 0 2 4 T T ∗ 5 ∗ 4 A = 3 T + 2 1 6 2 1 2 . 3  B = 3 T + 2 1 4 4 4 1 . 3 3 B   3 B      8 0 3 1 0 4 4 6 5 0 B B Equivalent strategies: b ∈ E ( a ) Weakly dominated strategy: e by a (or b ). � x L , j F � �� � � with α L = 5 , β F = 4. 3 , 2 1 = , c 3 7/24

  13. Existing results II � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Example � a b c d e � a b c d e � � 2 6 9 1 7 4 4 0 2 4 T T A = B = 8 0 3 1 0 4 4 6 5 0 B B Equivalent strategies: b ∈ E ( a ) Weakly dominated strategy: e by a (or b ). � x L , j F � �� � � with α L = 5 , β F = 4. 1 3 , 2 = , c 3 � x H , j F � = ( T , e ) with α H = 7. 7/24

  14. Existing results III � Von Stengel & Zamir (2010). Theorem (2) If ℓ denotes the lowest and h the highest Nash equilibrium payoff of player I in Γ, then ℓ ≤ α L and h ≤ α H . So, in degenerate games with α L < α H v A ≤ ℓ ≤ α L , v A ≤ ℓ ≤ h ≤ α H which for non-degenerate games simplifies to v A ≤ ℓ ≤ h ≤ α L = α H . � Lower and upper bounds for Nash equilibria payoffs. � Based on these results, characterize the bimatrix games for which v A = α L = α H : accept Nash (e.g. 0-sum games) v A = h < α L : question Nash (e.g. Traveler’s Dilemma) 7/24

  15. Outline Motivation 1 Definitions – Existing results 2 Results 3 2 × 2 bimatrix games Weakly unilaterally competitive games General bimatrix games: pure & completely mixed equilibria Future Research 4 8/24

  16. Outline Motivation 1 Definitions – Existing results 2 Results 3 2 × 2 bimatrix games Weakly unilaterally competitive games General bimatrix games: pure & completely mixed equilibria Future Research 4 9/24

  17. 2 × 2 bimatrix games � Study small games. Proposition Let Γ be an arbitrary 2 × 2 bimatrix game. Then 1 at least one player commits to a Nash equilibrium strategy in the game at which he moves first. 2 each follower’s payoff is at least as good as some of his Nash equilibrium payoffs in the simultaneous move game (in all but a technical case). � Upshot: incentive to play the game sequentially with the specified order, not simultaneously. � Necessity of conditions: extension to higher dimensions was not possible. 10/24

  18. Outline Motivation 1 Definitions – Existing results 2 Results 3 2 × 2 bimatrix games Weakly unilaterally competitive games General bimatrix games: pure & completely mixed equilibria Future Research 4 11/24

  19. Back to the drawing board � Study specific classes of games. Definition A bimatrix game Γ is weakly unilaterally competitive, if for all x 1 , x 2 ∈ X and all y ∈ Y α ( x 1 , y ) > α ( x 2 , y ) = ⇒ β ( x 1 , y ) ≤ β ( x 2 , y ) α ( x 1 , y ) = α ( x 2 , y ) = ⇒ β ( x 1 , y ) = β ( x 2 , y ) and similarly if for all y 1 , y 2 ∈ Y and all x ∈ X . � Introduced by Kats and Thisse (1992). � Retain the flavor of pure antagonism: any unilateral (cf. pure conflict) deviation, that improves a player’s payoff, incurs a weak loss to opponent’s payoff. 12/24

  20. Weakly unilaterally competitive games � For wuc games, the three concepts coincide. Proposition In a (wuc) game Γ, the leader’s payoff at any subgame perfect equilibrium of the commitment game is equal to his commitment value which is equal to his matrix game value, i.e. v A = α L = α H v B = β L = β H and � Proof: Consequence of the definitions. � Upshot: no controversies on optimal behavior or solution in (wuc) games. Naturally generalize 0-sum games. � Necessity of conditions: property fails in other generalizations. � Property extends to N -player wuc games: v A is different. 13/24

  21. Outline Motivation 1 Definitions – Existing results 2 Results 3 2 × 2 bimatrix games Weakly unilaterally competitive games General bimatrix games: pure & completely mixed equilibria Future Research 4 14/24

  22. General bimatrix games I � Equilibria in pure strategies. Theorem (Part I) If the bimatrix game Γ is non-degenerate for player I , and I as a leader commits optimally to a pure strategy, then the resulting strategy profile coincides with a pure Nash equilibrium of Γ. � Upshot: to improve over all his Nash equilibria payoffs, the leader opti- mally commits to a mixed strategy. In line with concealment interpretation, von Neumann & Morgenstern (1953) and Reny & Robson (2004). � Necessity of conditions: Not true for degenerate. 15/24

  23. Sketch of the proof ǫ, i := (1 − ǫ ) · i L + ǫ · i . � Proof: geometric using x L (1 , 0 , 0) (1 , 0 , 0) X (2) X (1) X (2) X (1) (0 , 1 , 0) (0 , 0 , 1) (0 , 1 , 0) (0 , 0 , 1) 16/24

  24. Sketch of the proof ǫ, i := (1 − ǫ ) · i L + ǫ · i . � Proof: geometric using x L � Consider pure strategy i L = (1 , 0 , 0). (1 , 0 , 0) (1 , 0 , 0) X (2) X (1) X (2) X (1) (0 , 1 , 0) (0 , 0 , 1) (0 , 1 , 0) (0 , 0 , 1) 16/24

  25. Sketch of the proof ǫ, i := (1 − ǫ ) · i L + ǫ · i . � Proof: geometric using x L � Consider pure strategy i L = (1 , 0 , 0). (1 , 0 , 0) (1 , 0 , 0) X (2) X (1) X (2) X (1) (0 , 1 , 0) (0 , 0 , 1) (0 , 1 , 0) (0 , 0 , 1) Non-degenerate: x L ǫ, i ∈ X (2) for every i . If I chooses i L , then it must be Nash. 16/24

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend