modes of persuasion toward unanimous consent
play

Modes of Persuasion Toward Unanimous Consent Arjada Bardhi, Yingni - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Modes of Persuasion Toward Unanimous Consent Arjada Bardhi, Yingni Guo 1 1 Northwestern Jan 05 2018 Features A sender promotes a project to a group of voters. Voters decide collectively on approval through unanimity rule. Voters vary in:


  1. Model: Timing and modes of persuasion Sender designs R i observes s i and Nature draws θ ∼ f and signals ( s i ) n i =1 . chooses d i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . an information policy. We consider two classes of information policies: Individual policy ( π i ) n i =1 : General policy π : π : { H , L } n → ∆ (∏ n ) i =1 S i . π i : { H , L } → ∆ ( S i ) , ∀ i . 9 / 25

  2. Model: Modes of persuasion Without loss, we focus on direct obedient policies: 10 / 25

  3. Model: Modes of persuasion Without loss, we focus on direct obedient policies: ▶ S i = { 0 , 1 } for each R i . ▶ R i follows her action recommendation ˆ d i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . ▶ ˆ d = ( d 1 , ..., d n ) . 10 / 25

  4. Model: Modes of persuasion Without loss, we focus on direct obedient policies: ▶ S i = { 0 , 1 } for each R i . ▶ R i follows her action recommendation ˆ d i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . ▶ ˆ d = ( d 1 , ..., d n ) . General policy π : π : { H , L } n → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } n ). 10 / 25

  5. Model: Modes of persuasion Without loss, we focus on direct obedient policies: ▶ S i = { 0 , 1 } for each R i . ▶ R i follows her action recommendation ˆ d i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . ▶ ˆ d = ( d 1 , ..., d n ) . General policy π : π : { H , L } n → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } n ). ( π ( ·| θ )) θ ∈{ H , L } n 10 / 25

  6. Model: Modes of persuasion Without loss, we focus on direct obedient policies: ▶ S i = { 0 , 1 } for each R i . ▶ R i follows her action recommendation ˆ d i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . ▶ ˆ d = ( d 1 , ..., d n ) . Individual policy ( π i ) n i =1 : General policy π : π : { H , L } n → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } n ). π i : { H , L } → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } ) , ∀ i . ( π ( ·| θ )) θ ∈{ H , L } n 10 / 25

  7. Model: Modes of persuasion Without loss, we focus on direct obedient policies: ▶ S i = { 0 , 1 } for each R i . ▶ R i follows her action recommendation ˆ d i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . ▶ ˆ d = ( d 1 , ..., d n ) . Individual policy ( π i ) n i =1 : General policy π : π : { H , L } n → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } n ). π i : { H , L } → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } ) , ∀ i . ( π ( ·| θ )) θ ∈{ H , L } n ( π i ( H ) , π i ( L )) , ∀ i 10 / 25

  8. Model: Modes of persuasion Without loss, we focus on direct obedient policies: ▶ S i = { 0 , 1 } for each R i . ▶ R i follows her action recommendation ˆ d i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . ▶ ˆ d = ( d 1 , ..., d n ) . Individual policy ( π i ) n i =1 : General policy π : π : { H , L } n → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } n ). π i : { H , L } → ∆ ( { 0 , 1 } ) , ∀ i . ( π ( ·| θ )) θ ∈{ H , L } n ( π i ( H ) , π i ( L )) , ∀ i We allow for any policy that is the limit of full-support policies. We solve for the Sender-optimal policy. 10 / 25

  9. Roadmap . . Model 1 . . General persuasion 2 . . Individual persuasion 3

  10. General persuasion R i evaluates her payoff conditional on her vote being pivotal: 11 / 25

  11. General persuasion R i evaluates her payoff conditional on her vote being pivotal: ▶ ˆ d a : all voters receive an approval recommendation. 11 / 25

  12. General persuasion R i evaluates her payoff conditional on her vote being pivotal: ▶ ˆ d a : all voters receive an approval recommendation. R i ’s posterior belief of being H is: i f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ d a | θ ) θ ∈ Θ H Pr( θ i = H | ˆ d a ) = . θ ∈{ H , L } n f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ d a | θ ) 11 / 25

  13. General persuasion R i evaluates her payoff conditional on her vote being pivotal: ▶ ˆ d a : all voters receive an approval recommendation. R i ’s posterior belief of being H is: i f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ d a | θ ) θ ∈ Θ H Pr( θ i = H | ˆ d a ) = . θ ∈{ H , L } n f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ d a | θ ) R i obeys an approval recommendation iff: ℓ i Pr( θ i = H | ˆ d a ) ⩾ . 1 + ℓ i 11 / 25

  14. General persuasion Sender’s problem is: 12 / 25

  15. General persuasion Sender’s problem is: f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ d a | θ ) max π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ⩾ 0 θ ∈{ H , L } n 12 / 25

  16. General persuasion Sender’s problem is: f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ d a | θ ) max π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ⩾ 0 θ ∈{ H , L } n s.t. π ( ˆ d a | θ ) − 1 ⩽ 0 , ∀ θ, 12 / 25

  17. General persuasion Sender’s problem is: f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ d a | θ ) max π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ⩾ 0 θ ∈{ H , L } n s.t. π ( ˆ d a | θ ) − 1 ⩽ 0 , ∀ θ, ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ℓ i − d a | θ ) ⩽ 0 , ∀ i . θ ∈ Θ L θ ∈ Θ H i i 12 / 25

  18. . . . Optimal policy under perfect correlation Only ( H .. H ) and ( L .. L ) are possible to realize. 13 / 25

  19. . . . Optimal policy under perfect correlation Only ( H .. H ) and ( L .. L ) are possible to realize. Due to perfect correlation, all voters share the same Pr( θ i = H | ˆ d a ). 13 / 25

  20. . . . Optimal policy under perfect correlation Only ( H .. H ) and ( L .. L ) are possible to realize. Due to perfect correlation, all voters share the same Pr( θ i = H | ˆ d a ). R 1 imposes the highest cutoff on this belief: ℓ 1 Pr( θ 1 = H | ˆ d a ) ⩾ . 1 + ℓ 1 13 / 25

  21. . . . Optimal policy under perfect correlation Only ( H .. H ) and ( L .. L ) are possible to realize. Due to perfect correlation, all voters share the same Pr( θ i = H | ˆ d a ). R 1 imposes the highest cutoff on this belief: ℓ 1 Pr( θ 1 = H | ˆ d a ) ⩾ . 1 + ℓ 1 This is as if Sender were facing R 1 alone. 13 / 25

  22. Optimal policy under perfect correlation Only ( H .. H ) and ( L .. L ) are possible to realize. Due to perfect correlation, all voters share the same Pr( θ i = H | ˆ d a ). R 1 imposes the highest cutoff on this belief: ℓ 1 Pr( θ 1 = H | ˆ d a ) ⩾ . 1 + ℓ 1 This is as if Sender were facing R 1 alone. . Proposition: . Suppose voters’ states are perfectly correlated. The unique optimal policy is d a | L .. L ) = f ( H .. H ) 1 π ( ˆ π ( ˆ d a | H .. H ) = 1 , . f ( L .. L ) ℓ 1 Only R 1 ’s IC binds. . 13 / 25

  23. . . . Imperfect correlation: Under unanimity, a binding IC is equivalent to a zero payoff. 14 / 25

  24. Imperfect correlation: Strictest voters’ ICs bind . Proposition: . In any optimal policy, the IC constraints for a subgroup of the strictest voters bind, i.e. IC binds for i ∈ { 1 , ..., i ′ } for some i ′ ⩾ 1 . . Under unanimity, a binding IC is equivalent to a zero payoff. 14 / 25

  25. Imperfect correlation: Strictest voters’ ICs bind . Proposition: . In any optimal policy, the IC constraints for a subgroup of the strictest voters bind, i.e. IC binds for i ∈ { 1 , ..., i ′ } for some i ′ ⩾ 1 . . Under unanimity, a binding IC is equivalent to a zero payoff. Examine the dual of the linear programming problem. 14 / 25

  26. The dual problem Sender’s problem is: ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ d a | θ ) max π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ⩾ 0 θ ∈{ H , L } n s.t. π ( ˆ d a | θ ) − 1 ⩽ 0 , ∀ θ, ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ℓ i − d a | θ ) ⩽ 0 , ∀ i . θ ∈ Θ L θ ∈ Θ H i i 15 / 25

  27. The dual problem Sender’s problem is: ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ d a | θ ) max π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ⩾ 0 θ ∈{ H , L } n s.t. π ( ˆ d a | θ ) − 1 ⩽ 0 , ∀ θ, ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ℓ i − d a | θ ) ⩽ 0 , ∀ i . θ ∈ Θ L θ ∈ Θ H i i Let γ θ , µ i be the dual variables. 15 / 25

  28. The dual problem Sender’s problem is: ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ d a | θ ) max π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ⩾ 0 θ ∈{ H , L } n s.t. π ( ˆ d a | θ ) − 1 ⩽ 0 , ∀ θ, ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ ∑ f ( θ ) π ( ˆ d a | θ ) ℓ i − d a | θ ) ⩽ 0 , ∀ i . θ ∈ Θ L θ ∈ Θ H i i Let γ θ , µ i be the dual variables. The dual problem is: ∑ min γ θ , γ θ ⩾ 0 ,µ i ⩾ 0 θ ∈{ H , L } n ( ) ∑ ∑ s.t. γ θ ⩾ f ( θ ) 1 + µ i − µ i ℓ i , ∀ θ. i : θ i = H i : θ i = L 15 / 25

  29. Imperfect correlation: . Proposition: . In any optimal policy, the IC constraints for a subgroup of the strictest voters bind, i.e. IC binds for i ∈ { 1 , ..., i ′ } for some i ′ ⩾ 1 . . Under unanimity, a binding IC is equivalent to a zero payoff. Examine the dual of the linear programming problem. 16 / 25

  30. Imperfect correlation: The strictest voters’ ICs bind . Proposition: . In any optimal policy, the IC constraints for a subgroup of the strictest voters bind, i.e. IC binds for i ∈ { 1 , ..., i ′ } for some i ′ ⩾ 1 . . Under unanimity, a binding IC is equivalent to a zero payoff. Examine the dual of the linear programming problem. Think of each IC as a “resource constraint.” 16 / 25

  31. Imperfect correlation: The strictest voters’ ICs bind . Proposition: . In any optimal policy, the IC constraints for a subgroup of the strictest voters bind, i.e. IC binds for i ∈ { 1 , ..., i ′ } for some i ′ ⩾ 1 . . Under unanimity, a binding IC is equivalent to a zero payoff. Examine the dual of the linear programming problem. Think of each IC as a “resource constraint.” Granting surplus to a tough voter is more expensive than to a lenient one. 16 / 25

  32. Roadmap . . Model 1 . . General persuasion 2 . . Individual persuasion 3

  33. Individual persuasion Sender designs ( π i ( H ) , π i ( L )) for each R i . 17 / 25

  34. Individual persuasion Sender designs ( π i ( H ) , π i ( L )) for each R i . Let Pr( θ i = H | R − i approve) denote the probability that θ i = H conditional on R − i approving: ∑ i f ( θ ) ∏ j ̸ = i π j ( θ j ) θ ∈ Θ H Pr( θ i = H | R − i approve) = j ̸ = i π j ( θ j ) . ∑ θ ∈{ H , L } n f ( θ ) ∏ 17 / 25

  35. Individual persuasion Sender designs ( π i ( H ) , π i ( L )) for each R i . Let Pr( θ i = H | R − i approve) denote the probability that θ i = H conditional on R − i approving: ∑ i f ( θ ) ∏ j ̸ = i π j ( θ j ) θ ∈ Θ H Pr( θ i = H | R − i approve) = j ̸ = i π j ( θ j ) . ∑ θ ∈{ H , L } n f ( θ ) ∏ R i obeys an approval recommendation if: Pr( θ i = H | R − i approve) π i ( H ) − ℓ i Pr( θ i = L | R − i approve) π i ( L ) ⩾ 0 . 17 / 25

  36. Individual persuasion R i ’s approval IC is easily written as: ℓ i π i ( L ) Pr( θ i = H | R − i approve) ⩾ ℓ i π i ( L ) + π i ( H ) . 18 / 25

  37. Individual persuasion R i ’s approval IC is easily written as: ℓ i π i ( L ) Pr( θ i = H | R − i approve) ⩾ ℓ i π i ( L ) + π i ( H ) . Sender chooses ( π i ( H ) , π i ( L )) n i =1 to maximize his payoff: ∑ ∏ f ( θ ) π i ( θ i ) , θ i subject to the approval ICs. 18 / 25

  38. Optimal policy under perfect correlation . Proposition: . Suppose voters’ states are perfectly correlated. Any optimal policy is of the form: π i ( H ) = 1 for all i , π i ( L ) = f ( H .. H ) 1 ( π 1 ( L ) , ..., π n ( L )) ∈ [0 , 1] n such that ∏ . f ( L .. L ) ℓ 1 . i 19 / 25

  39. Example 1: Binding ICs for all voters 20 / 25

  40. Example 1: Binding ICs for all voters The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . 20 / 25

  41. Example 1: Binding ICs for all voters The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . The voters are relatively homogeneous in their thresholds of doubt. 20 / 25

  42. Example 1: Binding ICs for all voters The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . The voters are relatively homogeneous in their thresholds of doubt. The optimal policy is: ( π 1 ( L ) , π 2 ( L ) , π 3 ( L )) = (0 . 071 , 0 . 073 , 0 . 075) . 20 / 25

  43. Example 1: Binding ICs for all voters The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . The voters are relatively homogeneous in their thresholds of doubt. The optimal policy is: ( π 1 ( L ) , π 2 ( L ) , π 3 ( L )) = (0 . 071 , 0 . 073 , 0 . 075) . All three IC constraints bind. 20 / 25

  44. Example 2: Rubber-stamping behavior 21 / 25

  45. Example 2: Rubber-stamping behavior The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 2) . 21 / 25

  46. Example 2: Rubber-stamping behavior The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 2) . R 3 becomes much more lenient than before. 21 / 25

  47. Example 2: Rubber-stamping behavior The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 2) . R 3 becomes much more lenient than before. The optimal policy is: ( π 1 ( L ) , π 2 ( L ) , π 3 ( L )) = (0 . 038 , 0 . 039 , 1) . 21 / 25

  48. Example 2: Rubber-stamping behavior The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 9 50 , f ( HHL ) = 1 20 , f ( HLL ) = 2 25 , f ( LLL ) = 43 100 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 2) . R 3 becomes much more lenient than before. The optimal policy is: ( π 1 ( L ) , π 2 ( L ) , π 3 ( L )) = (0 . 038 , 0 . 039 , 1) . R 3 rubber-stamps the others’ approval decisions, obtaining a positive payoff. 21 / 25

  49. Example 3: Truthful recommendation 22 / 25

  50. Example 3: Truthful recommendation The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 6 1 750 , f ( LLL ) = 18 7 25 , f ( HHL ) = 250 , f ( HLL ) = 25 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . 22 / 25

  51. Example 3: Truthful recommendation The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 6 1 750 , f ( LLL ) = 18 7 25 , f ( HHL ) = 250 , f ( HLL ) = 25 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . The correlation is stronger compared to Example 1. 22 / 25

  52. Example 3: Truthful recommendation The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 6 1 750 , f ( LLL ) = 18 7 25 , f ( HHL ) = 250 , f ( HLL ) = 25 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . The correlation is stronger compared to Example 1. The optimal policy is: ( π 1 ( L ) , π 2 ( L ) , π 3 ( L )) = (0 , 0 . 606 , 0 . 644) . 22 / 25

  53. Example 3: Truthful recommendation The distribution over state profiles is: f ( HHH ) = 6 1 750 , f ( LLL ) = 18 7 25 , f ( HHL ) = 250 , f ( HLL ) = 25 . The thresholds of doubt are: ( ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 ) = (41 , 40 , 39) . The correlation is stronger compared to Example 1. The optimal policy is: ( π 1 ( L ) , π 2 ( L ) , π 3 ( L )) = (0 , 0 . 606 , 0 . 644) . R 1 learns her state perfectly. The only slack IC is R 1 ’s IC. 22 / 25

  54. Monotonicity of persuasion . Proposition: . There exists an optimal policy in which the approval probability in low state weakly decreases in the threshold of doubt: π i ( L ) ⩽ π i +1 ( L ) for all i ∈ { 1 , ..., n − 1 } . Moreover, in any optimal policy in which R i ’s IC binds, π i ( L ) > π j ( L ) for all j ∈ { 1 , 2 , ..., i − 1 } . . 23 / 25

  55. Monotonicity of persuasion . Proposition: . There exists an optimal policy in which the approval probability in low state weakly decreases in the threshold of doubt: π i ( L ) ⩽ π i +1 ( L ) for all i ∈ { 1 , ..., n − 1 } . Moreover, in any optimal policy in which R i ’s IC binds, π i ( L ) > π j ( L ) for all j ∈ { 1 , 2 , ..., i − 1 } . . More demanding voters’ policies are more informative. 23 / 25

  56. Monotonicity of persuasion . Proposition: . There exists an optimal policy in which the approval probability in low state weakly decreases in the threshold of doubt: π i ( L ) ⩽ π i +1 ( L ) for all i ∈ { 1 , ..., n − 1 } . Moreover, in any optimal policy in which R i ’s IC binds, π i ( L ) > π j ( L ) for all j ∈ { 1 , 2 , ..., i − 1 } . . More demanding voters’ policies are more informative. Voters are divided into three subgroups: 23 / 25

  57. Monotonicity of persuasion . Proposition: . There exists an optimal policy in which the approval probability in low state weakly decreases in the threshold of doubt: π i ( L ) ⩽ π i +1 ( L ) for all i ∈ { 1 , ..., n − 1 } . Moreover, in any optimal policy in which R i ’s IC binds, π i ( L ) > π j ( L ) for all j ∈ { 1 , 2 , ..., i − 1 } . . More demanding voters’ policies are more informative. Voters are divided into three subgroups: perfectly informed partially manipulated rubber-stampers π i ( L ) = 0 π i ( L ) ∈ (0 , 1) π i ( L ) = 1 23 / 25

  58. When do some voters learn their states perfectly? ω ∈ { G , B } such that Pr( ω = G ) = p 0 . Pr( H | G ) = Pr( L | B ) = λ 1 ∈ [1 / 2 , 1]. ℓ i = ℓ for all i . λ 1 1 ℓ 1 λ ∗ ℓ +1 1 2 � �� � � �� � � �� � no truthful revelation truthful revelation to some voters no truthful revelation one partially informed voter π 1 ( L ) ∈ (0 , 1) π i ( L ) = π j ( L ) ∈ (0 , 1) ∀ i, j the rest rubber-stamp the rest rubber-stamp 24 / 25

  59. Concluding remarks We explore group persuasion in the context of unanimity rule, affiliated payoff states and heterogeneous thresholds of doubt. We compare two modes of persuasion: general and individual persuasion. General persuasion makes the strictest voters indifferent. Individual persuasion divides the group into perfectly-informed voters, partially-informed voters, and rubber-stampers. Under non-unanimous rules, general persuasion leads to certain approval, while individual persuasion does not. Future work: ▶ Non-unanimous rules under individual persuasion. ▶ Communication among voters. ▶ Sequential persuasion. 25 / 25

  60. Thank you!

  61. Independent states under general persuasion Three voters’ states are drawn independently. Each voter’s state is H with probability 19 / 20. The threshold profile is { ℓ 1 , ℓ 2 , ℓ 3 } = { 41 , 40 , 20 } . One optimal policy is π ( ˆ d a | θ ) = 1 for θ ∈ { HHH , HHL } , d a | LHH ) = 820 d a | HLH ) = 840 π ( ˆ π ( ˆ 1639 , 1639 , π ( ˆ d a | θ ) = 0 for θ ∈ { HLL , LLH , LHL , LLL } . R 1 ’s and R 2 ’s IC constraints bind. R 3 ’s does not. Back .

  62. k < n votes: Independent general persuasion Each voter’s recommendation is drawn independently conditional on the state profile. We can construct a certain approval policy which is the limit of a sequence of full-support policies. For state profiles with k high-state voters, these voters are recommended to approve. The low-state voters are recommended to reject. In all other state profiles, all voters are recommended to approve. When R i receives an approval recommendation and conditions on being pivotal, she believes that her state is high.

  63. k < n votes: Certain approval under IGP . Proposition: . Under independent general persuasion, Sender’s payoff is one. . This strengthens the previous result by showing that Sender achieves a certain approval even when constrained to independent general persuasion. The voters impose no check on Sender if Sender is allowed to condition on the entire state profile.

  64. Roadmap . . Model 1 . . General persuasion 2 . . Individual persuasion 3 . . Extensions: 4 ▶ Public and sequential persuasion ▶ Non-unanimous rule

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend