measuring together with the continuum large
play

Measuring together with the continuum large Miguel Angel Mota (ITAM) - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Measuring together with the continuum large Miguel Angel Mota (ITAM) Joint work with David Asper o III Arctic Set Theory Meeting Definition Measuring holds if and only if for every sequence C = ( C : 1 ) , if each C is a


  1. Measuring together with the continuum large Miguel Angel Mota (ITAM) Joint work with David Asper´ o III Arctic Set Theory Meeting

  2. Definition Measuring holds if and only if for every sequence � C = ( C δ : δ ∈ ω 1 ) , if each C δ is a closed subset of δ in the order topology, then there is a club C ⊆ ω 1 such that for every δ ∈ C there is some α < δ such that either • ( C ∩ δ ) \ α ⊆ C δ , or • ( C \ α ) ∩ C δ = ∅ . That is, a tail of ( C ∩ δ ) is either contained in or disjoint from C δ . This principle is of course equivalent to its restriction to club-sequences � C on ω 1 . Measuring is a strong form of failure of Club Guessing at ω 1 . Measuring follows from BPFA and also from MRP .

  3. Definition Measuring holds if and only if for every sequence � C = ( C δ : δ ∈ ω 1 ) , if each C δ is a closed subset of δ in the order topology, then there is a club C ⊆ ω 1 such that for every δ ∈ C there is some α < δ such that either • ( C ∩ δ ) \ α ⊆ C δ , or • ( C \ α ) ∩ C δ = ∅ . That is, a tail of ( C ∩ δ ) is either contained in or disjoint from C δ . This principle is of course equivalent to its restriction to club-sequences � C on ω 1 . Measuring is a strong form of failure of Club Guessing at ω 1 . Measuring follows from BPFA and also from MRP .

  4. Definition Measuring holds if and only if for every sequence � C = ( C δ : δ ∈ ω 1 ) , if each C δ is a closed subset of δ in the order topology, then there is a club C ⊆ ω 1 such that for every δ ∈ C there is some α < δ such that either • ( C ∩ δ ) \ α ⊆ C δ , or • ( C \ α ) ∩ C δ = ∅ . That is, a tail of ( C ∩ δ ) is either contained in or disjoint from C δ . This principle is of course equivalent to its restriction to club-sequences � C on ω 1 . Measuring is a strong form of failure of Club Guessing at ω 1 . Measuring follows from BPFA and also from MRP .

  5. Definition Measuring holds if and only if for every sequence � C = ( C δ : δ ∈ ω 1 ) , if each C δ is a closed subset of δ in the order topology, then there is a club C ⊆ ω 1 such that for every δ ∈ C there is some α < δ such that either • ( C ∩ δ ) \ α ⊆ C δ , or • ( C \ α ) ∩ C δ = ∅ . That is, a tail of ( C ∩ δ ) is either contained in or disjoint from C δ . This principle is of course equivalent to its restriction to club-sequences � C on ω 1 . Measuring is a strong form of failure of Club Guessing at ω 1 . Measuring follows from BPFA and also from MRP .

  6. Theorem (CH) Let κ be a cardinal such that 2 <κ = κ and κ ℵ 1 = κ . There is then a partial order P with the following properties. 1 P is proper. 2 P is ℵ 2 –Knaster. 3 P forces measuring. 4 P forces 2 ℵ 0 = 2 ℵ 1 = κ . 5 P forces b ( ω 1 ) = cf ( κ ) Recall that a poset is ℵ 2 –Knaster iff every collection of ℵ 2 –many conditions contains a subcollection of cardinality ℵ 2 consisting of pairwise compatible cond. Also, b ( ω 1 ) denotes the minimal cardinality of an unbounded subset of ω 1 ω 1 mod. countable.

  7. Theorem (CH) Let κ be a cardinal such that 2 <κ = κ and κ ℵ 1 = κ . There is then a partial order P with the following properties. 1 P is proper. 2 P is ℵ 2 –Knaster. 3 P forces measuring. 4 P forces 2 ℵ 0 = 2 ℵ 1 = κ . 5 P forces b ( ω 1 ) = cf ( κ ) Recall that a poset is ℵ 2 –Knaster iff every collection of ℵ 2 –many conditions contains a subcollection of cardinality ℵ 2 consisting of pairwise compatible cond. Also, b ( ω 1 ) denotes the minimal cardinality of an unbounded subset of ω 1 ω 1 mod. countable.

  8. The theorem will be proved by means of what can be described as a finite support iteration incorporating systems of ctble. struct. with symmetry requirements as side cond. In fact, our forcing P will be P κ , where P κ is the last step of this iteration. The actual construction is a variation of previous works. There are 2 main new ingredients in our present construction. Specifically, at any given stage β < κ of the iteration, (a) the set N q β of models N that are active at that stage, in the sense that β ∈ N and that the marker associated to N at that stage is β , is actually a T –symmetric system (for a suitable predicate T ), and (b) if β = α + 1, we use a separate symmetric system in the working part at α included in the above symmetric system corresponding to the previous stage, i.e., in N q α ; these are the symmetric systems we will denote by O q ,α .

  9. The theorem will be proved by means of what can be described as a finite support iteration incorporating systems of ctble. struct. with symmetry requirements as side cond. In fact, our forcing P will be P κ , where P κ is the last step of this iteration. The actual construction is a variation of previous works. There are 2 main new ingredients in our present construction. Specifically, at any given stage β < κ of the iteration, (a) the set N q β of models N that are active at that stage, in the sense that β ∈ N and that the marker associated to N at that stage is β , is actually a T –symmetric system (for a suitable predicate T ), and (b) if β = α + 1, we use a separate symmetric system in the working part at α included in the above symmetric system corresponding to the previous stage, i.e., in N q α ; these are the symmetric systems we will denote by O q ,α .

  10. This use of local symmetry is crucial in the verification that measuring holds in the final generic extension. Specifically, it is needed in the verification that the generic club C added at a stage α will be such that for every δ ∈ Lim ( ω 1 ) , a tail of C ∩ δ will be contained in C δ in case we could not make the promise of avoiding C δ (where C δ is the δ –indexed member of the club–sequence picked at stage α ).

  11. In a paper from the 80’s, Abraham and Shelah build, given any cardinal λ ≥ ℵ 2 , a forcing notion P which, if CH holds, preserves cardinals and is such that if G is P –generic over V , then in V [ G ] there is a family C of size λ consisting of clubs of ω 1 and with the property that, in any outer model M of V [ G ] with the same ω 1 and ω 2 as V [ G ] , there is no club E of ω 1 in M diagonalising C (where E diagonalising C means that E \ D is bounded in ω 1 for each D ∈ C ). CH necessarily fails in the Abraham–Shelah model V [ G ] since, by a result of Galvin, CH implies that for every family C of size ℵ 2 consisting of clubs of ω 1 there is an uncountable C ′ ⊆ C such that � C ′ is a club.

  12. It is not difficult to see that the generic club added at every stage α < κ of our iteration diagonalises all clubs of ω 1 from V [ G α ] (where G α is the generic filter at that stage). So, it would be impossible to run anything like our iteration over the Abraham–Shelah model without collapsing ω 2 , and therefore we should start from a ground model which is sufficiently different from the Abraham–Shelah model. That is accomplished by imposing that CH must be true in our ground model. Question: Is it consistent to have measuring together with b ( ω 1 ) = ℵ 2 and 2 ℵ 1 > ℵ 2 ?. Important problem: Is measuring compatible with CH?

  13. It is not difficult to see that the generic club added at every stage α < κ of our iteration diagonalises all clubs of ω 1 from V [ G α ] (where G α is the generic filter at that stage). So, it would be impossible to run anything like our iteration over the Abraham–Shelah model without collapsing ω 2 , and therefore we should start from a ground model which is sufficiently different from the Abraham–Shelah model. That is accomplished by imposing that CH must be true in our ground model. Question: Is it consistent to have measuring together with b ( ω 1 ) = ℵ 2 and 2 ℵ 1 > ℵ 2 ?. Important problem: Is measuring compatible with CH?

  14. It is not difficult to see that the generic club added at every stage α < κ of our iteration diagonalises all clubs of ω 1 from V [ G α ] (where G α is the generic filter at that stage). So, it would be impossible to run anything like our iteration over the Abraham–Shelah model without collapsing ω 2 , and therefore we should start from a ground model which is sufficiently different from the Abraham–Shelah model. That is accomplished by imposing that CH must be true in our ground model. Question: Is it consistent to have measuring together with b ( ω 1 ) = ℵ 2 and 2 ℵ 1 > ℵ 2 ?. Important problem: Is measuring compatible with CH?

  15. Notation. if N ∩ ω 1 ∈ ω 1 , then δ N := N ∩ ω 1 . Definition Let T ⊆ H ( θ ) and let N be a finite set of countable subsets of H ( θ ) . We will say that N is a T–symmetric system iff ( A ) For every N ∈ N , ( N , ∈ , T ) ≺ ( H ( θ ) , ∈ , T ) . ( B ) Given distinct N , N ′ in N , if δ N = δ N ′ , then there is a unique isomorphism → ( N ′ , ∈ , T ) Ψ N , N ′ : ( N , ∈ , T ) − Furthermore, Ψ N , N ′ is the identity on N ∩ N ′ . ( C ) N is closed under isomorphisms. That is, for all N , N ′ , M in N , if M ∈ N and δ N = δ N ′ , then Ψ N , N ′ ( M ) ∈ N . ( D ) For all N , M in N , if δ M < δ N , then there is some N ′ ∈ N such that δ N ′ = δ N and M ∈ N ′ .

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend