ma csse 474 theory of computation
play

MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation Bottom-up parsing Pumping - PDF document

MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation Bottom-up parsing Pumping Theorem for CFLs Recap: Going One Way Lemma : Each context-free language is accepted by some PDA. Proof (by construction): The idea: Let the stack do the work. Two approaches:


  1. MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation Bottom-up parsing Pumping Theorem for CFLs Recap: Going One Way Lemma : Each context-free language is accepted by some PDA. Proof (by construction): The idea: Let the stack do the work. Two approaches: • Top down • Bottom up

  2. Top-down VS Bottom-up Approach Top-down Bottom-up left-to-right left-to-right Read the input string leftmost rightmost Derivation forward backward Order of derivation discovery Bottom-Up PDA The outline of M is: M = ({ p , q },  , V ,  , p , { q }), where  contains: ● The shift transitions: (( p , c ,  ), ( p , c )), for each c   . ● The reduce transitions: (( p ,  , ( s 1 s 2 … s n .) R ), ( p , X )), for each rule X  s 1 s 2 … s n . in G . Undoes an application of this rule. ● The finish-up transition: (( p ,  , S ), ( q ,  )). Top-down parser discovers a leftmost derivation of the input string (If any). Bottom-up parser discovers a rightmost derivation (in reverse order)

  3. Bottom-Up PDA The idea: Let the stack keep track of what has been found. Discover a rightmost derivation in reverse order. (1) E  E + T Start with the string of terminals and attempt to (2) E  T "pull it back" (reduce) to S. (3) T  T  F (4) T  F (5) F  ( E ) (6) F  id Shift Transitions: (7) ( p , id,  ), ( p , id) Reduce Transitions: (8) ( p , (,  ), ( p , () (1) ( p ,  , T + E ), ( p , E ) (9) ( p , ),  ), ( p , )) (2) ( p ,  , T ), ( p , E ) Example: (10) ( p , +,  ), ( p , +) (3) ( p ,  , F  T ), ( p , T ) id + id * id (11) ( p ,  ,  ), ( p ,  ) (4) ( p ,  , F ), ( p , T ) (5) ( p ,  , ) E ( ), ( p , F ) When the right side of a production is (6) ( p ,  , id), ( p , F ) on the top of the stack, we can replace it by the left side of that production… …or not! That's where the nondeterminism comes in: choice between shift and reduce; choice between two reductions. Hidden during class, revealed later: Solution to bottom-up example A bottom-up parser is sometimes called a shift-reduce parser. Show how it works on id + id * id State stack remaining input transition to use p  id + id * id 7 p id + id * id 6 p F + id * id 4 p T + id * id 2 p E + id * id 10 p +E id * id 7 p id+E * id 6 p F+E * id 4 p T+E * id 11 p *T+E id 7 p id*T+E  6 p F*T+E  3 p T+E  1 p E  0 q   Note that the top of the stack is on the left. This is what I should have done in the class for sections 1 and 2 (and I did do it for section 3).

  4. Acceptance by PDA  derived from CFG • Much more complex than the other direction. • Nonterminals in the grammar that we build from the PDA M are based on a combination of M's states and stack symbols. • It gets very messy. • Takes 9½ dense pages in the textbook (265-274). • I think we can use our limited course time better. How Many Context-Free Languages Are There? (we had a slide just like this for regular languages) Theorem: For any finite input alphabet Σ , there is a countably infinite number of CFLs over Σ . Proof: ● Upper bound: we can lexicographically enumerate all the CFGs. ● Lower bound: Each of {a}, {aa}, {aaa}, … is a CFL. The number of languages over Σ is uncountable. Thus there are more languages than there are context- free languages. So there must be some languages that are not context- free .

  5. Languages That Are and Are Not Context-Free a * b * is regular. A n B n = { a n b n : n  0} is context-free but not regular. A n B n C n = { a n b n c n : n  0} is not context-free. We will show this soon. Is every regular language also context-free? Showing that L is Context-Free Techniques for showing that a language L is context-free: 1. Exhibit a CFG for L . 2. Exhibit a PDA for L . 3. Use the closure properties of context-free languages. Unfortunately, these are weaker than they are for regular languages. union, reverse, concatenation, Kleene star intersection of a CFL with a regular language NOT intersection, complement, set difference

  6. CFL Pumping Theorem Show that L is Not Context-Free Recall the basis for the pumping theorem for regular languages: A DFSM M. If a string is longer than the number of M's states… Why would it be hard to use a PDA to show that long strings from a CFL can be pumped?

  7. Some Tree Geometry Basics The height h of a tree is the length of the longest path from the root to any leaf. The branching factor b of a tree is the largest number of children associated with any node in the tree . Theorem: The length of the yield (concatenation of leaf nodes) of any tree T with height h and branching factor b is  b h . Shown in CSSE 230. A Review of Parse Trees A parse tree , (a.k.a. derivation tree ) derived from a grammar G = ( V ,  , R , S ), is a rooted, ordered tree in which: ● Every leaf node is labeled with an element of   {  }, ● The root node is labeled S , ● Every interior node is labeled with an element of N (i.e., V -  ), ● If m is a non-leaf node labeled X and the children of m (left-to-right on the tree) are labeled x 1 , x 2 , …, x n , then the rule X  x 1 x 2 … x n is in R .

  8. From Grammars to Trees Given a context-free grammar G : ● Let n be the number of nonterminal symbols in G . ● Let b be the branching factor of G Suppose that a tree T is generated by G and no nonterminal appears more than once on any path from the root: The maximum height of T is: The maximum length of T ’s yield is: The Context-Free Pumping Theorem We use parse trees, not machines, as the basis for our argument. Let L = L(G), and let w  L. Let T be a parse tree for w such that has the smallest possible number of nodes among all trees based on a derivation of w from G. Suppose L(G) contains a string w such that | w| is greater than b n . Then its parse tree must look like (for some nonterminal X): X[1] is the lowest place in the tree for which this happens. I.e., there is no other X in the derivation of x from X[2].

  9. The Context-Free Pumping Theorem Derivation of w There is another derivation in G : S  * uXz  * uxz , in which, at X[1], the nonrecursive rule that leads to x is used instead of the recursive one that leads to vXy. So uxz is also in L ( G ). The Context-Free Pumping Theorem There are infinitely many derivations in G , such as: S  * uXz  * uvXyz  * uvvXyyz  * uvvxyyz Those derivations produce the strings: uv 2 xy 2 z , uv 3 xy 3 z , uv 4 xy 4 z , … So all of those strings are also in L ( G ).

  10. The Context-Free Pumping Theorem If rule 1 is X  X a , we could have v =  . If rule 1 is X  a X , we could have y =  . But it is not possible that both v and y are  . If they were, then the derivation S  * uXz  * uxz would also yield w and it would create a parse tree with fewer nodes. But that contradicts the assumption that we started with a parse tree for w with the smallest possible number of nodes. The Context-Free Pumping Theorem The height of the subtree rooted at [1] is at most: So | vxy |  .

  11. The Context-Free Pumping Theorem Write it in contrapositive If L is a context-free language, then form. Try to  k  1 (  strings w  L , where | w |  k do this before (  u , v , x , y , z ( w = uvxyz , going on. vy   , | vxy |  k, and  q  0 ( uv q xy q z is in L )))). Pumping Theorem contrapositive • We want to write it in contrapositive form, so we can use it to show a language is NOT context-free. Original: If L is a context-free language, then  k  1 (  strings w  L , where | w |  k (  u , v , x , y , z ( w = uvxyz , vy   , | vxy |  k, and  q  0 ( uv q xy q z is in L )))). Contrapositive: If  k  1 (  string w  L , where | w |  k (  u , v , x , y , z ( w = uvxyz , vy   , | vxy |  k, and  q  0 ( uv q xy q z is not in L )))), then L is not a CFL.

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend