large cardinals in mathematics and infinite combinatorics
play

Large cardinals in mathematics and infinite combinatorics Vincenzo - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Large cardinals in mathematics and infinite combinatorics Vincenzo Dimonte 11 November 2015 1 / 53 Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms A


  1. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Large cardinals in mathematics and infinite combinatorics Vincenzo Dimonte 11 November 2015 1 / 53

  2. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms A point of view: the development of mathematics is driven by a search for completion. The integers are developed for completing the natural numbers under substraction. The rationals are developed for completing the integers under division. The reals are developed for completing the rationals under Cauchy sequences. The complex numbers are developed for completing the reals under square roots. 2 / 53

  3. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms What about counting? ∞ ∞ + 1 0 1 2 3 4 5 . . . There are some psychological studies that indicates that the concept of ”infinity plus one” is natural for children Monaghan, John (2001). ”Young Peoples’ Ideas of Infinity”. Educational Studies in Mathematics 48 (2): 239–257 In mathematics: uniqueness of an expansion of a function in a trigonometric series. 3 / 53

  4. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Theorem (Cantor, 1870) Suppose + ∞ � a 0 / 2 + ( a n cos nx + b n sin nx ) = 0 for any x ∈ R . n =1 Then a n = b n = 0. In trying to extend this results (weakening the hypothesis from ∀ x ), Cantor arrived to this definition: 4 / 53

  5. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Definition (Cantor, 1872) Let S be a set of reals. Then S ′ = { x ∈ S : x is a limit point of S } . Define by induction: • S (0) = S ′ ; • S ( n +1) = S ( n ) ′ ; • S ( ∞ ) = � n ∈ N S ( n ) . But maybe S ( ∞ ) has some isolated points... • S ( ∞ +1) = S ( ∞ ) ′ . . . 5 / 53

  6. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms 6 / 53

  7. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Definition (Cantor, 1883) Two ordered sets ( S , ≤ S ) and ( T , ≤ T ) have the same order type if there is an order isomorphism between them, i.e., ∃ f : S → T bijective such that x ≤ S y iff f ( x ) ≤ T f ( y ). α is an ordinal number if it’s the order type of a well-ordered set (i.e., linear without infinite descending chains). 7 / 53

  8. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms 1 8 / 53

  9. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms 2 9 / 53

  10. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms 3 10 / 53

  11. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ∞ 11 / 53

  12. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ω 12 / 53

  13. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ω + 1 13 / 53

  14. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ω + 2 14 / 53

  15. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ω + ω = ω · 2 15 / 53

  16. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ω + ω + ω = ω · 3 16 / 53

  17. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ω · ω (the order type of the Sieve of Eratosthenes) 17 / 53

  18. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms ω · ω 18 / 53

  19. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms But wait a minute... ω + 1 is after ω , but it’s not bigger! Definition(Cantor, 1874-1884) Two sets have the same cardinality if there is a bijection between them. κ is a cardinal number if it is the cardinality of an ordinal number. ω is both a cardinal and an ordinal number. When we use it as a cardinal, we call it ℵ 0 . There is a bijection between ω + 1 and ω (Hilbert’s Paradox of the Grand Hotel). Is there an ordinal really bigger? 19 / 53

  20. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Theorem(Cantor, 1874) |P ( ω ) | > ℵ 0 . The smallest cardinal bigger than ℵ 0 is ℵ 1 , then ℵ 2 , ℵ 3 , . . . ℵ ω , ℵ ω +1 , . . . ℵ ω ω . . . Operations are defined, like sum, multiplications... Definition κ γ = |{ f : γ → κ }| . For example 2 κ = |P ( κ ) | . 20 / 53

  21. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Main Problems in Set Theory #2 Suppose for any n , 2 ℵ n < ℵ ω . How big is 2 ℵ ω ? Best result: 2 ℵ ω < ℵ ω 4 . But wait a minute... ℵ 1 is still too close to ℵ 0 : 2 ℵ 0 ≥ ℵ 1 , but 2 n < ℵ 0 for all n ! Definition(Sierpi´ nski, Tarski, Zermelo, 1930) κ is an inaccessible cardinal iff • κ > ℵ 0 ; • for any γ, η < κ , γ η < κ ; • for any A ⊆ κ , | A | < κ → sup( A ) < κ . 21 / 53

  22. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms inaccessible 22 / 53

  23. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Mahlo inaccessible 23 / 53

  24. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms weakly compact Mahlo inaccessible 24 / 53

  25. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms measurable weakly compact Mahlo inaccessible 25 / 53

  26. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms strongly compact measurable weakly compact Mahlo inaccessible 26 / 53

  27. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Mathematics works through theorems . They are logical derivations of the form if. . . then. . . . It is clear that there needs to be a starting point, i.e., an axiomatic system. ZFC is now the favourite axiomatic system for mathematics. We can say it’s the mathematics. 27 / 53

  28. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Theorem(G¨ odel, 1931) Any effectively generated theory capable of expressing elementary arithmetic cannot be both consistent and complete. For any formal effectively generated theory T including basic arithmetical truths and also certain truths about formal provabil- ity, if T includes a statement of its own consistency then T is inconsistent. A statement is independent from ZFC if ZFC cannot prove it or disprove it. If there is an inaccessible cardinal, then one can prove that ZFC is consistent. Then ZFC cannot prove that there exists an inaccessible cardinal, so it’s independent from ZFC. 28 / 53

  29. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Theorem The existence of an inaccessible cardinal is equiconsistent to • the measurability of the projective sets in R ; • the existence of Kurepa trees. Theorem The existence of a measurable cardinal is equiconsistent to • every Borelian measure on B ([0 , 1]) can be extended on a measure on P ([0 , 1]); • there exists a cardinal κ and a non-trivial homomorphism h : Z κ \ Z <κ → Z . Theorem(Nyikos, Fleissner 1982) The consistency of the normal Moore conjecture is between measur- able and strongly compact. 29 / 53

  30. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms I axioms supercompact strongly compact Woodin strong 0 † measurable weakly compact Mahlo inaccessible 30 / 53

  31. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Theorem (Wiles, 1995) Suppose there are unboundedly inaccessible cardinals. Then for any n > 2 there are no a , b , c integers such that a n + b n = c n . In 1983 Pitowsky constructed hidden variable models for spin-1/2 and spin-1 particles in quantum mechanics. Pitowsky’s functions calculate in this model the probabilities of spin values. Theorem (Farah, Magidor, 2012) If there exists a measurable cardinal, then Pitowski functions do not exist. 31 / 53

  32. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms There are also very debatable results. . . Theorem (H. Friedman, 2012) The existence of a measurable cardinal is close to equiconsistent to the existence of God. . . . and large cardinals even appear in pop culture! 32 / 53

  33. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms 33 / 53

  34. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms 34 / 53

  35. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Main questions when dealing with a large cardinal: • What is the relationship between it and other large cardinals? E.g. is it really different? Is it really stronger (or weaker)? • What are its consequences on set theory? And mathematics? • Which theorems needs it to be proven? 35 / 53

  36. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms I axioms supercompact strongly compact Woodin Strong 0 † measurable weakly compact Mahlo inaccessible 36 / 53

  37. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms Main Problems in Set Theory #3 Is supercompact equiconsistent to strongly compact? Main Problems in Set Theory #5 Suppose κ is strongly compact. Is it true that if for any η < κ 2 η = η + , then this is true for every η ? Main Problems in Set Theory #1 Is there an inner model for supercompact? 37 / 53

  38. Breaking the ceiling of infinity Stronger than mathematics I axioms I axioms supercompact strongly compact Woodin Strong 0 † measurable weakly compact Mahlo inaccessible 38 / 53

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend