insights from feminist ethics of care as a contemporary
play

Insights from Feminist Ethics of Care as a Contemporary Critical - PDF document

Insights from Feminist Ethics of Care as a Contemporary Critical Theory for Contesting Binaries and Imagining Possibilities Presentation at the Canadian Association for Research in Early Childhood Online Symposium Early Childhood in a Gendered


  1. Insights from Feminist Ethics of Care as a Contemporary Critical Theory for Contesting Binaries and Imagining Possibilities Presentation at the Canadian Association for Research in Early Childhood Online Symposium Early Childhood in a Gendered World: Contesting Binaries and Imagining Possibilities June 4 , 2020 Alana Powell MA-Early Childhood Studies, Association of Early Childhood Educators, Ontario Rachel Langford, PhD, Ryerson University Melinda Bruce, MA-Early Childhood Studies Candidate, Ryerson University Introduction Since its emergence as a relational approach to morality in the 1980s, feminist ethics of care has been perceived by some critics as a feminine, colonial, humanist ethics, which lacks contemporary rigour. In this presentation, we consider these critiques of feminist ethics of care and consider how they have a homogenizing effect, which neglects the phases, adaptations, innovations and flexibility of feminist ethics of care (Hamington, 2018). Instead, we position feminist ethics of care as a robust critical theory. To begin, we contend that ethics of care is a feminist not a feminine ethic that inherently disrupts and resists hierarchical relations that “divide people into categories and separate them from others and indeed from themselves” (Robinson, 2019, p. 11). In addition, from our perspective, both the historical and current place of care work at the personal, political and global level must be a key point of intersectional analysis (Hankivsky, 2014). We also consider how feminist ethics of care creates opportunities to decolonize practice in early childhood education by calling on us to respond in our relations to crises (e.g. inequalities, injustices, insecurities) brought on by settler colonialism (Mooten, 2015 p. 1; Raghuram, 2016). Feminist ethics of care prioritizes the contextual, temporal, nuanced and interdependency of care and care work by requiring us to respond in-situ with careful consideration for the place and time in all our relations. Finally, we consider, given urgent calls to decentre the human, how feminist ethics of care reminds us that in order to care well for our world and live well with others, we must create the conditions within which care can occur. We acknowledge that enacting care occurs simultaneously in multiple worlds, interconnected and entangled in relations between the human and the more-than-human. As such, we must continue to think with feminist ethics of care in order to create a caring imagination and capacity and to prioritize caring practices, so that we do not continue to fail to care well for our worlds. 1

  2. Our Understanding of Care We want to state upfront how we do and do not understand care. We want to dispel any assumptions that we are “softies” when it comes to care. So--- we do not idealize care as self-less feminine goodness. We do not support care as self-sacrifice. We do not see care as easy, natural, simple and perfect for nice girls who want to please everybody. In contrast, we see care as hard, learned, complex and fraught with many challenges. We see the discursive, the material, the human and the more-than human all wrapped up in messy caring encounters that can be smooth, conflictual and reparative. We understand care to be an act of embodiment in that care is always experienced materially in bodies, minds and hearts whether we give it or receive it. We see care as an ethic because we always make decisions about what we notice is care and what we notice it is not, and about how we enact care in our social relations. The kind of care we advocate for is not paternalistic and controlling. It is not the violent state care imposed on particular communities. Care then is both ethical and political in its concerns with power relations at multiple levels. In talking about care, we use the word “universal” only to insist that there is a universal need for care. Our priority in caring encounters is not a universal standard but rather contextual sensitivity. We do sometimes, use the word, normative” to describe the human condition because we maintain that ethics of care is normative in its calls to relationality, interdependence and responsibility. However, our use of the term “normative” is not the same as “closing off to” the one right way to thinking about and practicing care. Finally, while we describe care as a feminist ethic and as an ethic of resistance to patriarchy, we do not ignore other forms of oppression---settler colonialism and anti-black racism ---which are multiple and interlocking and given time and place the basis of oppression, persecution and exclusion. (Hyndman, (2004) quoted in Robinson, 2019). The Feminine Ethics Critique Some critics perceive ethics of care as a feminine ethics—one that is unique to women. How did this criticism arise? In 1982 Carol Gilligan, a moral psychologist, pioneered ethics of care when she questioned Lawrence Kohlberg’s conclusion that girls’ (and therefore women’s) moral development is deficient. She found in her research that girls seek solutions to ethical dilemmas through care relations, particularity, empathy, and contextual sensitivity rather than through impartial, abstract principles. Most importantly for the focus of this conference, Gilligan, on the basis of this research, set out a new moral paradigm, one that is not an addition to or an adjustment of morality based on abstract principles. She called this brand-new moral paradigm-an ethic of care- and at its core it dismantles the binaries and its 2

  3. hierarchies of the self over relationality, the mind over the body, the disembodied over the embodied, and reason over emotion. Susan Hekman (2014, p. 76) writes that in Gilligan’s rejection of traditional moral thinking, “the rug was pulled out from underneath the autonomous, disembodied subject” and the moral and political theory it grounds. How did she do this dismantling? Gilligan found in listening to girls’ narratives on responding to ethical dilemmas that they struggle to separate themselves from relationship and to choose reason over emotion and the body. Gilligan also found that many girls silence their struggles or voice, as Gilligan calls it, and uphold the separations to preserve relationships. She writes in her 2011 book, Joining the Resistance , that consequently “[these] separation(s) entail a sacrifice of both voice and integrity in relationship and lead girls and women to lose touch with what they know and who they are” (p. 76). While some feminists embraced Gilligan’s claims, her reference to girls’ care narratives as a different voice along with its comparison to a masculine voice of justice appeared on the surface, for some critics, to reinforce a feminine/masculine binary. On top of this, in 1980s, Sara Ruddick (1989), asserted, from a philosophical perspective, the value of maternal thinking, long considered without moral merit, for promoting important ethical values. Furthermore, Nel Noddings (1986), an educational philosopher, insisted on the centrality of women’s maternal experiences in the development of care ethics. This seemed to some to reinforce the claim that care is a feminine ethic. In response Gilligan, Noddings and many other second and third generation feminist care scholars, including ourselves, began to explicitly reject reading ethics of care as promoting a feminine/masculine binary. We will discuss two ways they and (we) do this. The first way is to argue that if all humans are born “second persons” in relation to others and this interdependence fosters caring about others then care can not be natural to a certain gender. Ethics of care, therefore, subverts not only the feminine/masculine binary but also a presumed natural hierarchical order in which some persons care and others do not. Thus, Fiona Robinson, a political scientist, (2019) argues that feminist ethics of care resists hierarchical relations that, as she says, ‘divide people into categories and separate them from others and indeed from themselves” (p. 13). Similarly, in a 2018 book Gilligan and Naomi Snider emphasize that “the different voice is identified not by gender but by theme” setting it apart from moral theories that uphold binaries and hierarchies (p. 37). They argue that ethics of care is a human voice “that joins thought and emotion, mind with body, self with relationship” (p. 37). Consequently, contemporary care scholars are more concerned with questions such as the meaning of embodied care and the loss of the capacity to care. A second way of addressing the assumption that care is a feminine ethic is by emphasizing that ethics of care emerged out of girls’ and women’s concrete everyday experiences with caring under patriarchal conditions. Sandra Laugier, (2019) a care scholar interested in care as a politics of the 3

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend