indirect measurements of a harmonic oscillator
play

Indirect measurements of a harmonic oscillator Gian Michele Graf - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Indirect measurements of a harmonic oscillator Gian Michele Graf ETH Zurich Quantissima in the Serenissima III Palazzo Pesaro Papafava, Venezia August 19-23, 2019 Indirect measurements of a harmonic oscillator Gian Michele Graf ETH Zurich


  1. Indirect measurements of a harmonic oscillator Gian Michele Graf ETH Zurich Quantissima in the Serenissima III Palazzo Pesaro Papafava, Venezia August 19-23, 2019

  2. Indirect measurements of a harmonic oscillator Gian Michele Graf ETH Zurich Quantissima in the Serenissima III Palazzo Pesaro Papafava, Venezia August 19-23, 2019 based on joint work with M. Fraas, L. H¨ anggli discussions with J. Fr¨ ohlich, K. Hepp

  3. Outline Setting the stage The model defined at last Results

  4. Setting the stage The model defined at last Results

  5. Born rule (BR) If an ideal measurement of the observable � A = A ∗ = λ P λ λ ∈ spec ( A ) (spectral decomposition) is done in the state ψ , then the outcome λ is found with probability � ψ | P λ | ψ � .

  6. Born rule (BR) If an ideal measurement of the observable � A = A ∗ = λ P λ λ ∈ spec ( A ) (spectral decomposition) is done in the state ψ , then the outcome λ is found with probability � ψ | P λ | ψ � . Remarks on what goes with BR, though untold: ◮ The relation between physical meaning (e.g. momentum) and mathematical operation ( A = − i d / dx ) is premised (e.g. correspondence principle).

  7. Born rule (BR) If an ideal measurement of the observable � A = A ∗ = λ P λ λ ∈ spec ( A ) (spectral decomposition) is done in the state ψ , then the outcome λ is found with probability � ψ | P λ | ψ � . Remarks on what goes with BR, though untold: ◮ The relation between physical meaning (e.g. momentum) and mathematical operation ( A = − i d / dx ) is premised (e.g. correspondence principle). ◮ The relation between the physical and the operational meaning of A is not even addressed. The apparatus remains exophysical; the observable dry.

  8. Born rule (BR) If an ideal measurement of the observable � A = A ∗ = λ P λ λ ∈ spec ( A ) (spectral decomposition) is done in the state ψ , then the outcome λ is found with probability � ψ | P λ | ψ � . Remarks on what goes with BR, though untold: ◮ The relation between physical meaning (e.g. momentum) and mathematical operation ( A = − i d / dx ) is premised (e.g. correspondence principle). ◮ The relation between the physical and the operational meaning of A is not even addressed. The apparatus remains exophysical; the observable dry. Cf. Heisenberg 1927: If one wants to be clear about what is meant by ”position of an object,” for example of an electron (relatively to a given reference frame), then one has to specify definite experiments by which the ”position of an electron” can be measured; otherwise this term has no meaning at all.

  9. Born rule (BR) If an ideal measurement of the observable � A = A ∗ = λ P λ λ ∈ spec ( A ) (spectral decomposition) is done in the state ψ , then the outcome λ is found with probability � ψ | P λ | ψ � . Remarks on what goes with BR, though untold: ◮ The relation between physical meaning (e.g. momentum) and mathematical operation ( A = − i d / dx ) is premised (e.g. correspondence principle). ◮ The relation between the physical and the operational meaning of A is not even addressed. The apparatus remains exophysical; the observable dry. ◮ State ψ changes with time. Hence the ideal measurement is instantaneous. (But any real measurement takes time.)

  10. Remarks on duration of measurement ◮ If the measurement of the intended observable A takes a time T , then the observable actually measured is (at best) the time average � T A T := 1 e i Ht A e − i Ht dt T 0

  11. Remarks on duration of measurement ◮ If the measurement of the intended observable A takes a time T , then the observable actually measured is (at best) the time average � T A T := 1 e i Ht A e − i Ht dt T 0 ◮ General protocol: Measure A T before it deviates a lot from A (von Neumann: Strong coupling to apparatus)

  12. Remarks on duration of measurement ◮ If the measurement of the intended observable A takes a time T , then the observable actually measured is (at best) the time average � T A T := 1 e i Ht A e − i Ht dt T 0 ◮ General protocol: Measure A T before it deviates a lot from A (von Neumann: Strong coupling to apparatus) ◮ Special protocol: If A is a constant of motion, then T does not matter: A T = A . (To the contrary: the larger T , the better, because the initialization of the apparatus matters ever less; e.g. quantum non-demolition experiments (QND) and their theory, T → ∞ .)

  13. Stability of QND A intended observable � T A T := 1 e i Ht A e − i Ht dt actual observable T 0

  14. Stability of QND A intended observable � T A T := 1 e i Ht A e − i Ht dt actual observable T 0 ◮ If A = f ( H ) , then A T = A (as seen).

  15. Stability of QND A intended observable � T A T := 1 e i Ht A e − i Ht dt actual observable T 0 ◮ If A = f ( H ) , then A T = A (as seen). ◮ If A = f ( H 0 ) with H − H 0 small (Hamiltonian error, unavoidable), then � A T − A � ≤ 2 � f ( H ) − f ( H 0 ) �

  16. Stability of QND A intended observable � T A T := 1 e i Ht A e − i Ht dt actual observable T 0 ◮ If A = f ( H ) , then A T = A (as seen). ◮ If A = f ( H 0 ) with H − H 0 small (Hamiltonian error, unavoidable), then � A T − A � ≤ 2 � f ( H ) − f ( H 0 ) � ∴ stability: � A T − A � small uniformly in T > 0 (no apparatus, though).

  17. The dilemma and the way out ◮ BR applies to ideal (hence instantaneous) measurements only ◮ There are no instantaneous measurements ◮ There is no rule for other measurements ◮ Can we nonetheless tell how close real measurements come to ideal ones (and hence test BR)?

  18. The dilemma and the way out ◮ BR applies to ideal (hence instantaneous) measurements only ◮ There are no instantaneous measurements ◮ There is no rule for other measurements ◮ Can we nonetheless tell how close real measurements come to ideal ones (and hence test BR)? ◮ Yes.

  19. The dilemma and the way out ◮ BR applies to ideal (hence instantaneous) measurements only ◮ There are no instantaneous measurements ◮ There is no rule for other measurements ◮ Can we nonetheless tell how close real measurements come to ideal ones (and hence test BR)? ◮ Yes. By applying BR at a different levels: Postulate it for the pointer observable of the apparatus A , in order to analyze the system proper S (indirect measurement).

  20. The dilemma and the way out ◮ BR applies to ideal (hence instantaneous) measurements only ◮ There are no instantaneous measurements ◮ There is no rule for other measurements ◮ Can we nonetheless tell how close real measurements come to ideal ones (and hence test BR)? ◮ Yes. By applying BR at a different levels: Postulate it for the pointer observable of the apparatus A , in order to analyze the system proper S (indirect measurement). ◮ What it takes: Make A endophysical (shift of Heisenberg cut).

  21. The dilemma and the way out ◮ BR applies to ideal (hence instantaneous) measurements only ◮ There are no instantaneous measurements ◮ There is no rule for other measurements ◮ Can we nonetheless tell how close real measurements come to ideal ones (and hence test BR)? ◮ Yes. By applying BR at a different levels: Postulate it for the pointer observable of the apparatus A , in order to analyze the system proper S (indirect measurement). ◮ What it takes: Make A endophysical (shift of Heisenberg cut). ◮ The shift is real, and not just of perspective, because S and A are now coupled; the test will be a pointer mirroring A

  22. The dilemma and the way out ◮ BR applies to ideal (hence instantaneous) measurements only ◮ There are no instantaneous measurements ◮ There is no rule for other measurements ◮ Can we nonetheless tell how close real measurements come to ideal ones (and hence test BR)? ◮ Yes. By applying BR at a different levels: Postulate it for the pointer observable of the apparatus A , in order to analyze the system proper S (indirect measurement). ◮ What it takes: Make A endophysical (shift of Heisenberg cut). ◮ The shift is real, and not just of perspective, because S and A are now coupled; the test will be a pointer mirroring A ◮ We’ll see: The stability of QND is lost for T → ∞ , because A is feeding back on S .

  23. The dilemma and the way out ◮ BR applies to ideal (hence instantaneous) measurements only ◮ There are no instantaneous measurements ◮ There is no rule for other measurements ◮ Can we nonetheless tell how close real measurements come to ideal ones (and hence test BR)? ◮ Yes. By applying BR at a different levels: Postulate it for the pointer observable of the apparatus A , in order to analyze the system proper S (indirect measurement). ◮ What it takes: Make A endophysical (shift of Heisenberg cut). ◮ The shift is real, and not just of perspective, because S and A are now coupled; the test will be a pointer mirroring A ◮ We’ll see: The stability of QND is lost for T → ∞ , because A is feeding back on S . There is a time window of opportunity ( t ∈ [ 0 , T ] ) for measurement.

  24. Requisites for the apparatus A and their implementation ◮ A is quantum, but establishes a record that is classical.

  25. Requisites for the apparatus A and their implementation ◮ A is quantum, but establishes a record that is classical. → Dyson: “As a general rule, knowledge about the past can only be expressed in classical terms.”

  26. Requisites for the apparatus A and their implementation ◮ A is quantum, but establishes a record that is classical. → Fr¨ ohlich: “ETH approach”

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend