hypergraph framework for spekkens contextuality applied
play

Hypergraph framework for Spekkens contextuality applied to - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Hypergraph framework for Spekkens contextuality applied to Kochen-Specker scenarios Ravi Kunjwal, Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics, Canada (Purdue Winer Memorial Lectures 2018) November 10, 2018 Outline Contextuality ` a la


  1. Hypergraph framework for Spekkens contextuality applied to Kochen-Specker scenarios Ravi Kunjwal, Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics, Canada (Purdue Winer Memorial Lectures 2018) November 10, 2018

  2. Outline Contextuality ` a la Spekkens Kochen-Specker contextuality ` a la CSW Hypergraph-theoretic ingredients Beyond CSW Takeaway

  3. a la Spekkens 1 Contextuality ` 1 R. W. Spekkens, Contextuality for preparations, transformations, and unsharp measurements, Phys. Rev. A 71, 052108 (2005).

  4. Schematic of a prepare-and-measure scenario and its two descriptions

  5. A prepare-and-measure scenario Measurement Source

  6. Two descriptions: Operational vs. Ontological ◮ Operational: p ( m , s | M , S ) ∈ [0 , 1] , (1) where p ( m , s | M , S ) = p ( m | M , S , s ) p ( s | S ). ◮ Ontological: � p ( m , s | M , S ) = ξ ( m | M , λ ) µ ( λ, s | S ) , (2) λ ∈ Λ where µ ( λ, s | S ) = µ ( λ | S , s ) p ( s | S ).

  7. Features of the operational theory necessary to define noncontextuality

  8. Operational equivalences Preparations ◮ Source events: [ s | S ] ≃ [ s ′ | S ′ ], i.e., p ( m , s | M , S ) = p ( m , s ′ | M , S ′ ) ∀ [ m | M ] . (3) ◮ Source settings: [ ⊤| S ] ≃ [ ⊤| S ′ ], i.e., � � p ( m , s ′ | M , S ′ ) p ( m , s | M , S ) = ∀ [ m | M ] . (4) s ∈ V S s ′ ∈ V S ′

  9. Measurements Measurement events are operationally equivalent ([ m | M ] ≃ [ m ′ | M ′ ]) if no source event can distinguish them, i.e., ∀ [ s | S ] : p ( m , s | M , S ) = p ( m ′ , s | M ′ , S ) , (5) e.g., when the same projector appears in two different measurement bases.

  10. What is a ‘context’? Any distinction between operationally equivalent procedures. Difference Difference of context of context

  11. Examples Preparation contexts: Different realizations of a given quantum state, e.g., different convex decompositions, 2 = 1 2 | 0 �� 0 | + 1 2 | 1 �� 1 | = 1 2 | + �� + | + 1 I 2 |−��−| , or different purifications, ρ A = Tr B | ψ �� ψ | AB = Tr C | φ �� φ | AC , etc .

  12. Measurement contexts: Different realizations of a given POVM or a POVM element, e.g., same projector appearing in different measurement bases, joint measurability contexts for a given POVM, or even different ways of implementing a fair coin flip measurement. 2 2 Mazurek et. al., Nature Communications 7:11780 (2016).

  13. Noncontextuality

  14. Noncontextuality: identity of indiscernibles If there exists no operational way to distinguish two things, then they must be physically identical. 3 ◮ Measurement noncontextuality: [ m | M ] ≃ [ m ′ | M ′ ] ⇒ ξ ( m | M , λ ) = ξ ( m ′ | M ′ , λ ) ∀ λ ∈ Λ ◮ Preparation noncontextuality: [ s | S ] ≃ [ s ′ | S ′ ] ⇒ µ ( λ, s | S ) = µ ( λ, s ′ | S ′ ) ∀ λ ∈ Λ , [ ⊤| S ] ≃ [ ⊤| S ′ ] ⇒ µ ( λ | S ) = µ ( λ | S ′ ) ∀ λ ∈ Λ . 3 Equivalently: if two things are non-identical, or physically distinct, then there must exist an operational way to distinguish them.

  15. Kochen-Specker (KS) noncontextuality KS-noncontextuality ⇔ Measurement noncontextuality and Outcome determinism 4 4 Applied to measurement contexts of the type arising from joint measurability. Outcome determinism: for any [ m | M ], ξ ( m | M , λ ) ∈ { 0 , 1 } ∀ λ ∈ Λ.

  16. Kochen-Specker theorem: logical proof Cabello et al., Physics Letters A 212, 183 (1996)

  17. Kochen-Specker theorem: statistical proof Klyachko et al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 101, 020403 (2008)

  18. a la CSW 5 Kochen-Specker contextuality ` 5 Cabello et al., PRL 112, 040401 (2014).

  19. Contextuality scenario, Γ A hypergraph Γ where the nodes of the hypergraph v ∈ V (Γ) denote measurement outcomes and hyperedges denote measurements e ∈ E (Γ) ⊆ 2 V (Γ) such that � e ∈ E (Γ) = V (Γ). 6 Figure: Γ for KCBS. 7 6 We will further assume that no hyperedge is a strict subset of another in Γ, following Ac´ ın et al (AFLS), Comm. Math. Phys. 334(2), 533-628 (2015) 7 Klyachko et al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 101, 020403 (2008).

  20. Orthogonality graph of Γ, i.e., O (Γ) Vertices of O (Γ) are given by V ( O (Γ)) ≡ V (Γ), and the edges of O (Γ) are given by E ( O (Γ)) ≡ {{ v , v ′ }| v , v ′ ∈ e for some e ∈ E (Γ) } .

  21. Probabilistic models on Γ A probabilistic model on Γ is given by p : V (Γ) → [0 , 1] such that � v ∈ e p ( v ) = 1 for all e ∈ E (Γ). The set of all probabilistic models on Γ is denoted G (Γ). Relevant subsets of G (Γ): ◮ KS-noncontextual, C (Γ): a convex mixture of p : V (Γ) → { 0 , 1 } , � v ∈ e p ( v ) = 1 ∀ e ∈ E (Γ). ◮ Consistently exclusive, CE 1 (Γ): p : V (Γ) → [0 , 1], such that � v ∈ c p ( v ) ≤ 1 for all cliques c in O (Γ). Clearly, C (Γ) ⊆ CE 1 (Γ) ⊆ G (Γ) .

  22. Exclusivity graph, G : a subgraph of O (Γ) � R ([ s | S ]) ≡ w v p ( v | S , s ) , (6) v ∈ V ( G ) where w v > 0 for all v ∈ V ( G ) and p ( v | S , s ) is a probabilistic model induced by source event [ s | S ] on measurements events in Γ.

  23. CSW bounds � R ([ s | S ]) ≡ w v p ( v | S , s ) v ∈ V ( G ) KS ≤ α ( G , w ) Q ≤ θ ( G , w ) E 1 α ∗ ( G , w ) , ≤ KCBS 8 : w v = 1 for all v ∈ V ( G ), √ 5, and α ∗ = 5 / 2. α = 2, θ = 8 Klyachko et al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 101, 020403 (2008).

  24. Missing ingredients? ◮ Measurement noncontextuality alone yields a trivial upper bound α ∗ ( G , w ). (Remember: no outcome determinism.) ◮ Need to invoke preparation noncontextuality. ◮ We do this next.

  25. Hypergraph-theoretic ingredients

  26. The contextuality scenario Γ G Turn maximal cliques in G into hyperedges and add an extra (“nondetection”) vertex to each hyperedge. We can now take p ( v | S , s ) to be a probabilistic model on Γ G rather than the full scenario Γ and retain the same probabilities on G .

  27. Weighted max-predictability, β (Γ G , q ) � β (Γ G , q ) ≡ max q e ζ ( M e , p ) , (7) p ∈G (Γ G ) | ind e ∈ E (Γ G ) where q e ≥ 0 for all e ∈ E (Γ G ), � e ∈ E (Γ G ) q e = 1, and ζ ( M e , p ) ≡ max v ∈ e p ( v ) (8) is the maximum probability assigned to a vertex in e ∈ E (Γ G ) by an indeterministic probabilistic model p ∈ G (Γ G ).

  28. Source hypergraph

  29. Source-measurement correlations: Corr � � Corr ≡ q e δ m e , s e p ( m e , s e | M e , S e ) , (9) m e , s e e ∈ E (Γ G ) where { q e } e ∈ E (Γ G ) is a probability distribution, i.e., q e ≥ 0 for all e ∈ E (Γ G ) q e = 1. 9 e ∈ E (Γ G ) and � 9 Such that β (Γ G , q ) < 1 holds.

  30. Beyond CSW: Hypergraph framework for Spekkens contextuality

  31. General form of the noise-robust noncontextuality inequality: KS-colourable case 10 , 11 ≤ α ( G , w ) + α ∗ ( G , w ) − α ( G , w ) 1 − Corr NC R ([ s e ∗ = 0 | S e ∗ ]) 1 − β (Γ G , q ) . p ∗ Here, p ∗ ≡ p ( s e ∗ = 0 | S e ∗ ) = p ( v 0 e ∗ ) and all the measurement events in G are evaluated on the source event [ s e ∗ = 0 | S e ∗ ] to compute R ([ s e ∗ = 0 | S e ∗ ]). For the KCBS scenario: α ( G , w ) = 2, α ∗ ( G , w ) = 5 / 2, and β (Γ G , q ) = 1 / 2. We then have R ≤ 2 + 1 − Corr p ∗ 10 R. Kunjwal, arXiv:1709.01098 [quant-ph] (2017). 11 R. Kunjwal and R. W. Spekkens, Phys. Rev. A 97, 052110 (2018).

  32. Scope of this generalization of CSW The framework presented so far applies to KS-colourable contextuality scenarios where statistical proofs of the KS theorem apply. In particular, it covers contextuality scenarios Γ (hence also Γ G ) such that ◮ C (Γ) � = ∅ , ◮ CE 1 (Γ) = G (Γ).

  33. Hypergraph framework for KS-uncolourable scenarios ◮ For Γ such that C (Γ) = ∅ , we obtain a framework (cf. arXiv:1805.02083) based entirely on the hypergraph invariant β (Γ G , q ). ◮ It’s basic ingredients are still the contextuality scenario Γ and the corresponding source events hypergraph. 𝑁 " # 𝑇 " # 𝑇 " ( 𝑁 " $ 𝑁 " ( 𝑁 " ) 𝑇 " $ 𝑁 " * 𝑇 " ) 𝑇 " * 𝑇 " + 𝑁 " + 𝑇 " ' 𝑇 " % 𝑁 " ' 𝑁 " % 𝑇 " & 𝑁 " &

  34. Recall � β (Γ G , q ) ≡ max q e ζ ( M e , p ) , (10) p ∈G (Γ G ) | ind e ∈ E (Γ G ) where q e ≥ 0 for all e ∈ E (Γ G ), � e ∈ E (Γ G ) q e = 1, and ζ ( M e , p ) ≡ max v ∈ e p ( v ) (11) is the maximum probability assigned to a vertex in e ∈ E (Γ G ) by an indeterministic probabilistic model p ∈ G (Γ G ).

  35. Recall � � Corr ≡ q e δ m e , s e p ( m e , s e | M e , S e ) , (12) m e , s e e ∈ E (Γ) where { q e } e ∈ E (Γ) is a probability distribution, i.e., q e ≥ 0 for all e ∈ E (Γ) q e = 1. 12 e ∈ E (Γ G ) and � 12 Such that β (Γ , q ) < 1 holds.

  36. General form of the noise-robust noncontextuality inequality: KS-uncolourable case Corr ≤ β (Γ , q ) . (13)

  37. Example: 18 ray Corr ≤ 5 6 , (14) where q e i = 1 9 for all i ∈ [9]. 1 2 ⁄ 0 1 2 ⁄ 0 1 1 2 ⁄ 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend