going beyond 2 4 in freiman s 2 4k theorem
play

Going beyond 2.4 in Freimans 2.4k-Theorem Pablo Candela Oriol - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Going beyond 2.4 in Freimans 2.4k-Theorem Pablo Candela Oriol Serra Christoph Spiegel CANT 2018 New York, May 2018 I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition


  1. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Going beyond 2.4 in Freiman’s 2.4k-Theorem Pablo Candela Oriol Serra Christoph Spiegel CANT 2018 New York, May 2018

  2. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1)

  3. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } .

  4. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k :

  5. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k : 1. For A = { 0 , . . . , k − 1 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = 2 k − 1.

  6. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k : 1. For A = { 0 , . . . , k − 1 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = 2 k − 1. 2. For A = { 0 , 1 , 2 , 4 , . . . , 2 k − 2 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = � k � + 2. 2

  7. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k : 1. For A = { 0 , . . . , k − 1 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = 2 k − 1. 2. For A = { 0 , 1 , 2 , 4 , . . . , 2 k − 2 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = � k � + 2. 2 Inverse Problems: We are interested in understanding the structure of A when the doubling | 2 A | / | A | is small.

  8. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 .

  9. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression.

  10. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) .

  11. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) . Theorem (Vosper ’56) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfying |A| ≥ 2 and | 2 A| = 2 |A| − 1 ≤ p − 2 must be an arithmetic progression.

  12. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) . Theorem (Vosper ’56) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfying |A| ≥ 2 and | 2 A| = 2 |A| − 1 ≤ p − 2 must be an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Kneser ’53) Any set A ⊆ Z n satisfies | 2 A| ≥ 2 |A + H | − | H | where H = { x ∈ Z n : x + 2 A ⊂ 2 A} is the stabilizer of the sumset.

  13. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) . Theorem (Vosper ’56) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfying |A| ≥ 2 and | 2 A| = 2 |A| − 1 ≤ p − 2 must be an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Kneser ’53) Any set A ⊆ Z n satisfies | 2 A| ≥ 2 |A + H | − | H | where H = { x ∈ Z n : x + 2 A ⊂ 2 A} is the stabilizer of the sumset. The corresponding inverse statement is due to Kemperman ’60.

  14. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 .

  15. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95.

  16. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider .

  17. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime.

  18. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a .

  19. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a . � � 4. | 2 A | = | 2 A| + # x ∈ [ 0 , a ) : x , a + x ∈ 2 A + 1 ≥ | 2 A| + | A | .

  20. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a . � � 4. | 2 A | = | 2 A| + # x ∈ [ 0 , a ) : x , a + x ∈ 2 A + 1 ≥ | 2 A| + | A | . 5. If | 2 A| = max( A ) we are done. If not, then Cauchy-Davenport gives us the contradiction | 2 A | ≥ 2 |A| − 1 + | A | = 3 | A | − 3.

  21. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a . � � 4. | 2 A | = | 2 A| + # x ∈ [ 0 , a ) : x , a + x ∈ 2 A + 1 ≥ | 2 A| + | A | . 5. If | 2 A| = max( A ) we are done. If not, then Cauchy-Davenport gives us the contradiction | 2 A | ≥ 2 |A| − 1 + | A | = 3 | A | − 3. Example For k ≥ 3 and x > 2 ( k − 2 ) the sets A x = { 0 , . . . , k − 2 } ∪ { x } all satisfy | 2 A x | = 3 | A x | − 3 but require arbitrarily large APs to be covered.

  22. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Obtaining an analogue in Z p A similar result is conjectured to hold in Z p .

  23. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Obtaining an analogue in Z p A similar result is conjectured to hold in Z p . Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A| ≤ 3 |A| − 4 as well as is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A| − |A| + 1.

  24. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Obtaining an analogue in Z p A similar result is conjectured to hold in Z p . Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A| ≤ 3 |A| − 4 as well as is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A| − |A| + 1. Corollary to Green, Ruzsa ’06 |A| ≤ p / 10 250

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend