games in descriptive set theory or it s all fun and games
play

Games in Descriptive Set Theory, or: its all fun and games until - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Games in Descriptive Set Theory, or: its all fun and games until someone loses the axiom of choice Hugo Nobrega Cool Logic 22 May 2015 Descriptive set theory and the Baire space Presentation outline [0] 1 Descriptive set theory and the


  1. Games in Descriptive Set Theory, or: it’s all fun and games until someone loses the axiom of choice Hugo Nobrega Cool Logic 22 May 2015

  2. Descriptive set theory and the Baire space Presentation outline [0] 1 Descriptive set theory and the Baire space Why DST, why N N ? The topology of N N and its many flavors 2 Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy 3 Games for classes of functions The classical games The tree game Games for finite Baire classes

  3. Descriptive set theory and the Baire space Why DST, why N N ? Descriptive set theory The real line R can have some pathologies (in ZFC): for example, not every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable, there may be sets of reals of cardinality strictly between | N | and | R | , etc. Descriptive set theory, the theory of definable sets of real numbers, was developed in part to try to fill in the template “No definable set of reals of complexity c can have pathology P”

  4. Descriptive set theory and the Baire space Why DST, why N N ? Baire space N N For a lot of questions which interest set theorists, working with R is unnecessarily clumsy. It is often better to work with other (Cauchy-)complete topological spaces of cardinality | R | which have bases of cardinality | N | (a.k.a. Polish spaces), and this is enough (in a technically precise way). The Baire space N N is especially nice, as I hope to show you, and set theorists often (usually?) mean this when they say “real numbers”.

  5. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The topology of N N We consider N N with the product topology of discrete N . . . . This topology is generated by the complete metric � 0 if x = y d ( x , y ) = 2 − n if x � = y and n is least such that x ( n ) � = y ( n ) . For each σ ∈ N < N , we denote [ σ ] := { x ∈ N N ; σ is a prefix of x } Then { [ σ ] ; σ ∈ N < N } is a (countable) basis for the topology of N N .

  6. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The topology of N N We consider N N with the product topology of discrete N . . . . This topology is generated by the complete metric � 0 if x = y d ( x , y ) = 2 − n if x � = y and n is least such that x ( n ) � = y ( n ) . For each σ ∈ N < N , we denote [ σ ] := { x ∈ N N ; σ is a prefix of x } Then { [ σ ] ; σ ∈ N < N } is a (countable) basis for the topology of N N .

  7. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The topology of N N We consider N N with the product topology of discrete N . . . . This topology is generated by the complete metric � 0 if x = y d ( x , y ) = 2 − n if x � = y and n is least such that x ( n ) � = y ( n ) . For each σ ∈ N < N , we denote [ σ ] := { x ∈ N N ; σ is a prefix of x } Then { [ σ ] ; σ ∈ N < N } is a (countable) basis for the topology of N N .

  8. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The topology of N N We consider N N with the product topology of discrete N . . . . This topology is generated by the complete metric � 0 if x = y d ( x , y ) = 2 − n if x � = y and n is least such that x ( n ) � = y ( n ) . For each σ ∈ N < N , we denote [ σ ] := { x ∈ N N ; σ is a prefix of x } Then { [ σ ] ; σ ∈ N < N } is a (countable) basis for the topology of N N .

  9. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The topology of N N We consider N N with the product topology of discrete N . . . . This topology is generated by the complete metric � 0 if x = y d ( x , y ) = 2 − n if x � = y and n is least such that x ( n ) � = y ( n ) . For each σ ∈ N < N , we denote [ σ ] := { x ∈ N N ; σ ⊂ x } Then { [ σ ] ; σ ∈ N < N } is a (countable) basis for the topology of N N .

  10. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The computational flavor of N N Thus a set X ⊆ N N is open iff there exists some A ⊆ N < N such that � X ∈ [ σ ] . σ ∈ A Hence, if X is open and we want to decide if some given x is in X , then we can inspect longer and longer finite prefixes of x , � x 0 � � x 0 , x 1 � � x 0 , x 1 , x 2 � . . . and in case x ∈ X is indeed true, at some finite stage we will “know” this (if x �∈ X then all bets are off). This is analogous to the recursively enumerable sets in computability theory.

  11. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The combinatorial flavor of N N A tree is a set T ⊆ N < N which is closed under prefixes. An element x ∈ N N is an infinite path of a tree T if all finite prefixes of x are in T . The body of T is the set of all its infinite paths, denoted [ T ] . Theorem The closed sets of N N are exactly the bodies of trees.

  12. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The combinatorial flavor of N N A tree is a set T ⊆ N < N which is closed under prefixes. An element x ∈ N N is an infinite path of a tree T if all finite prefixes of x are in T . The body of T is the set of all its infinite paths, denoted [ T ] . Theorem The closed sets of N N are exactly the bodies of trees.

  13. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space Notation clash? We use the same notation for basic open sets, [ σ ] , as for bodies of trees, [ T ] . But actually [ σ ] is also the body of a certain tree: Thus every basic open set is also closed, in stark contrast to R which has only two clopen sets, ∅ and R .

  14. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  15. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  16. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  17. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  18. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  19. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  20. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  21. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  22. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy

  23. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy � Σ 0 A set is Borel iff it belongs to α α<ω 1

  24. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy � Π 0 A set is Borel iff it belongs to α α<ω 1

  25. The topology of N N and its many flavors Descriptive set theory and the Baire space The Borel hierarchy � ∆ 0 A set is Borel iff it belongs to α α<ω 1

  26. Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy Presentation outline [0] 1 Descriptive set theory and the Baire space Why DST, why N N ? The topology of N N and its many flavors 2 Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy 3 Games for classes of functions The classical games The tree game Games for finite Baire classes

  27. Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy Gale-Stewart games Given A ⊆ N N , the Gale-Stewart game for A is played between two players, I and II , in N rounds. Player I plays in even rounds, II in odd rounds. At round n the corresponding player picks x n ∈ N (with perfect information). Round I II

  28. Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy Gale-Stewart games Given A ⊆ N N , the Gale-Stewart game for A is played between two players, I and II , in N rounds. Player I plays in even rounds, II in odd rounds. At round n the corresponding player picks x n ∈ N (with perfect information). Round I II

  29. Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy Gale-Stewart games Given A ⊆ N N , the Gale-Stewart game for A is played between two players, I and II , in N rounds. Player I plays in even rounds, II in odd rounds. At round n the corresponding player picks x n ∈ N (with perfect information). Round 0 I x 0 II

  30. Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy Gale-Stewart games Given A ⊆ N N , the Gale-Stewart game for A is played between two players, I and II , in N rounds. Player I plays in even rounds, II in odd rounds. At round n the corresponding player picks x n ∈ N (with perfect information). Round 0 1 I x 0 II x 1

  31. Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy Gale-Stewart games Given A ⊆ N N , the Gale-Stewart game for A is played between two players, I and II , in N rounds. Player I plays in even rounds, II in odd rounds. At round n the corresponding player picks x n ∈ N (with perfect information). Round 0 1 2 I x 0 x 2 II x 1

  32. Gale-Stewart games and the Axiom of Determinacy Gale-Stewart games Given A ⊆ N N , the Gale-Stewart game for A is played between two players, I and II , in N rounds. Player I plays in even rounds, II in odd rounds. At round n the corresponding player picks x n ∈ N (with perfect information). Round 0 1 2 3 I x 0 x 2 II x 1 x 3

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend