game theory and its applications to networks
play

Game Theory and its Applications to Networks Corinne Touati / Bruno - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Game Theory and its Applications to Networks Corinne Touati / Bruno Gaujal Master ENS Lyon, Fall 2011 Course Overview Part 1 (C. Touati) : Games, Solutions and Applications Sept. 21 Introduction - Main Game Theory Concepts Sept. 28 Special


  1. The Minimax Theorem Theorem 1: The Minimax Theorem . def In mixed strategies: V m − = V m = V m + Proof . Lemma 1: Theorem of the Alternative for Matrices . Let A = ( a ij ) m × n Either (i) (0 , ..., 0) is contained in the convex hull of A . 1 , ..., A .n , e 1 , ...e m . Or (ii) There exists x 1 , ..., x m s.t. m m � � ∀ i, x i > 0 , x i = 1 , ∀ j ∈ 1 , ..., n, a ij x i . i =1 i =1 Lemma 2. Lemma 3: Let A be a game and k ∈ R . Let B the game such that ∀ i, j, b ij = a ij + k . Then V m − ( A ) = V m − ( B ) + k and V m + ( A ) = V m + ( B ) + k . Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 16 / 66

  2. The Minimax Theorem Theorem 1: The Minimax Theorem . def In mixed strategies: V m − = V m = V m + Proof . From Lemma 2 , we get that for any game, either (i) from lemma 2 and V m + ≤ 0 or (ii) and V m − > 0 . Hence, we cannot have V m − ≤ 0 < V m + . With Lemma 3 this implies that V m − = V m + . Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 16 / 66

  3. The Minimax Theorem - Illustration � 4 � 2 Example: 1 3 4 4 2 . 5 4 4 4 4 2 2 . 5 3 3.5 3.5 3.5 3.5 3.5 3 3 3 3 3 2.5 2.5 2.5 2.5 2.5 2 . 5 2 2 2 2 2 2 . 5 1.5 1.5 1.5 1.5 1.5 1 1 1 1 1 2 2 2 2 1 1 1 1 1 1 . 75 1 . 5 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 17 / 66

  4. A Note on Symmetric Games Definition: Symmetric Game . A game is symmetric if its matrix is skew-symmetric Proposition: The value of a symmetric game is 0 and any strategy optimal for player 1 is also optimal for player 2. Proof . Note that xAx t = − xA t x t = − ( xAx t ) t = − xAx t = 0 . Hence xAy t ≤ 0 and max yAx t ≥ 0 so V = 0 . ∀ x, min y y If x is an optimal strategy for 1 then 0 ≤ xA = x ( − A t ) = − xA t and Ax t ≤ 0 . Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 18 / 66

  5. Outline ”Simple” Games and their solutions: One Round, Simultaneous 1 plays, Perfect Information Zero-Sum Games General Case Two Inspiring Examples 2 Optimality 3 Bargaining Concepts 4 Measuring the Inefficiency of a Policy 5 Application: Multiple Bag-of-Task Applications in Distributed 6 Platforms Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 19 / 66

  6. Game in Normal Form Definition: (Finite or Matrix) Game . ◮ N players, finite number of actions ◮ Payoffs of players (depend of each other actions and) are real valued ◮ Stable points are called Nash Equilibria Definition: Nash Equilibrium . In a NE, no player has incentive to unilaterally modify his strategy. strategy payoff s ∗ is a Nash equilibrium iff: ∀ p, ∀ s p , u p ( s ∗ s ∗ p , . . . s ∗ n ) ≥ u p ( s ∗ s p , . . . , s ∗ 1 , . . . , 1 , . . . , n ) In a compact form: ∀ p, ∀ s p , u p ( s ∗ − p , s ∗ p ) ≥ u p ( s ∗ − p , s p ) Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 20 / 66

  7. Nash Equilibrium: Examples Why are these games be called “matrix” games? Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 21 / 66

  8. Nash Equilibrium: Examples Why are these games be called “matrix” games? How many vector matrices (and of which size) need to be used to represent a game with N players where each player has M strategies? Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 21 / 66

  9. Nash Equilibrium: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with pure strategies) The prisoner dilemma collaborate deny collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) Rock-Scisor-Paper Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 21 / 66

  10. Nash Equilibrium: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with pure strategies) The prisoner dilemma Battle of the sexes Paul / Claire Opera Foot collaborate deny Opera (2 , 1) (0 , 0) collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) Foot (0 , 0) (1 , 2) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) ⇒ not efficient Rock-Scisor-Paper 1 / 2 P R S P (0 , 0) (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) R ( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) (1 , − 1) S (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 21 / 66

  11. Nash Equilibrium: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with pure strategies) The prisoner dilemma Battle of the sexes Paul / Claire Opera Foot collaborate deny Opera (2 , 1) (0 , 0) collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) Foot (0 , 0) (1 , 2) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) ⇒ not unique ⇒ not efficient Rock-Scisor-Paper 1 / 2 P R S P (0 , 0) (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) R ( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) (1 , − 1) S (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) ⇒ No equilibrium Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 21 / 66

  12. Mixed Nash Equilibria Definition: Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibria . A mixed strategy for player i is a probability distribution over the set of pure strategies of player i . An equilibrium in mixed strategies is a strategy profile σ ∗ of mixed strategies such that: ∀ p, ∀ σ i , u p ( σ ∗ − p , σ ∗ p ) ≥ u p ( σ ∗ − p , σ p ) . Theorem 2. Any finite n -person noncooperative game has at least one equilibrium n -tuple of mixed strategies. Proof . Kakutani fixed point theorem: Apply Kakutani to f : σ �→ ⊗ i ∈{ 1 ,N } B i ( σ i ) with B i ( σ ) the best response of player i . Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 22 / 66

  13. Mixed Nash Equilibria Definition: Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibria . A mixed strategy for player i is a probability distribution over the set of Consequence: pure strategies of player i . An equilibrium in mixed strategies is a strategy profile σ ∗ of mixed ◮ The players mixed strategies are independant randomizations.   strategies such that: ∀ p, ∀ σ i , u p ( σ ∗ − p , σ ∗ p ) ≥ u p ( σ ∗ − p , σ p ) . � �  u i ( a ) . ◮ In a finite game, u p ( σ ) = σ p ′ ( a p ′ ) a p ′ Theorem 2. ◮ Function u i is multilinear Any finite n -person noncooperative game has at least one equilibrium ◮ In a finite game, σ ∗ is a Nash equilibrium iff ∀ a i in the support n -tuple of mixed strategies. of σ i , a i is a best response to σ ∗ − i Proof . Kakutani fixed point theorem: Apply Kakutani to f : σ �→ ⊗ i ∈{ 1 ,N } B i ( σ i ) with B i ( σ ) the best response of player i . Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 22 / 66

  14. Mixed Nash Equilibria: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with mixed strategies) The prisoner dilemma collaborate deny collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 23 / 66

  15. Mixed Nash Equilibria: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with mixed strategies) The prisoner dilemma Battle of the sexes Paul / Claire Opera Foot collaborate deny Opera (2 , 1) (0 , 0) collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) Foot (0 , 0) (1 , 2) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) ⇒ No strictly mixed equilibria Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 23 / 66

  16. Mixed Nash Equilibria: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with mixed strategies) The prisoner dilemma Battle of the sexes Paul / Claire Opera Foot collaborate deny Opera (2 , 1) (0 , 0) collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) Foot (0 , 0) (1 , 2) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) σ 1 = (2 / 3 , 1 / 3) , σ 2 = (1 / 3 , 2 / 3) ⇒ No strictly mixed equilibria Rock-Scisor-Paper Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 23 / 66

  17. Mixed Nash Equilibria: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with mixed strategies) The prisoner dilemma Battle of the sexes Paul / Claire Opera Foot collaborate deny Opera (2 , 1) (0 , 0) collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) Foot (0 , 0) (1 , 2) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) σ 1 = (2 / 3 , 1 / 3) , σ 2 = (1 / 3 , 2 / 3) ⇒ No strictly mixed equilibria Rock-Scisor-Paper 1 / 2 P R S P (0 , 0) (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) R ( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) (1 , − 1) S (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 23 / 66

  18. Mixed Nash Equilibria: Examples Find the Nash equilibria of these games (with mixed strategies) The prisoner dilemma Battle of the sexes Paul / Claire Opera Foot collaborate deny Opera (2 , 1) (0 , 0) collaborate (1 , 1) (3 , 0) Foot (0 , 0) (1 , 2) deny (0 , 3) (2 , 2) σ 1 = (2 / 3 , 1 / 3) , σ 2 = (1 / 3 , 2 / 3) ⇒ No strictly mixed equilibria Rock-Scisor-Paper 1 / 2 P R S P (0 , 0) (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) R ( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) (1 , − 1) S (1 , − 1)( − 1 , 1) (0 , 0) σ 1 = σ 2 = (1 / 3 , 1 / 3 , 1 / 3) Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Simple Games 23 / 66

  19. Outline ”Simple” Games and their solutions: One Round, Simultaneous 1 plays, Perfect Information Zero-Sum Games General Case Two Inspiring Examples 2 Optimality 3 Bargaining Concepts 4 Measuring the Inefficiency of a Policy 5 Application: Multiple Bag-of-Task Applications in Distributed 6 Platforms Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 24 / 66

  20. The Prisoner Dilemma Prisoner B stays Silent Prisoner B Betrays Prisoner A: 10 years A stays Silent Each serves 6 months Prisoner B: goes free Prisoner A goes free A Betrays Each serves 5 years Prisoner B: 10 years What is the best interest of each prisoner? What is the output (Nash Equilibrium) of the game? Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 25 / 66

  21. The Prisoner Dilemma - Cost Space Cost for Prisoner B (B,S) What are the optimal points? (B,B) What is the equilibrium? (S,S) (S,B) Cost for Prisoner A Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 26 / 66

  22. The Prisoner Dilemma - Cost Space Cost for Prisoner B (B,S) What are the optimal points? Equilibrium Point (B,B) What is the equilibrium? (S,S) (S,B) Cost for Prisoner A Optimal points Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 26 / 66

  23. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? x ◮ 2 possibles routes ◮ the needed time is a function 10 .a b + 50 of the number of cars on the road (congestion) A B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  24. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 A B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  25. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 Cost of route “north”: A B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  26. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 Cost of route “north”: 10 ∗ x + ( x + 50) = 11 ∗ x + 50 A B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  27. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 Cost of route “north”: 10 ∗ x + ( x + 50) = 11 ∗ x + 50 A B Cost of route “south”: c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  28. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 Cost of route “north”: 10 ∗ x + ( x + 50) = 11 ∗ x + 50 A B Cost of route “south”: ( y + 50) + 10 ∗ y = 11 ∗ y + 50 c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  29. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 Cost of route “north”: 10 ∗ x + ( x + 50) = 11 ∗ x + 50 A B Cost of route “south”: ( y + 50) + 10 ∗ y = 11 ∗ y + 50 Constraint: x + y = 6 c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  30. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 Cost of route “north”: 10 ∗ x + ( x + 50) = 11 ∗ x + 50 A B Cost of route “south”: ( y + 50) + 10 ∗ y = 11 ∗ y + 50 Constraint: x + y = 6 c + 50 10 .d y Conclusion? What if everyone makes the same reasoning? Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  31. The Braess Paradox Question: A flow of users goes from A to B, with rate of 6 (thousands of people / sec). Each driver has two possible routes to go from A to B. Who takes which route? Which route will one take? x The one with minimum cost 10 .a b + 50 Cost of route “north”: 10 ∗ x + ( x + 50) = 11 ∗ x + 50 A B Cost of route “south”: ( y + 50) + 10 ∗ y = 11 ∗ y + 50 Constraint: x + y = 6 c + 50 10 .d y Conclusion? What if everyone makes the same reasoning? We get x = y = 3 and everyone receives 83 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 27 / 66

  32. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? x 10 .a b + 50 z A e + 10 B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  33. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is x 10 .a b + 50 z A e + 10 B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  34. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x 10 .a b + 50 z A e + 10 B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  35. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x Cost of route“north”: 10 .a b + 50 z A e + 10 B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  36. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x Cost of route“north”: 10 .a 10 ∗ ( x + z ) + ( x + 50) = b + 50 z 11 ∗ x + 50 + 10 ∗ z A e + 10 B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  37. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x Cost of route“north”: 10 .a 10 ∗ ( x + z ) + ( x + 50) = b + 50 z 11 ∗ x + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of route “south”: A e + 10 B c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  38. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x Cost of route“north”: 10 .a 10 ∗ ( x + z ) + ( x + 50) = b + 50 z 11 ∗ x + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of route “south”: A e + 10 B 11 ∗ y + 50 + 10 ∗ z c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  39. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x Cost of route“north”: 10 .a 10 ∗ ( x + z ) + ( x + 50) = b + 50 z 11 ∗ x + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of route “south”: A e + 10 B 11 ∗ y + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of “new” route: c + 50 10 .d y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  40. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x Cost of route“north”: 10 .a 10 ∗ ( x + z ) + ( x + 50) = b + 50 z 11 ∗ x + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of route “south”: A e + 10 B 11 ∗ y + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of “new” route: c + 50 10 .d 10 ∗ x + 10 ∗ y + 21 ∗ z + 10 y Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  41. The Braess Paradox A new road is opened! What happens? If noone takes it, it cost is 70! so rational users will take it... � x Cost of route“north”: 10 .a 10 ∗ ( x + z ) + ( x + 50) = b + 50 z 11 ∗ x + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of route “south”: A e + 10 B 11 ∗ y + 50 + 10 ∗ z Cost of “new” route: c + 50 10 .d 10 ∗ x + 10 ∗ y + 21 ∗ z + 10 y Conclusion? We get x = y = z = 2 and everyone gets a cost of 92 ! Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 28 / 66

  42. The Braess Paradox In le New York Times, 25 Dec., 1990, Page 38, What if They Closed 42d Street and Nobody Noticed?, By GINA KOLATA: ON Earth Day this year, New York City’s Transportation Commissioner decided to close 42d Street, which as every New Yorker knows is always congested. ”Many predicted it would be doomsday,” said the Commissioner, Lucius J. Riccio. ”You didn’t need to be a rocket scientist or have a sophisticated computer queuing model to see that this could have been a major problem.” But to everyone’s surprise, Earth Day generated no historic traffic jam. Traffic flow actually improved when 42d Street was closed. Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 29 / 66

  43. Braess Paradox: Definition Definition: Braess-paradox . A Braess-paradoxes is a situation where exists two configurations S 1 and S 2 corresponding to utility sets U ( S 1 ) and U ( S 2 ) such that U ( S 1 ) ⊂ U ( S 2 ) and ∀ k, α k ( S 1 ) > α k ( S 2 ) with α ( S ) being the utility vector at equilibrium point for utility set S . ◮ In other words, in a Braess paradox, adding resource to the system decreases the utility of all players. ◮ Note that in systems where the equilibria are (Pareto) optimal, Braess paradoxes cannot occur. Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 30 / 66

  44. Efficiency versus (Individual) Stability Prisoner Dilemma / Braess paradox show: ◮ Inherent conflict between individual interest and global interest ◮ Inherent conflict between stability and optimality Typical problem in economy: free-market economy versus regulated economy. Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 31 / 66

  45. Efficiency versus (Individual) Stability Free-Market: Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 31 / 66

  46. Efficiency versus (Individual) Stability Regulated Market Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Two Inspiring Examples 31 / 66

  47. Outline ”Simple” Games and their solutions: One Round, Simultaneous 1 plays, Perfect Information Zero-Sum Games General Case Two Inspiring Examples 2 Optimality 3 Bargaining Concepts 4 Measuring the Inefficiency of a Policy 5 Application: Multiple Bag-of-Task Applications in Distributed 6 Platforms Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 32 / 66

  48. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems ◮ Optimality for a single user Utility Optimal point Parameter Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  49. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems ◮ Situation with multiple users Utility of user 2 Good for user 2 Good for user 1 Utility of user 1 Analogy with: multi-criteria, hierarchical, zenith optimization. Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  50. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  51. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  52. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  53. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  54. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  55. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  56. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  57. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  58. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  59. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  60. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Pareto Optimality . A point is said Pareto optimal if it cannot be strictly dominated by another. Utility of user 2 Utility of user 1 Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  61. Defining Optimality in Multi-User Sytems Definition: Canonical order . We define the strict partial order ≪ on R n + , namely the strict Pareto-superiority, by u ≪ v ⇔ ∀ k : u k ≤ v k and ∃ ℓ, u ℓ < v ℓ . Definition: Pareto optimality . A choice u ∈ U is said to be Pareto optimal if it is maximal in U for the canonical partial order on R n + . A policy function α is said to be Pareto-optimal if ∀ U ∈ U , α ( U ) is Pareto-optimal. Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Optimality 33 / 66

  62. Outline ”Simple” Games and their solutions: One Round, Simultaneous 1 plays, Perfect Information Zero-Sum Games General Case Two Inspiring Examples 2 Optimality 3 Bargaining Concepts 4 Measuring the Inefficiency of a Policy 5 Application: Multiple Bag-of-Task Applications in Distributed 6 Platforms Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 34 / 66

  63. Bargaining Theory ◮ Aims at predicting the outcome of a bargain between 2 (or more) players ◮ The players are bargaining over a set of goods ◮ To each good is associated for each player a utility (for instance real valued) Assumptions: ◮ Players have identical bargaining power ◮ Players have identical bargaining skills Then, players will eventually agree on an point considered as “fair” for both of them. Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 35 / 66

  64. The Nash Solution Let S be a feasible set, closed, convex, ( u ∗ , v ∗ ) a point in this set, enforced if no agreement is reached. A fair solution is a point φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) satisfying the set of axioms: 1 (Individual Rationality) φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) ≥ ( u ∗ , v ∗ ) (componentwise) 2 (Feasibility) φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) ∈ S 3 (Pareto-Optimality) ∀ ( u, v ) ∈ S, ( u, v ) ≥ φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) → ( u, v ) = φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) 4 (Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives) φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) ∈ T ⊂ S ⇒ φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = φ ( T, u ∗ , v ∗ ) 5 (Independence of Linear Transformations) Let F ( u, v ) = ( α 1 u + β 1 , α 2 v + β 2 ) , T = F ( S ) , then φ ( T, F ( u ∗ , v ∗ )) = F ( φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ )) 6 (Symmetry) If S is such that ( u, v ) ∈ S ⇔ ( v, u ) ∈ S and u ∗ = v ∗ then φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) def = ( a, b ) is such that a = b Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  65. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  66. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  67. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  68. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Symmetry Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  69. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Symmetry Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  70. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Symmetry ( u ∗ , v ∗ ) Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  71. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Rationality Symmetry ( u ∗ , v ∗ ) Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  72. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Rationality Symmetry ( u ∗ , v ∗ ) Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  73. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Ind. to Lin. Transf. Symmetry ( u ∗ , v ∗ ) Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  74. The Nash Solution Proposition: Nash Bargaining Solution There is a unique solution function φ satisfying all axioms: φ ( S, u ∗ , v ∗ ) = max u,v ( u − u ∗ )( v − v ∗ ) Proof . First case: Positive quadrant Second Case: General case right isosceles triangle Feasability Ind. Irr. Alter. Symmetry ( u ∗ , v ∗ ) Pareto Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 36 / 66

  75. The Nash Solution Example Example (The Rich and the Poor Man) ◮ A rich man, a wealth of $1 . 000 . 000 ◮ A poor man, with a wealth of $100 ◮ A sum of $100 to be shared between them. If they can’t agree, none of them gets anything ◮ The utility to get some amount of money is the logarithm of the wealth growth ◮ How much should each one gets? Let x be the sum going to the rich man. � 1000000 + x � � 200 − x � x u ( x ) = log ∼ 1000000 and v ( x ) = log . 1000000 100 � 200 − x � The NBS is the solution of: max x log , i.e. 100 x = $54 . 5 and $45 . 5 the rich gets more! � Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 37 / 66

  76. Axiomatic Definition VS Optimization Problem 1 Individual Rationality 2 Feasibility 3 Pareto-Optimality 5 Independence of Linear Transformations 6 Symmetry Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 38 / 66

  77. Axiomatic Definition VS Optimization Problem   4 Independant to irrelevant      alternatives Nash (NBS) /  �   ( u i − u d 1 Individual Rationality  Proportional Fairness i )     2 Feasibility  4 Monotony      3 Pareto-Optimality Raiffa-Kalai-Smorodinsky /  max-min + 5 Independence of   Recursively max { u i |∀ j, u i ≤ u j }  Linear     4 Inverse Monotony Transformations     Thomson / global Optimum  6 Symmetry     (Social welfare)  �    max u i  Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 38 / 66

  78. Example: The Flow Control Problem (1) 4 connections / 3 links. x 1 x 2 x 3  x 1 + x 0 ≤ 1 ,  x 2 + x 0 ≤ 1 ,  x 3 + x 0 ≤ 1 . x 0 ⇒ 4 variables and 3 (in)equalities. How to choose x 0 among the Pareto optimal points? x i x 0 (Nota: in this case the utility set is the same as the strategy set) Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 39 / 66

  79. Example: The Flow Control Problem (1) 4 connections / 3 links. x 1 x 2 x 3  x 1 + x 0 ≤ 1 ,  x 2 + x 0 ≤ 1 ,  x 3 + x 0 ≤ 1 . x 0 ⇒ 4 variables and 3 (in)equalities. How to choose x 0 among the Pareto SO optimal points? x i PF � x 0 = 0 . 5 , Mm Max-Min fairness x 1 = x 2 = x 3 = 0 . 5 � x 0 = 0 , Social Optimum x 1 = x 2 = x 3 = 1 � x 0 = 0 . 25 , x 0 x 1 = x 2 = x 3 = 0 . 75 Proportionnal Fairness (Nota: in this case the utility set is the same as the strategy set) Corinne Touati (INRIA) Part I. Main Concepts Bargaining Concepts 39 / 66

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend