experimental identification of causal mechanisms
play

Experimental Identification of Causal Mechanisms Kosuke Imai 1 Dustin - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Experimental Identification of Causal Mechanisms Kosuke Imai 1 Dustin Tingley 2 Teppei Yamamoto 3 1 Princeton University 2 Harvard University 3 Massachusetts Institute of Technology March 14, 2012 Royal Statistical Society, London


  1. Experimental Identification of Causal Mechanisms Kosuke Imai 1 Dustin Tingley 2 Teppei Yamamoto 3 1 Princeton University 2 Harvard University 3 Massachusetts Institute of Technology March 14, 2012 Royal Statistical Society, London Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 1 / 26

  2. Experiments, Statistics, and Causal Mechanisms Causal inference is a central goal of most scientific research Experiments as gold standard for estimating causal effects A major criticism of experimentation: it can only determine whether the treatment causes changes in the outcome, but not how and why Experiments merely provide a black box view of causality But, scientific theories are all about causal mechanisms Knowledge about causal mechanisms can also improve policies Key Challenge: How can we design and analyze experiments to identify causal mechanisms? Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 2 / 26

  3. Overview of the Talk Show the limitation of a common approach Consider alternative experimental designs What is a minimum set of assumptions required for identification under each design? How much can we learn without the key identification assumptions under each design? Identification of causal mechanisms is possible but difficult Distinction between design and statistical assumptions Roles of creativity and technological developments Illustrate key ideas through recent social science research Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 3 / 26

  4. Causal Mechanisms as Indirect Effects What is a causal mechanism? Cochran (1957)’s example: soil fumigants increase farm crops by reducing eel-worms Political science example: incumbency advantage Causal mediation analysis Mediator, M Treatment, T Outcome, Y Quantities of interest: Direct and indirect effects Fast growing methodological literature Alternative definition: causal components (Robins; VanderWeele) Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 4 / 26

  5. Formal Statistical Framework of Causal Inference Binary treatment: T i ∈ { 0 , 1 } Mediator: M i ∈ M Outcome: Y i ∈ Y Observed pre-treatment covariates: X i ∈ X Potential mediators: M i ( t ) where M i = M i ( T i ) Potential outcomes: Y i ( t , m ) where Y i = Y i ( T i , M i ( T i )) Fundamental problem of causal inference (Rubin; Holland): Only one potential value is observed If T i = 1, then M i ( 1 ) is observed but M i ( 0 ) is not 1 If T i = 0 and M i ( 0 ) = 0, then Y i ( 0 , 0 ) is observed but 2 Y i ( 1 , 0 ) , Y i ( 0 , m ) , and Y i ( 1 , m ) are not when m � = 0 Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 5 / 26

  6. Defining and Interpreting Indirect Effects Total causal effect: τ i ≡ Y i ( 1 , M i ( 1 )) − Y i ( 0 , M i ( 0 )) Indirect (causal mediation) effects (Robins and Greenland; Pearl): δ i ( t ) ≡ Y i ( t , M i ( 1 )) − Y i ( t , M i ( 0 )) Change M i ( 0 ) to M i ( 1 ) while holding the treatment constant at t Effect of a change in M i on Y i that would be induced by treatment Fundamental problem of causal mechanisms: For each unit i, Y i ( t , M i ( t )) is observable but Y i ( t , M i ( 1 − t )) is not even observable Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 6 / 26

  7. Defining and Interpreting Direct Effects Direct effects: ζ i ( t ) ≡ Y i ( 1 , M i ( t )) − Y i ( 0 , M i ( t )) Change T i from 0 to 1 while holding the mediator constant at M i ( t ) Causal effect of T i on Y i , holding mediator constant at its potential value that would be realized when T i = t Total effect = indirect effect + direct effect: = δ i ( t ) + ζ i ( 1 − t ) τ i = δ i + ζ i where the second equality assumes δ i ( 0 ) = δ i ( 1 ) and ζ i ( 0 ) = ζ i ( 1 ) Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 7 / 26

  8. Mechanisms, Manipulations, and Interactions Mechanisms Indirect effects: δ i ( t ) ≡ Y i ( t , M i ( 1 )) − Y i ( t , M i ( 0 )) Counterfactuals about treatment-induced mediator values Manipulations Controlled direct effects: ξ i ( t , m , m ′ ) ≡ Y i ( t , m ) − Y i ( t , m ′ ) Causal effect of directly manipulating the mediator under T i = t Interactions Interaction effects: ξ ( 1 , m , m ′ ) − ξ ( 0 , m , m ′ ) � = 0 Doesn’t imply the existence of a mechanism Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 8 / 26

  9. Single Experiment Design Assumption Satisfied Randomization of treatment { Y i ( t , m ) , M i ( t ′ ) } ⊥ ⊥ T i , | X i = x Key Identifying Assumption Sequential Ignorability: Y i ( t ′ , m ) ⊥ ⊥ M i | T i = t , X i = x Selection on pre-treatment observables Unmeasured pre-treatment confounders Measured and unmeasured post-treatment confounders Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 9 / 26

  10. Identification under the Single Experiment Design Sequential ignorability yields nonparametric identification � � ¯ δ ( t ) = E ( Y i | M i , T i = t , X i ) { dP ( M i | T i = 1 , X i ) − dP ( M i | T i = 0 , X i ) } dP ( X i ) Linear structural equation modeling (a.k.a. Baron-Kenny) Alternative assumptions: Robins, Pearl, Petersen et al. , VanderWeele, and many others Sequential ignorability is an untestable assumption Sensitivity analysis: How large a departure from sequential ignorability must occur for the conclusions to no longer hold? But, sensitivity analysis does not solve the problem Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 10 / 26

  11. A Typical Psychological Experiment Brader et al. : media framing experiment Treatment: Ethnicity (Latino vs. Caucasian) of an immigrant Mediator: anxiety Outcome: preferences over immigration policy Single experiment design with statistical mediation analysis Emotion: difficult to directly manipulate Sequential ignorability assumption is not credible Possible confounding Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 11 / 26

  12. Identification Power of the Single Experiment Design How much can we learn without sequential ignorability? Sharp bounds on indirect effects (Sjölander):     − P 001 − P 011 P 101 + P 111      ≤ ¯ − P 011 − P 010 − P 110 P 010 + P 110 + P 111 max δ ( 1 ) ≤ min − P 000 − P 001 − P 100 P 000 + P 100 + P 101        − P 100 − P 110 P 000 + P 010      ≤ ¯ − P 011 − P 111 − P 110 δ ( 0 ) ≤ min P 011 + P 111 + P 010 max − P 001 − P 101 − P 100 P 000 + P 001 + P 101    where P ymt = Pr ( Y i = y , M i = m | T i = t ) The sign is not identified Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 12 / 26

  13. Alternative Experimental Designs Can we design experiments to better identify causal mechanisms? Perfect manipulation of the mediator: Parallel Design 1 Crossover Design 2 Imperfect manipulation of the mediator: Parallel Encouragement Design 1 Crossover Encouragement Design 2 Implications for designing observational studies Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 13 / 26

  14. The Parallel Design No manipulation effect assumption: The manipulation has no direct effect on outcome other than through the mediator value Running two experiments in parallel: Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 14 / 26

  15. Identification under the Parallel Design Difference between manipulation and mechanism: Prop. M i ( 1 ) M i ( 0 ) Y i ( t , 1 ) Y i ( t , 0 ) δ i ( t ) 0.3 1 0 0 1 − 1 0.3 0 0 1 0 0 0.1 0 1 0 1 1 0.3 1 1 1 0 0 E ( M i ( 1 ) − M i ( 0 )) = E ( Y i ( t , 1 ) − Y i ( t , 0 )) = 0 . 2, but ¯ δ ( t ) = − 0 . 2 Is the randomization of mediator sufficient? No The no interaction assumption (Robins) yields point identification Y i ( 1 , m ) − Y i ( 1 , m ′ ) = Y i ( 0 , m ) − Y i ( 0 , m ′ ) Must hold at the unit level but indirect tests are possible Implication: analyze a group of homogeneous units Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 15 / 26

  16. Identification under the Parallel Design Is the randomization of mediator sufficient? No! Sharp bounds: Binary mediator and outcome Use of linear programming (Balke and Pearl): Objective function: 1 1 � � E { Y i ( 1 , M i ( 0 )) } = ( π 1 ym 1 + π y 1 m 1 ) y = 0 m = 0 where π y 1 y 0 m 1 m 0 = Pr ( Y i ( 1 , 1 ) = y 1 , Y i ( 1 , 0 ) = y 0 , M i ( 1 ) = m 1 , M i ( 0 ) = m 0 ) Constraints implied by Pr ( Y i = y , M i = m | T i = t , D i = 0 ) , Pr ( Y i = y | M i = m , T i = t , D i = 1 ) , and the summation constraint More informative than those under the single experiment design Can sometimes identify the sign of average direct/indirect effects Imai/Tingley/Yamamoto (PU/HU/MIT) Experiments and Causal Mechanisms RSS, London (March 14, 2012) 16 / 26

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend