everything
play

Everything Second Example of . . . Third Example of . . . Is a - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Everything Is a Matter . . . Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . First Example of . . . Everything Second Example of . . . Third Example of . . . Is a Matter of Degree: Our Explanation of . . . First Explanation: . . . Second


  1. Everything Is a Matter . . . Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . First Example of . . . Everything Second Example of . . . Third Example of . . . Is a Matter of Degree: Our Explanation of . . . First Explanation: . . . Second Explanation: . . . A New Theoretical Symmetry: Another . . . Case Study: Territory . . . Justification of Acknowledgments Title Page Zadeh’s Principle ◭◭ ◮◮ Hung T. Nguyen ◭ ◮ Department of Mathematical Sciences Page 1 of 13 New Mexico State University Go Back Vladik Kreinovich Department of Computer Science Full Screen University of Texas at El Paso Close El Paso, TX 79968 Email: vladik@utep.edu Quit

  2. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 1. Everything Is a Matter of Degree: One of the Main Ideas Behind Fuzzy Logic First Example of . . . Second Example of . . . • One of the main ideas behind Zadeh’s fuzzy logic and Third Example of . . . its applications is that everything is a matter of degree. Our Explanation of . . . First Explanation: . . . • We are often accustomed to think that every statement about a physical world is true or false: Second Explanation: . . . Symmetry: Another . . . – that an object is either a particle or a wave, Case Study: Territory . . . – that a person is either young or not, Acknowledgments – that a person is either well or ill. Title Page • However, in reality, we sometimes encounter interme- ◭◭ ◮◮ diate situations. ◭ ◮ Page 2 of 13 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  3. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 2. Formulation of the Problem First Example of . . . • That everything is a matter of degree is a convincing Second Example of . . . empirical fact. Third Example of . . . Our Explanation of . . . • A natural question is: why? First Explanation: . . . • How can we explain this fact? Second Explanation: . . . • This is what we will try to do in this talk: come up Symmetry: Another . . . with a theoretical explanation of this empirical fact. Case Study: Territory . . . Acknowledgments Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ Page 3 of 13 Go Back Full Screen Close Quit

  4. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 3. There Should be an Objective Theoretical Expla- nation for Fuzziness First Example of . . . Second Example of . . . • Most traditional examples of fuzziness come from the Third Example of . . . analysis of commonsense reasoning. Our Explanation of . . . • When we reason, we use words from natural language First Explanation: . . . like “young”, “well”. Second Explanation: . . . Symmetry: Another . . . • In many practical situations, these words do not have Case Study: Territory . . . a precise true-or-false meaning, they are fuzzy. Acknowledgments • Impression: fuzziness is subjective, it is how our brains Title Page work. ◭◭ ◮◮ • However, we are the result of billions of years of suc- ◭ ◮ cessful adjusting-to-the-environment evolution. Page 4 of 13 • Everything about us humans is not accidental. Go Back • In particular, the fuzziness in our reasoning must have Full Screen an objective explanation – in fuzziness of the real world. Close Quit

  5. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 4. First Example of Objective “Fuzziness” – Fractals First Example of . . . • Since the ancient times, we know: Second Example of . . . Third Example of . . . – 0-dimensional objects (points), Our Explanation of . . . – 1-dimensional objects (lines), First Explanation: . . . – 2-dimensional objects (surfaces), Second Explanation: . . . – 3-dimensional objects (bodies), etc. Symmetry: Another . . . • In all these examples, dim is an integer: 0, 1, 2, 3, etc. Case Study: Territory . . . Acknowledgments • In the 19th century, mathematicians discovered sets of Title Page fractional dimension (fractals). ◭◭ ◮◮ • In the 1970s, B. Mandlebrot noticed that many real-life ◭ ◮ objects are fractals, e.g.: Page 5 of 13 – shoreline of England Go Back – shape of the clouds and mountains Full Screen – noises in electric circuits. Close Quit

  6. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 5. Second Example of Objective “Fuzziness” – Quan- tum Physics First Example of . . . Second Example of . . . • In general, states are described by continuous variables. Third Example of . . . Our Explanation of . . . • However, the set of stable states is usually discrete . First Explanation: . . . • Example: computers use memory cells with 2 stable Second Explanation: . . . states representing 0 and 1. Symmetry: Another . . . • In quantum physics: we can have superpositions Case Study: Territory . . . c 0 · � 0 | + c 1 · � 1 | for complex c i . Acknowledgments • Resulting quantum computations are much faster: Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ – we can search in an unsorted list of n elements in time √ n ; ◭ ◮ – we can factor large integers fast – and thus, crack Page 6 of 13 the existing codes. Go Back • What we originally thought of as an integer-valued Full Screen variable turned out to be real-valued. Close Quit

  7. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 6. Third Example of Objective “Fuzziness” – Frac- tional Charges of Quarks First Example of . . . Second Example of . . . • Matter is seemingly continuous. Third Example of . . . • It turned out that matter is discrete: it consists of Our Explanation of . . . molecules, atoms, and elementary particles. First Explanation: . . . Second Explanation: . . . • One experimental fact: all electric charges are propor- Symmetry: Another . . . tional to a single charge. Case Study: Territory . . . • Thus, protons, etc., cannot be further decomposed. Acknowledgments • Gell-Mann discovered that we can design p , n , mesons, Title Page etc. in terms of a few quarks . ◭◭ ◮◮ • Interesting aspect: quarks have fractional electric charge. ◭ ◮ • Original idea: quarks are theoretical concepts. Page 7 of 13 • Experiments revealed 3 partons within p – actual quarks. Go Back • So, what we originally thought of as an integer-valued Full Screen variable turned out to be real-valued. Close Quit

  8. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 7. Our Explanation of Why Physical Quantities Origi- nally Thought to Be Integer-Valued Turned out to First Example of . . . Be Real-Valued: Main Idea Second Example of . . . Third Example of . . . • In philosophical terms: what we are doing is “cogniz- Our Explanation of . . . ing” the world. First Explanation: . . . • Clarification: understanding how it works and trying Second Explanation: . . . to predict consequences of different actions. Symmetry: Another . . . Case Study: Territory . . . • Objective: select the most beneficial action. Acknowledgments • If a phenomenon is not cognizable, there is nothing we Title Page can do about it. ◭◭ ◮◮ • Our explanation: in cognizable phenomena, it is rea- ◭ ◮ sonable to expect continuous-valued variables. Page 8 of 13 • In other words: properties originally thought to be dis- Go Back crete are actually matters of degree. Full Screen Close Quit

  9. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 8. First Explanation: Goedel’s Theorem vs. Tarski’s Algorithm First Example of . . . Second Example of . . . • Goedel’s theorem: 1st example of non-cognizability. Third Example of . . . • Formulations: Our Explanation of . . . First Explanation: . . . – variables x , y , z , etc. run over integers; Second Explanation: . . . – terms t are formed from x , . . . , and const. by +, · ; Symmetry: Another . . . – elementary formulas: t = t ′ , t < t ′ , t ≤ t ′ , etc. Case Study: Territory . . . – formulas: from elem. formulas by ∨ , &, ¬ , ∃ , ∀ . Acknowledgments • Example: ∀ x ∀ y ( x < y → ∃ z ( y = x + z )) . Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ • Goedel’s theorem: no algorithm can tell whether a given formula is true or not. ◭ ◮ • Tarski’s theorem: if we consider variables over real Page 9 of 13 numbers, then such an algorithm is possible. Go Back • Conclusion: in cognizable situations, we must have Full Screen continuous-valued variables. Close Quit

  10. Formulation of the . . . There Should be an . . . 9. Second Explanation: Efficient Algorithms for Lin- ear Algebra vs. NP-Hardness of Integer Program- First Example of . . . ming Second Example of . . . Third Example of . . . • Practical situation: find the values x 1 , . . . , x n from the Our Explanation of . . . results y 1 , . . . , y m of indirect measurements: First Explanation: . . . f 1 ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) = y 1 ; f m ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) = y m . Second Explanation: . . . Symmetry: Another . . . • Frequent case: we know approximate � x i values of x i . Case Study: Territory . . . • How this helps: we can linearize the system: Acknowledgments Title Page a i 1 · ∆ x 1 + . . . + a in · ∆ x n = ∆ y i , 1 ≤ i ≤ m. ◭◭ ◮◮ • Case of continuous variables: efficient algorithms solve ◭ ◮ systems of linear equations. Page 10 of 13 • Case of discrete variables: problem becomes NP-hard. Go Back • Meaning (informal): every algorithm requires un-realistic Full Screen time in some cases (unless P=NP). Close Quit

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend