equations
play

Equations Second Example: . . . Interesting Relation to . . . - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . Equations Second Example: . . . Interesting Relation to . . . Without Equations: Acknowledgments Challenges on a Way Physicists Assume . . . to a More Adequate Title Page


  1. Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . Equations Second Example: . . . Interesting Relation to . . . Without Equations: Acknowledgments Challenges on a Way Physicists Assume . . . to a More Adequate Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ Formalization of ◭ ◮ Reasoning in Physics Page 1 of 22 Go Back Roberto Araiza, Vladik Kreinovich, and Juan Ferret Full Screen University of Texas, El Paso, TX 79968, USA raraiza@gmail.com, vladik@utep.edu Close Quit

  2. 1. Need to Formalize Reasoning in Physics Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • Fact: in medicine, geophysics, etc., expert systems use Second Example: . . . automated expert reasoning to help the users. Interesting Relation to . . . • Hope: similar systems may be helpful in general theo- Acknowledgments retical physics as well. Physicists Assume . . . • What is needed: describe physicists’ reasoning in pre- Title Page cise terms. ◭◭ ◮◮ • Reason: formalize this reasoning inside an automated computer system. ◭ ◮ • Formalized part of physicists’ reasoning: theories are Page 2 of 22 formulated in terms of PDEs (or ODEs) dx dt = F ( x ). Go Back Full Screen • Meaning: these equations describe how the correspond- ing fields (or quantities) x change with time t . Close Quit

  3. 2. Mathematician’s View of Physics and Its Limita- Need to Formalize . . . tions First Example: . . . Second Example: . . . • Mathematician’s view: we know the initial conditions Interesting Relation to . . . x ( t 0 ) at some moment of time t 0 . Acknowledgments • We solve the corresponding Cauchy problem and find Physicists Assume . . . the values x ( t ) for all t . • Limitation: not all solutions to the equation Title Page dx dt = F ( x ) are physically meaningful. ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ • Example 1: when a cup breaks into pieces, the corre- sponding trajectories of molecules make physical sense. Page 3 of 22 • Example 2: when we reverse all the velocities, we get Go Back pieces assembling themselves into a cup. Full Screen • Fact: this is physically impossible. Close • Fact: the reverse process satisfies all the original Quit (T-invariant) equations.

  4. 3. Physicists’ Explanation Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • Reminder: not all solutions to the physical equation Second Example: . . . are physically meaningful. Interesting Relation to . . . • Explanation: the “time-reversed” solution is non-physical Acknowledgments because its initial conditions are “degenerate”. Physicists Assume . . . • Clarification: once we modify the initial conditions even slightly, the pieces will no longer get together. Title Page • Conclusion: not only the equations must be satisfied, ◭◭ ◮◮ but also the initial conditions must be “non-degenerate”. ◭ ◮ • Two challenges in formalizing this idea: Page 4 of 22 – how to formalize “non-degenerate”; Go Back – the separation between equations and initial condi- Full Screen tions depends on the way equations are presented. Close • First challenge: can be resolved by using Kolmogorov Quit complexity and randomness.

  5. 4. First Example: Schr¨ odinger’s Equation Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • Example: Schr¨ odinger’s equation Second Example: . . . ∂t = − � 2 i � · ∂ Ψ 2 m · ∇ 2 Ψ + V ( � Interesting Relation to . . . r ) · Ψ . Acknowledgments • In this representation: the potential V is a part of the Physicists Assume . . . equation, and Ψ( � r, t 0 ) are initial conditions. Title Page • Transformation: ◭◭ ◮◮ – we represent V ( � r ) as a function of Ψ and its deriva- ◭ ◮ tives, Page 5 of 22 – differentiate the right-hand side by time, and – equate the derivative w.r.t. time to 0. Go Back Full Screen • Result: ∂t + � 2 2 m · ∇ 2 Ψ � i � � ∂ Ψ · ∂ Ψ Close = 0 . Ψ ∂t Quit

  6. 5. First Example (cont-d) Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • Reminder: Second Example: . . . ∂t + � 2 2 m · ∇ 2 Ψ � i � Ψ · ∂ Ψ � ∂ = 0 . Interesting Relation to . . . ∂t Ψ Acknowledgments Physicists Assume . . . • Mathematically: the new equation (2nd order in time) is equivalent to the Schr¨ odinger’s equation: Title Page – every solution of the Schr¨ odinger’s equation for any ◭◭ ◮◮ V ( � r ) satisfies this new equation, and ◭ ◮ – every solution of the new equation satisfies Sch¨ odinger’s equation for some V ( � r ). Page 6 of 22 • Observation: in the new equation, initial conditions, in Go Back effect, include V ( � r ). Full Screen • Conclusion: “non-degeneracy” (“randomness”) condi- Close tion must now include V ( � r ) as well. Quit

  7. 6. Towards 2nd Example: General Physical Theories Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • Traditional description of physical theories: in terms Second Example: . . . of differential equations. Interesting Relation to . . . • Example (17 cent.): Newton’s mechanics m · d 2 x dt 2 = F. Acknowledgments Physicists Assume . . . • Important discovery (18 cent.): most physical theories can be reformulated as S → min for “action” S . Title Page • Example: Newton’s mechanics is equivalent to ◭◭ ◮◮ L dt → min , where L = 1 x 2 + V ( x ) . � S = 2 · m · ˙ ◭ ◮ • For functions f ( x 1 , . . . , x n ) : minimum when Page 7 of 22 f ( x + dx ) ≈ f ( x ), so ∂f = 0 for all i . Go Back ∂x i Full Screen • For functions of functions (“functionals”): minimum when S ( f + δf ) ≈ S ( f ), so δS Close δf ( x ) = 0 for all x . Quit

  8. 7. Euler-Lagrange Equations Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • Reminder: physical theories can be formulated in terms Second Example: . . . of the minimal action principle S → min. Interesting Relation to . . . � • Here, S = L dx for a “Lagrange” f-n L that depends Acknowledgments = ∂ϕ def on the fields ϕ , . . . , and their derivatives ϕ ,i . Physicists Assume . . . ∂x i � • Euler-Lagrange equations: when S = L dx , Title Page � ∂L � δS δf = ∂L ∂f − ∂ ◭◭ ◮◮ = 0 . ∂x i ∂f ,i ◭ ◮ • Comment: we use “Einstein’s rule” that repeated in- Page 8 of 22 dices mean summation: e.g., f ,i f ,i means � f ,i f ,i . Go Back i • For a single scalar field ϕ : Full Screen � ∂L ∂L ∂ϕ − ∂ � Close = 0 . ∂x i ∂ϕ ,i Quit

  9. 8. Second Example: General Scalar Field Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • General scalar theory: L = L ( ϕ, ϕ ,i ). Second Example: . . . • 3-D case: it is reasonable to consider rotation-invariant Interesting Relation to . . . Lagrangian functions L . Acknowledgments • Conclusion: L depends only on the length ϕ ,i ϕ ,i of the Physicists Assume . . . vector ϕ ,i ,not on its orientation. Title Page • 4-D case: L should be invariant w.r.t. Lorentz trans- ◭◭ ◮◮ formations (4-D “rotations”). ◭ ◮ def = ϕ ,i ϕ ,i . • Conclusion: L = L ( ϕ, a ), where a Page 9 of 22 • Traditional formulation: every Lagrangian is possible, but initial conditions ϕ ( x, t 0 ) must be non-degenerate. Go Back Full Screen • Our result: there exists a 3rd order equation such that: Close ϕ satisfies this equation ⇔ ϕ satisfies Euler-Lagrange equation for some L . Quit

  10. 9. Scalar Field: Proof Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . def = ϕ ,i ϕ ,i . • Reminder: L = L ( ϕ, a ), where a Second Example: . . . • Euler-Lagrange equations: ∂L ∂L ∂ϕ − ∂ i = 0. Interesting Relation to . . . ∂ϕ ,i Acknowledgments • Using chain rule: ∂L ( ϕ, a ) = ∂L ∂a · ∂a = ∂L Physicists Assume . . . ∂a · 2 ϕ ,i . ∂ϕ ,i ∂ϕ ,i Title Page • Conclusion: L ,ϕ − ∂ i (2 L ,a · ϕ ,i ) = 0. ◭◭ ◮◮ • Using chain rule again, we get L ,ϕ − 2 L ,a · � ϕ − 2 L ,aϕ · ( ϕ ,i ϕ ,i ) − 4 L ,aa · ϕ ,ij ϕ ,i ϕ ,j = 0 , ◭ ◮ Page 10 of 22 def = ϕ ,i where � ϕ ,i . Go Back • Conclusion: Full Screen – if at two points, we have the same values of Close ϕ , ϕ ,i ϕ ,i , and � ϕ , – then we have same values of ϕ ,ij ϕ ,i ϕ ,j . Quit

  11. 10. Scalar Field: Proof (cont-d) Need to Formalize . . . First Example: . . . • Reminder: if at two points, we have the same values of Second Example: . . . def ϕ , a = ϕ ,i ϕ ,i , and b = � ϕ , then we have same values Interesting Relation to . . . def = ϕ ,ij ϕ ,i ϕ ,j . of c Acknowledgments • Particular case: if we have dx k for which ϕ ,k · dx k = 0, Physicists Assume . . . a ,k · dx k = 0, and b ,k · dx k = 0, then c ,k · dx k = 0. • In geom. terms: if dx k ⊥ ϕ ,k , dx k ⊥ a ,k , and dx k ⊥ b ,k , Title Page then dx k ⊥ c ,k . ◭◭ ◮◮ • Conclusion: ϕ ,k , a ,k , b ,k , and c ,k lie in the same 3-plane. ◭ ◮ Page 11 of 22 • In algebraic terms: the determinant is 0: Go Back ε ijkl · ϕ ,i · a ,j · b ,k · c ,l = 0 , Full Screen where ε ijkl = 0 if some indices are equal and is ± 1 else. Close • We get a 3-rd order equation; so, we can predict future Quit evolution – w/o knowing L .

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend