decision making beyond
play

Decision Making Beyond How We Can . . . Problem: Sometimes . . . - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . Different Utility Scales Expected Utility Nashs Bargaining . . . Properties of Nashs . . . Decision Making Beyond How We Can . . . Problem: Sometimes . . . Arrows Impossibility In Case of


  1. Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . Different Utility Scales Expected Utility Nash’s Bargaining . . . Properties of Nash’s . . . Decision Making Beyond How We Can . . . Problem: Sometimes . . . Arrow’s “Impossibility In Case of Uncertainty, . . . Case Study: Territorial . . . Theorem”, with the Analysis Decision Making . . . For Territorial . . . How to Find Individual . . . of Effects of Collusion and Comments How to Find Individual . . . Mutual Attraction We Must Take . . . Paradox of Love Why Two and not Three? Hung T. Nguyen Emotional vs. . . . New Mexico State University Acknowledgments hunguyen@nmsu.edu Title Page Olga Kosheleva and Vladik Kreinovich ◭◭ ◮◮ University of Texas at El Paso ◭ ◮ vladik@utep.edu Page 1 of 25 Go Back Full Screen

  2. Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . 1. Group Decision Making and Arrow’s Impossibility Different Utility Scales Expected Utility Theorem Nash’s Bargaining . . . Properties of Nash’s . . . • In 1951, Kenneth J. Arrow published his famous result about group decision How We Can . . . making. Problem: Sometimes . . . • This result that became one of the main reasons for his 1972 Nobel Prize. In Case of Uncertainty, . . . Case Study: Territorial . . . • The problem: Decision Making . . . – A group of n participants P 1 , . . . , P n needs to select between one of m For Territorial . . . alternatives A 1 , . . . , A m . How to Find Individual . . . Comments – To find individual preferences, we ask each participant P i to rank the alternatives A j from the most desirable to the least desirable: How to Find Individual . . . We Must Take . . . A j 1 ≻ i A j 2 ≻ i . . . ≻ i A j n . Paradox of Love Why Two and not Three? – Based on these n rankings, we must form a single group ranking (in the Emotional vs. . . . group ranking, equivalence ∼ is allowed). Acknowledgments Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ Page 2 of 25 Go Back Full Screen

  3. Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . 2. Case of Two Alternatives Is Easy Different Utility Scales Expected Utility • Simplest case: Nash’s Bargaining . . . Properties of Nash’s . . . – we have only two alternatives A 1 and A 2 , How We Can . . . – each participant either prefers A 1 or prefers A 2 . Problem: Sometimes . . . In Case of Uncertainty, . . . • Solution: it is reasonable, for a group: Case Study: Territorial . . . – to prefer A 1 if the majority prefers A 1 , Decision Making . . . For Territorial . . . – to prefer A 2 if the majority prefers A 2 , and How to Find Individual . . . – to claim A 1 and A 2 to be of equal quality for the group (denoted A 1 ∼ Comments A 2 ) if there is a tie. How to Find Individual . . . We Must Take . . . Paradox of Love Why Two and not Three? Emotional vs. . . . Acknowledgments Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ Page 3 of 25 Go Back Full Screen

  4. Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . 3. Case of Three or More Alternatives Is Not Easy Different Utility Scales Expected Utility • Arrow’s result: no group decision rule can satisfy the following natural con- Nash’s Bargaining . . . ditions. Properties of Nash’s . . . How We Can . . . • Pareto condition: if all participants prefer A j to A k , then the group should Problem: Sometimes . . . also prefer A j to A k . In Case of Uncertainty, . . . • Independence from Irrelevant Alternatives: the group ranking between A j and Case Study: Territorial . . . A k should depend only on how participants rank A j and A k – and should Decision Making . . . not depend on how they rank other alternatives. For Territorial . . . How to Find Individual . . . • Arrow’s theorem: every group decision rule which satisfies these two condition Comments is a dictatorship rule: How to Find Individual . . . – the group accepts the preferences of one of the participants as the group We Must Take . . . decision and Paradox of Love – ignores the preferences of all other participants. Why Two and not Three? Emotional vs. . . . • This clearly violates another reasonable condition of symmetry : that the Acknowledgments group decision rules should not depend on the order in which we list the Title Page participants. ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ Page 4 of 25 Go Back Full Screen

  5. Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . 4. Beyond Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem: Nash’s Bar- Different Utility Scales Expected Utility gaining Solution Nash’s Bargaining . . . Properties of Nash’s . . . • Usual claim: Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem is often cited as a proof that How We Can . . . reasonable group decision making is impossible – e.g., that a perfect voting Problem: Sometimes . . . procedure is impossible. In Case of Uncertainty, . . . • Our claim: Arrow’s result is only valid if we have binary (partial) information Case Study: Territorial . . . about individual preferences. Decision Making . . . For Territorial . . . • Conclusion: that the pessimistic interpretation of Arrow’s result is, well, too How to Find Individual . . . pessimistic :-) Comments • Implicit assumption behind Arrow’s result: the only information we have How to Find Individual . . . about individual preferences is the binary (“yes”-“no”) preferences between We Must Take . . . the alternatives. Paradox of Love • Fact: this information does not fully describe a persons’ preferences. Why Two and not Three? Emotional vs. . . . • Example: the preference A 1 ≻ A 2 ≻ A 3 : Acknowledgments – it may indicate that a person strongly prefers A 1 to A 2 , and strongly Title Page prefers A 2 to A 3 , and ◭◭ ◮◮ – it may also indicate that this person strongly prefers A 1 to A 2 , and at the same time, A 2 is almost of the same quality as A 3 . ◭ ◮ • How can this distinction be described: to describe this degree of preference, Page 5 of 25 researchers in decision making use the notion of utility . Go Back Full Screen

  6. Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . 5. Why Utility Different Utility Scales Expected Utility • Idea of value: a person’s rational decisions are based on the relative values Nash’s Bargaining . . . to the person of different outcomes. Properties of Nash’s . . . How We Can . . . • Monetary value is often used: in financial applications, the value is usually Problem: Sometimes . . . measured in monetary units such as dollars. In Case of Uncertainty, . . . • Problem with monetary value: the same monetary amount may have different Case Study: Territorial . . . values for different people: Decision Making . . . For Territorial . . . – a single dollar is likely to have more value to a poor person How to Find Individual . . . – than to a rich one. Comments How to Find Individual . . . • Thus, a new scale is needed: in view of this difference, in decision theory, to describe the relative values of different outcomes, researchers use a special We Must Take . . . utility scale instead of the more traditional monetary scales. Paradox of Love Why Two and not Three? Emotional vs. . . . Acknowledgments Title Page ◭◭ ◮◮ ◭ ◮ Page 6 of 25 Go Back Full Screen

  7. Why Utility What Is Utility: a . . . 6. What Is Utility: a Reminder Different Utility Scales Expected Utility • Main idea behind utility: a common approach is based on preferences of a Nash’s Bargaining . . . decision maker among lotteries . Properties of Nash’s . . . How We Can . . . • Specifics: Problem: Sometimes . . . – take a very undesirable outcome A − and a very desirable outcome A + ; In Case of Uncertainty, . . . – consider the lottery A ( p ) in which we get A + with given probability p Case Study: Territorial . . . and A − with probability 1 − p ; Decision Making . . . For Territorial . . . – a utility u ( B ) of an outcome B is defined as the probability p for which How to Find Individual . . . B is of the same quality as A ( p ): B ∼ A ( p ) = A ( u ( B )) . Comments • Assumptions behind this definition: How to Find Individual . . . We Must Take . . . – clearly, the larger p , the more preferable A ( p ): Paradox of Love p < p ′ ⇒ A ( p ) < A ( p ′ ); Why Two and not Three? Emotional vs. . . . – the comparison amongst lotteries is a linear order – i.e., a person can Acknowledgments always select one of the two alternatives; Title Page – comparison is Archimedean – i.e. if for all ε > 0, an outcome B is better than A ( p − ε ) and worse than A ( p + ε ), then it is of the same quality as ◭◭ ◮◮ A ( p ): B ∼ A ( p ). ◭ ◮ Page 7 of 25 Go Back Full Screen

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend