cocon a type theory for defining logics and proofs
play

Cocon: A Type Theory for Defining Logics and Proofs Brigitte - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Cocon: A Type Theory for Defining Logics and Proofs Brigitte Pientka McGill University Montreal, Canada What are good high-level proof languages that make it easier to mechanize metatheory? What are good high-level proof languages that make


  1. Cocon: A Type Theory for Defining Logics and Proofs Brigitte Pientka McGill University Montreal, Canada

  2. What are good high-level proof languages that make it easier to mechanize metatheory?

  3. What are good high-level proof languages that make it easier to mechanize metatheory?

  4. Theory Def. Operational Semantics Type System Model Type Theory Program Transformations Type Inference Algorithm Logic ...

  5. Theory Def. Operational Semantics Type System Model Type Theory Program Transformations Metatheory Type Inference Algorithm Type Safety Logic Decidability of Type Checking ... Soundness of Prog. Transform. Consistency Completeness Program Equivalence Bisimulation

  6. Mechanized Theory Def. Metatheory Operational Semantics Type System Model Type Theory Program Transformations Metatheory Type Inference Algorithm Type Safety Logic Decidability of Type Checking ... Soundness of Prog. Transform. Consistency Completeness Program Equivalence implemented Bisimulation in a proof assistant

  7. Correct proofs are tricky to write. On paper: • Challenging to keep track of all the details • Easy to skip over details • Difficult to understand interaction between different features • Difficulties increase with size In a proof assistant: • A lot of overhead in building basic infrastructure • May get lost in the technical, low-level details • Time consuming • Experience, experience, experience 2

  8. Mechanizing Normalization for STLC “To those that doubted de Bruijn, I wished to prove them wrong, or discover why they were right. Now, after some years and many hundred hours of labor, I can say with some authority: they were right. De Bruijn indices are foolishly difficult for this kind of proof. [ . . . ] The full proof runs to 3500 lines, although that relies on a further library of 1900 lines of basic facts about lists and sets. [ . . . ] the cost of de Bruijn is partly reflected in the painful 1600 lines that are used to prove facts about “shifting” and “substitution”.” Ezra Cooper (PhD Student) https://github.com/ezrakilty/sn-stlc-de-bruijn-coq 3

  9. Mechanizing Normalization for STLC “To those that doubted de Bruijn, I wished to prove them wrong, or discover why they were right. Now, after some years and many hundred hours of labor, I can say with some authority: they were right. De Bruijn indices are foolishly difficult for this kind of proof. [ . . . ] The full proof runs to 3500 lines, although that relies on a further library of 1900 lines of basic facts A. Rossberg, C. Russo, D. Dreyer. F-ing Modules. JFP, 2014 about lists and sets. [ . . . ] the cost of de Bruijn is partly reflected in the painful 1600 lines that are used to prove facts about “shifting” and “substitution”.” Ezra Cooper (PhD Student) https://github.com/ezrakilty/sn-stlc-de-bruijn-coq 3

  10. Abstraction, Abstraction, Abstraction “The motivation behind the work in very-high-level languages is to ease the programming task by providing the programmer with a language containing primitives or abstractions suitable to his problem area. The programmer is then able to spend his effort in the right place; he concentrates on solving his problem, and the resulting program will be more reliable as a result. Clearly, this is a worthwhile goal.” B. Liskov [1974] 4

  11. Abstraction, Abstraction, Abstraction “The motivation behind the work in very-high-level languages is to ease the programming task by providing the programmer with a language containing primitives or abstractions suitable to his problem area. The programmer is then able to spend his effort in the right place; he concentrates on solving his problem, s e d v i o r p and the resulting program will be more reliable as a result. t a h t s ) c a i d g o g A l g n Clearly, this is a worthwhile goal.” o r B. Liskov [1974] i n q fi o e C d o y l t t n a r a g i l m e l i e s ( d n y Goal: r a o e y l h t t c a e p p m y t o c t n r e o d f n s e n o p e t i d c A a r t s b a t h g i r e h t and proofs. 4

  12. “To know your future you must know your past.” – G. Santayana

  13. Back in the 80s... 5

  14. Back in the 80s... 1987 • R. Harper, F. Honsell, G. Plotkin: A Framework for Defining Logics, LICS’87 1988 • F. Pfenning and C. Elliott : Higher-Order Abstract Syntax, PLDI’88 • LF = Dependently Typed Lambda Calculus ( λ Π ) serves as a Meta-Language for representing formal systems • Higher-order Abstract Syntax (HOAS) : Uniformly model binding structures in Object Language with (intensional) functions in LF 5

  15. Representing Types and Terms in LF – In a Nutshell Types A , B ::= nat | A ⇒ B Terms M ::= x | lam x : A . M | app M N 6

  16. Representing Types and Terms in LF – In a Nutshell Types A , B ::= nat | A ⇒ B Terms M ::= x | lam x : A . M | app M N LF Representation obj: type . tm: type . nat: obj. lam: obj → (tm → tm) → tm. arr: obj → obj → obj. app: tm → tm → tm. On Paper (Object Language) In LF (Meta Language) lam x :nat . x lam nat λ x.x lam x :nat . (lam x :nat ⇒ nat . x ) lam nat λ x.(lam (arr nat nat) λ x.x) lam x :nat . (lam f :nat ⇒ nat . app f x ) lam nat λ x.(lam (arr nat nat) λ f.app f x) Higher-order Abstract Syntax (HOAS) : • Uniformly model bindings with (intensional) functions in LF • Inherit α -renaming and single substitutions 6 Model

  17. Uniformly Model Binding Structures using LF Functions Types A , B ::= nat | A ⇒ B | Terms M ::= x | lam x : A . M | app M N | α | ∀ α. A let x = M in N | tlam α. M | . . . 7

  18. Uniformly Model Binding Structures using LF Functions Types A , B ::= nat | A ⇒ B | Terms M ::= x | lam x : A . M | app M N | α | ∀ α. A let x = M in N | tlam α. M | . . . LF Representation obj: type . tm: type . nat: obj. lam: obj → (tm → tm) → tm. arr: obj → obj → obj. app: tm → tm → tm. all: (obj → obj) → obj. let: tm → (tm → tm) → tm. tlam: (obj → tm) → tm. On Paper (Object Language) In LF (Meta Language) tlam α. (lam x : α. x ) tlam λ a.(lam a λ x.x) ∀ α. ∀ β.α ⇒ β all λ a.all λ b.arr a b 7

  19. Uniformly Model Binding Structures using LF Functions LF = Dependently Typed Lambda Calculus λ Π Types A , B ::= nat | A ⇒ B | Terms M ::= x | lam x : A . M | app M N | α | ∀ α. A let x = M in N | tlam α. M | . . . • LF functions only encode variable scope LF Representation no recursion, no pattern matching, etc. • HOAS trees = Syntax trees with binders obj: type . tm: type . • Benefit: α -renaming and substitution principles nat: obj. lam: obj → (tm → tm) → tm. arr: obj → obj → obj. app: tm → tm → tm. all: (obj → obj) → obj. let: tm → (tm → tm) → tm. • Scales: Model derivation trees - Hypothetical derivations as LF functions tlam: (obj → tm) → tm. - Parametric derivations as LF functions On Paper (Object Language) In LF (Meta Language) tlam α. (lam x : α. x ) tlam λ a.(lam a λ x.x) ∀ α. ∀ β.α ⇒ β all λ a.all λ b.arr a b 7

  20. Sounds cool . . . can I do this in OCaml or Agda?

  21. An Attempt in OCaml OCaml 1 type tm = Lam of (tm -> tm) 2 let apply = function (Lam f) -> f 3 let omega = Lam (function x -> apply x x) What happens, when we try to evaluate apply omega omega ? 8

  22. An Attempt in OCaml OCaml 1 type tm = Lam of (tm -> tm) 2 let apply = function (Lam f) -> f 3 let omega = Lam (function x -> apply x x) What happens, when we try to evaluate apply omega omega ? It will loop. 8

  23. An Attempt in OCaml and Agda OCaml 1 type tm = Lam of (tm -> tm) 2 let apply = function (Lam f) -> f 3 let omega = Lam (function x -> apply x x) What happens, when we try to evaluate apply omega omega ? It will loop. Agda data tm : type = lam : (tm → tm) → tm Violates positivity restriction 8

  24. An Attempt in OCaml and Agda OCaml 1 type tm = Lam of (tm -> tm) Functions in OCaml and Agda are opaque (black box). 2 let apply = function (Lam f) -> f 3 let omega = Lam (function x -> apply x x) • We can observe the result that a function computes • We cannot pattern match to inspect the function body What happens, when we try to evaluate apply omega omega ? It will loop. Agda data tm : type = lam : (tm → tm) → tm Violates positivity restriction 8

  25. OK . . . so, how do we write recursive programs over with HOAS trees? We clearly want pattern matching, since a HOAS tree is a data structure.

  26. An Attempt to Compute the Size of a Term size (lam λ x.lam λ f. app f x) = ⇒ size (lam λ f. app f x) + 1 = ⇒ (app f x) + 1 + 1 size = ⇒ size f + size x + 1 + 1 + 1 = ⇒ 0 + 0 + 1 + 1 + 1 “the whole HOAS approach by its very nature disallows a feature that we regard of key practical importance: the ability to manipulate names of bound variables explicitly in computation and proof. ” [Pitts, Gabbay’97] 9

  27. Back in 2008 . . .

  28. LF and Holes in HOAS trees – Revisited In LF (Meta Lang.) lam λ x. lam λ f.app f x lam λ x. lam λ f. app f x LF Typing Judgment: : Ψ ⊢ ⊢ M A LF Type LF Context LF Term 10

  29. LF and Holes in HOAS trees – Revisited In LF (Meta Lang.) lam λ x. lam λ f.app f x lam λ x. lam λ f. app f x LF Typing Judgment: : tm x : tm ⊢ lam λ f . app f x ⊢ LF Type LF Context LF Term 10

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend