coalitional agency and evidence based ability
play

Coalitional agency and evidence-based ability Nicolas Troquard - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Coalitional agency and evidence-based ability Nicolas Troquard ISTC-CNR (LOA group, Trento) International Workshop on The Cognitive Foundations of Group Attitudes and Social Interaction Toulouse, May 31-June 1, 2012 1 / 31 Outline


  1. Coalitional agency and evidence-based ability Nicolas Troquard ISTC-CNR (LOA group, Trento) International Workshop on The Cognitive Foundations of Group Attitudes and Social Interaction Toulouse, May 31-June 1, 2012 1 / 31

  2. Outline Introduction 1 Elgesem’s account of individual agency and ability 2 Coalitional agency and ability 3 Meta-mathematics and reasoning about coalitional agency 4 Explicit objectives and Evidences 5 2 / 31

  3. Formal theories of Agency Talking explicitly about action terms: using Dynamic Logics in computer science using first-order theories in the study of action sentences Actions are identified with what they bring about: St. Anselm (11th century) “seeing-to-it-that” (STIT): Chellas, Belnap and Perlo ff , ... “bringing-it-about”: Kanger, Pörn, Lindahl, Elgesem, ... 3 / 31

  4. “bringing-it-about” in multi-agent systems (I) The bringing-it-about modality E x is popular in the MAS community to model the actions and responsibilities of acting entities: agency of an individual agent (Kanger, ...): E i ϕ ⇒ “agent i is responsible ( ex post acto ) for ϕ ” “agent i is agentive for ϕ ” “agent i brings it about that ϕ ” agency of an agent in a role (Santos and Jones, Sartor, Carmo and Pacheco, ...): E i : r ϕ ⇒ “agent i qua r is responsible for ϕ ” obligations of an agent in a role: OE i : r ϕ ⇒ “agent i playing the role r ought to achieve ϕ ” 4 / 31

  5. “bringing-it-about” in multi-agent systems (II) Example Beliefs and expectations about other agents’ current behaviour: Bel Mary ¬ E John “dinner is ready” Obligation to do / Imperatives: E Mary O John E John “dinner is ready” Constraining a behaviour: E Mary E John “dinner is ready” Deliberate inaction: E Mary ¬ E Mary “Mary eats chocolate” 5 / 31

  6. Outline Introduction 1 Elgesem’s account of individual agency and ability 2 Coalitional agency and ability 3 Meta-mathematics and reasoning about coalitional agency 4 Explicit objectives and Evidences 5 6 / 31

  7. Goal-oriented (possibly non-intentional) individual agency Sommerho ff [Sommerho ff 1969]: agency is the actual bringing about of a goal towards which an activity is oriented. An agent acts to achieve a goal. But an agent is not necessarily aware of his goals, at least not in the sense that he is consciously committed to achieve them. Frankfurt [Frankfurt 1988]: the pertinent aspect of agency is the manifestation of the agent’s guidance (or control) towards a goal; not necessarily an intentional action. 7 / 31

  8. Core principles of agency Propositional logic ⊢ ¬ E i ⊤ ⊢ E i ϕ ∧ E i ψ → E i ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) ⊢ E i ϕ → ϕ if ⊢ ϕ ↔ ψ then ⊢ E i ϕ ↔ E i ψ Example ⊢ ¬ E i ⊥ E i ϕ ∧ ¬ E i E i ϕ is satisfiable 8 / 31

  9. Agency as the manifestation of control Elgesem observes that the manifestation of control is the exercise of a power to bring about something. Therefore, the notion of potential control of an agent for a goal should be integrated in a theory of agency. Example ([Elgesem 1998]) Bob Beamon, jumped 8.90 m (long jump) in the 1968 Olympics. If Beamon jumped that far it is that he was exercising control towards a goal. Even though this goal was probably not intentionally to jump 8.90 m, we would not take back from Beamon that on that day: he brought about the fact that he jumped that far, and he had the ability to do it. 9 / 31

  10. Ability Elgesem then suggests: there is a more basic notion of ability than an intention-based one, and this non-intentional notion of ability is a necessary condition for agency. By bringing about something, an agent is deemed able. Similar to Mele’s simple ability in [Mele 2003, p. 448]: ”an agent’s A-ing at a time is su ffi cient for his having the simple ability to A at that time.”, and “being able to A intentionally entails having a simple ability to A and the converse is false” 10 / 31

  11. Principles of ability ⊢ ¬ C i ⊥ ⊢ ¬ C i ⊤ ⊢ E i ϕ → C i ϕ if ⊢ ϕ ↔ ψ then ⊢ C i ϕ ↔ C i ψ Example ⊢ E i ϕ ∧ E i ψ → E i ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) → C i ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) 11 / 31

  12. Outline Introduction 1 Elgesem’s account of individual agency and ability 2 Coalitional agency and ability 3 Meta-mathematics and reasoning about coalitional agency 4 Explicit objectives and Evidences 5 12 / 31

  13. Joint actions and collective goals A group is a set of agents. Joint actions are a species of actions involving a group that acts towards a shared goal. S. Miller [Miller 2001] says of a joint action that it involves two co-present agents each of whom performs simultaneously with the other agent one basic individual action, and in relation to a collective goal. (Joint actions are not necessarily social actions.) “Joint actions consist of the individual actions of a number of agents directed to the realisation of a collective end. A collective end —notwithstanding its name— is a species of individual end; it is an end possessed by each of the individuals involved in the joint action.” 13 / 31

  14. A weaker requirement than collective intentionality Despite resorting to the concept of a collective goal, Miller argues that we-intentions are not a necessary element of joint actions. Example ([Bottazzi, Ferrario]) Two scholars start chatting at a conference break and somewhat start to take a walk in the park. They respect their turn in the conversation, they synchronize their pace, and take a direction in the park without having previously agreed on it. 14 / 31

  15. Goal-oriented non-intentional coalitional agency and ability Similar to the individual case: there is a more basic notion of coalitional goal-directed agency than an intentional one (coalitional) agency is the manifestation of an existing control that means that there is a basic notion of coalitional ability that is a necessary condition for coalitional agency 15 / 31

  16. Inferring coalitional responsibilities and abilities In social choice theory, superadditivity is: E ff G 1 ϕ ∧ E ff G 2 ψ → E ff G 1 ∪ G 2 ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) , when G 1 ∩ G 2 = ∅ We already have the aggregation principle: E G ϕ ∧ E G ψ → E G ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) We should not have (even when G 1 ∩ G 2 = ∅ ): E G 1 ϕ ∧ E G 2 ψ → E G 1 ∪ G 2 ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) G 1 and G 2 would need to share a goal. (I’ll come back to it.) C G 1 ϕ ∧ C G 2 ψ → C G 1 ∪ G 2 ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) Ability would need some kind of context. We have something mixed (for any G 1 and G 2 ): E G 1 ϕ ∧ E G 2 ψ → C G 1 ∪ G 2 ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) 16 / 31

  17. Principles of coalitional agency and ability For all groups G , G 1 , and G 2 and formulas ϕ and ψ : Ax0 ⊢ ϕ , when ϕ is a tautology of propositional logic Ax1 ⊢ E G ϕ ∧ E G ψ → E G ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) Ax2 ⊢ E G ϕ → ϕ Ax3 ⊢ E G ϕ → C G ϕ Ax4 ⊢ ¬ C G ⊥ Ax5 ⊢ ¬ C G ⊤ Ax6 ⊢ ¬ C ∅ ϕ Ax7 ⊢ E G 1 ϕ ∧ E G 2 ψ → C G 1 ∪ G 2 ( ϕ ∧ ψ ) MP if ⊢ ϕ and ⊢ ϕ → ψ then ⊢ ψ ERE if ⊢ ϕ ↔ ψ then ⊢ E G ϕ ↔ E G ψ ERC if ⊢ ϕ ↔ ψ then ⊢ C G ϕ ↔ C G ψ 17 / 31

  18. Additional candidate axioms Ax8 ⊢ E G 1 ϕ → ¬ E G 2 ϕ , when G 2 ⊂ G 1 Ax9 ⊢ E G 1 E G 2 ϕ → E G 1 ϕ Ax10 ⊢ E G 1 E G 2 ϕ → E G 1 ∪ G 2 ϕ 18 / 31

  19. Outline Introduction 1 Elgesem’s account of individual agency and ability 2 Coalitional agency and ability 3 Meta-mathematics and reasoning about coalitional agency 4 Explicit objectives and Evidences 5 19 / 31

  20. Semantics and completeness There is a class C of neighborhood models with respect to which the Hilbert system presented on Slide 17 is sound an complete. We say that a formula ϕ is COAL-sat if there is a model in C in which ϕ is true. 20 / 31

  21. An algorithm to decide whether ϕ is COAL-sat 1 non-deterministically guess a semi-valuation π for ϕ ; if E ∅ ψ ∈ sub ¬ ( ψ ) , then check that π ( E ∅ ψ ) = 0 ; 2 if C ∅ ψ ∈ sub ¬ ( ψ ) , then check that π ( C ∅ ψ ) = 0 ; 3 if E G ψ ∈ sub ¬ ( ϕ ) and π ( E G ψ ) = 1 , then check that π ( ψ ) = 1 ; 4 if E G ψ ∈ sub ¬ ( ϕ ) and π ( E G ψ ) = 1 , recursively check that ¬ ψ is COAL-sat; 5 if C G ψ ∈ sub ¬ ( ϕ ) and π ( C G ψ ) = 1 , recursively check that both: 6 ¬ ψ is COAL-sat; ψ is COAL-sat; if E G ψ 1 , C G ψ 2 ∈ sub ¬ ( ϕ ) , with π ( E G ψ 1 ) = 1 and π ( C G ψ 2 ) = 0 then recursively check that 7 ψ 1 ∧ ¬ ψ 2 is COAL-sat; 8 if either: E G ψ 1 , . . . , E G ψ k , E G ψ ∈ sub ¬ ( ϕ ) , with π ( E G ψ j ) = 1 for all j , and π ( E G ψ ) = 0 ; E G 1 ψ 1 , . . . , E Gk ψ k , C G ψ ∈ sub ¬ ( ϕ ) , with π ( E Gj ψ j ) = 1 for all j , π ( C G ψ ) = 0 , and G = G 1 ∪ . . . G k ; then non-deterministically and recursively check that either: � j ( ψ j ) ∧ ¬ ψ is COAL-sat ( ¬ ψ 1 ) ∧ ψ is COAL-sat; . . . ( ¬ ψ k ) ∧ ψ is COAL-sat. 21 / 31

  22. Computational complexity of reasoning about agency The satisfiability of: the core logic of agency, Elgesem’s logic of agency and ability, and the logic of coalitional agency and ability can all be decided in space polynomial (in PSPACE). 22 / 31

  23. Outline Introduction 1 Elgesem’s account of individual agency and ability 2 Coalitional agency and ability 3 Meta-mathematics and reasoning about coalitional agency 4 Explicit objectives and Evidences 5 23 / 31

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend