a universality argument for graph homomorphisms
play

A universality argument for graph homomorphisms cka 2 and Yangjing - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

A universality argument for graph homomorphisms cka 2 and Yangjing Long 3 Fiala 1 , Jan Hubi Ji r 1 Charles University, Czech Republic 2 University of Calgary, Canada 3 Max Planck Institute for Mathematics in the Sciences, Leipzig,


  1. A universality argument for graph homomorphisms cka 2 and Yangjing Long 3 ı Fiala 1 , Jan Hubiˇ Jiˇ r´ 1 Charles University, Czech Republic 2 University of Calgary, Canada 3 Max Planck Institute for Mathematics in the Sciences, Leipzig, Germany

  2. Terminology Partial order . . . a reflexive, antisymmetric and transitive relation ≤ over a countable set P Past-finite . . . every down set ↓ x = { y : y ≤ x } is finite. Future-finite . . . every up set ↑ x = { y : y ≥ x } is finite. Examples of past-finite orders: ◮ N ordered by divisibility ◮ Finite subsets P fin ( A ) of a countable set A ordered by inclusion Two future-finite orders: ◮ ( ConnGraph , ≤ B ) and ( ConnGraph , ≤ S ) Observe: ( P , ≤ ) is past-finite ⇐ ⇒ ( P , ≥ ) is future-finite. Observe: ↓ x ⊆ ↓ y ⇐ ⇒ x ≤ y . Corollary: A past-finite ( P , ≤ ) is a suborder of ( P fin ( P ) , ⊆ ) (via the embedding x → ↓ x ).

  3. Universality Definition: A partial order is    finite  finite-universal         past-finite-universal past-finite     if it contains any future-finite-universal future-finite         universal countable     order as a suborder. Proposition: For any countably infinite A : ◮ ( P fin ( A ) , ⊆ ) is past-finite-universal. ◮ ( P fin ( A ) , ⊇ ) is future-finite-universal. . . . w.l.o.g. consider only ( P , ≤ ) where P ⊆ A , then use x → ↓ x . Example: ( P fin ( P ) , ⊇ ) is future-finite-universal, where P are all odd primes.

  4. Definition: The subset order ( P fin ( Q ) , ≤ dom ) of ( Q , ≤ Q ) is given Q by X ≤ dom Y iff ∀ x ∈ X ∃ y ∈ Y : x ≤ Q y . Q Theorem ”[Hedrl´ ın 1969]”: If ( F , ≤ F ) is future-fin.-universal, then ( P fin ( F ) , ≤ dom ) is universal. F Proof: Given any countable ( P , ≤ P ), w.l.o.g. P ⊆ N . Then: � x ≤ f y iff x ≤ P y and x ≤ y 1. decompose ≤ P into x ≤ b y iff x ≤ P y and x ≥ y . . . . ( P , ≤ f ) is past-finite and ( P , ≤ b ) is future-finite. 2. find an embedding e : ( P , ≤ b ) → ( F , ≤ F ). 3. argue that g ( x ) = { e ( y ) : y ≤ f x } is an embedding of ( P , ≤ P ) in ( P fin ( F ) , ≤ dom ). F

  5. Example with ( P fin ( P ) , ⊇ ) as ( F , ≤ F ) ( P , ≤ P ) The given order ( P , ≤ P ),

  6. Example with ( P fin ( P ) , ⊇ ) as ( F , ≤ F ) ( P , ≤ P ) 5 3 11 7 label P by P ⊂ N

  7. Example with ( P fin ( P ) , ⊇ ) as ( F , ≤ F ) ( P , ≤ b ) 5 3 11 ( P , ≤ P ) 5 7 3 11 ( P , ≤ f ) 7 5 3 11 7 � x ≤ f y iff x ≤ P y and x ≤ y decompose ≤ P into x ≤ b y iff x ≤ P y and x ≥ y .

  8. Example with ( P fin ( P ) , ⊇ ) as ( F , ≤ F ) ( P , ≤ b ) embedding in ( P fin ( P ), ⊇ ) 5 { 5 } e 3 11 { 3 } { 5, 11 } ( P , ≤ P ) 5 7 { 3, 5, 7 } 3 11 ( P , ≤ f ) 7 5 3 11 7 find an embedding e : ( P , ≤ b ) → ( F , ≤ F )

  9. Example with ( P fin ( P ) , ⊇ ) as ( F , ≤ F ) ( P , ≤ b ) embedding in ( P fin ( P ), ⊇ ) 5 { 5 } e 3 11 { 3 } { 5, 11 } ( P , ≤ P ) 5 7 { 3, 5, 7 } g 3 11 embedding in ( P fin ( P fin ( P )), ⊇ dom ( P , ≤ f ) P fin ( P ) ) 7 5 {{ 3 } , { 5 }} 3 11 {{ 3 }} {{ 3, 5, 7 } , { 5, 11 }} 7 {{ 3, 5, 7 }} define embedding by g ( x ) = { e ( y ) : y ≤ f x }

  10. Example with ( P fin ( P ) , ⊇ ) as ( F , ≤ F ) ( P , ≤ b ) embedding in ( P fin ( P ), ⊇ ) 5 { 5 } e 3 11 { 3 } { 5, 11 } ( P , ≤ P ) 5 7 { 3, 5, 7 } g 3 11 embedding in ( P fin ( P fin ( P )), ⊇ dom ( P , ≤ f ) P fin ( P ) ) 7 5 {{ 3 } , { 5 }} 3 11 {{ 3 }} {{ 3, 5, 7 } , { 5, 11 }} 7 {{ 3, 5, 7 }} Recall: X ⊇ dom P fin ( P ) Y iff ∀ X ∈ X ∃ Y ∈ Y s.t. X ⊇ Y Hence {{ 3 }} is incomparable with {{ 3 , 5 , 7 } , { 5 , 11 }} .

  11. P fin ( P ) ) ⊂ ( P fin ( N ) , ← − Indeed ( P fin ( P fin ( P )) , ⊇ dom | dom ) N Let a = � X , b = � Y , A = { � X , X ∈ X} , B = { � Y , Y ∈ Y} then X ⊇ dom P fin ( P ) Y ⇐ ⇒ ∀ X ∈ X ∃ Y ∈ Y : X ⊇ Y ⇐ ⇒ A ← − | dom ∀ a ∈ A ∃ b ∈ B : a is divided by b ⇐ ⇒ B N embedding in ( P fin ( N ), ← − dom embedding in ( P fin ( P fin ( P )), ⊇ dom ( P , ≤ P ) P fin ( P ) ) | ) N {{ 3 } , { 5 }} { 3, 5 } {{ 3 }} {{ 3, 5, 7 } , { 5, 11 }} { 3 } { 105, 55 } {{ 3, 5, 7 }} { 105 }

  12. Consequences on homomorphism orders Theorem: Collections of directed cycles ordered by homomorphisms are universal. embedding in ( P fin ( N ), ← − dom ( P , ≤ P ) | ) embedding in ( DiCycles , ≤ Hom ) N { 3, 5 } � C 105 ∪ � { 3 } { 105, 55 } C 55 � { 105 } C 105

  13. Consequences on homomorphism orders Theorem: Collections of directed cycles ordered by homomorphisms are universal. Corrollary: Homomorphism order is universal on graphs that are ◮ maximum degree 3, ◮ planar, ◮ have treewidth at most 4, etc. replace all by in each � C k

  14. Many other directions Choose mappings Goal: Classify M monomorphisms ◮ Universality F full homomorphisms — if possible on E embeddings a narrow subclass VS vertex surjective homomorphisms ◮ Cores ES edge surjective homomorphisms ◮ Density S surjective homomorphisms ◮ Gaps LB locally bijective homomorphisms . . . LI locally injective homomorphisms . . . LS locally surjective homomorphisms . . . . . . . . . . . . Directed graphs could be also considered.

  15. Coverings and their variants Definition: A homomorphism f : G → H is a graph covering if f acts bijectively between N ( u ) and N ( f ( u )) for all u ∈ V G . B If f : G → H acts always injectively between N ( u ) and N ( f ( u )) then is a partial covering . If f acts locally surjectively then it is a role assignment . I S

  16. Degree refinement / equitable partition Definition: A partition of V G into B 1 , . . . , B k is called a degree partition if u , v ∈ B i then | N ( u ) ∩ B j | = | N ( v ) ∩ B j | for all j . (Also known as an equitable partition .) The unique partition with minimum number of classes can be computed iteratively and is called degree refinement . (3) (2) (0,1,2) (1,0,1) (0,1,2,0) (1,0,0,1) drm( G ) =   0 1 2 0 1 0 0 1     1 0 0 0   0 1 0 0 (1) (1) (1) (1,0,0) (1,0,0) (0,1,0) (1,0,0,0) (0,1,0,0) There is a canonical ordering of the classes B 1 , . . . , B k , hence the constants m i , j = | N ( u ) ∩ B j | for u ∈ B i can be arranged into a unique degree refinement matrix drm( G ). B Folklore: On connected graphs: if G − → H then drm( G ) = drm( H ).

  17. Homomorphisms as orders View G → H as G ≤ H , it is a transitive and reflexive relation. Similarly define ≤ B , ≤ I and ≤ S Theorem [Fiala, Maxov´ a, 2006]: ( ConnGraph , ≤ B ) = ( ConnGraph , ≤ I ) ∩ ( ConnGraph , ≤ S ) Observe: ( ConnGraph , ≤ B ) is a disjoint union of orders. Graphs in the same part have the same degree refinement matrix. What about order properties like universatity, density, cores, gaps, dualities, . . . of these orders? Observe: ( ConnGraph , ≤ B ) and ( ConnGraph , ≤ S ) are not dense since G ≤ B H or G ≤ S H imply | V G | ≥ | V H | .

  18. Consequences on covering orders Theorem: Collections of cycles ordered by coverings are universal. embedding in ( P fin ( N ), ← − dom ( P , ≤ P ) | ) embedding in ( Cycles , ≤ B ) N { 3, 5 } { 3 } { 105, 55 } C 105 ∪ C 55 { 105 } C 105 Corollary: ( Cycles , ≤ I ) and ( Cycles , ≤ S ) are universal orders. Observe: drm could be also prescribed, except for forests

  19. Consequences on covering orders Theorem: Collections of cycles ordered by coverings are universal. embedding in ( P fin ( N ), ← − dom ( P , ≤ P ) | ) embedding in ( Cycles , ≤ B ) N { 3, 5 } { 3 } { 105, 55 } C 105 ∪ C 55 { 105 } C 105 Corollary: ( Cycles , ≤ I ) and ( Cycles , ≤ S ) are universal orders. Observe: drm could be also prescribed, except for forests Theorem: ( ConnGraph , ≤ I ) is a universal order.

  20. Density Theorem: On connected graphs of minimum degree 2, distinct from cycles: If G < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( H ), then there exists F , such that G < I F < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( F ) � = drm ( H ). H G f ( u ) u

  21. Density Theorem: On connected graphs of minimum degree 2, distinct from cycles: If G < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( H ), then there exists F , such that G < I F < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( F ) � = drm ( H ). H G f ( u ) u F u

  22. Density Theorem: On connected graphs of minimum degree 2, distinct from cycles: If G < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( H ), then there exists F , such that G < I F < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( F ) � = drm ( H ). H G f ( u ) u F u

  23. Density Theorem: On connected graphs of minimum degree 2, distinct from cycles: If G < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( H ), then there exists F , such that G < I F < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( F ) � = drm ( H ). H G f ( u ) u F u

  24. Density Theorem: On connected graphs of minimum degree 2, distinct from cycles: If G < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( H ), then there exists F , such that G < I F < I H and drm ( G ) � = drm ( F ) � = drm ( H ). H G f ( u ) u F u

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend