a survey of the model theory of tracial von neumann
play

A survey of the model theory of tracial von Neumann algebras Isaac - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

A survey of the model theory of tracial von Neumann algebras Isaac Goldbring University of Illinois at Chicago Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar November 11, 2013 Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 1 / 34


  1. A survey of the model theory of tracial von Neumann algebras Isaac Goldbring University of Illinois at Chicago Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar November 11, 2013 Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 1 / 34

  2. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Introduction to von Neumann algebras 1 Isomorphic ultrapowers 2 Connes Embedding Problem 3 4 Model companions Computability theory 5 6 Future directions Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 2 / 34

  3. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Von Neumann algebras Throughout, H is a complex Hilbert space and B ( H ) is the ∗ -algebra of bounded operators on H . For X ⊆ B ( H ) , we set X ′ := { T ∈ B ( H ) : TS = ST for all S ∈ X } . Observe that: X ′ is a unital subalgebra of B ( H ) that is closed under ∗ if X is. X ⊆ X ′′ . Definition A von Neumann algebra is a ∗ -subalgebra M of B ( H ) such that M = M ′′ . Equivalently, M is a ∗ -subalgebra of B ( H ) that is closed in either the weak operator topology or the strong operator topology . Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 3 / 34

  4. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Examples of vNas Example B ( H ) is a von Neumann algebra. Example Suppose that ( X , µ ) is a finite measure space. Then L ∞ ( X , µ ) acts on the Hilbert space L 2 ( X , µ ) by left multiplication, yielding an embedding L ∞ ( X , µ ) ֒ → B ( L 2 ( X , µ )) , the image of which is a von Neumann algebra. (Actually, all abelian von Neumann algebras are isomorphic to some L ∞ ( X , µ ) , whence von Neumann algebra theory is sometimes dubbed “noncommutative measure theory.”) Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 4 / 34

  5. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Group von Neumann algebras Example Suppose that G is a locally compact group and α : G → B ( H ) is a unitary group representation. Then the group von Neumann algebra of α is α ( G ) ′′ . (Understanding α ( G ) ′′ is tantamount to understanding the invariant subspaces of α .) In the important special case that α : G → B ( L 2 ( G )) (where G is equipped with its haar measure) is given by left translations α ( g )( f )( x ) := f ( g − 1 x ) , we call α ( G ) ′′ the group von Neumann algebra of G and denote it by L ( G ) . Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 5 / 34

  6. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Group von Neumann algebras Example Suppose that G is a locally compact group and α : G → B ( H ) is a unitary group representation. Then the group von Neumann algebra of α is α ( G ) ′′ . (Understanding α ( G ) ′′ is tantamount to understanding the invariant subspaces of α .) In the important special case that α : G → B ( L 2 ( G )) (where G is equipped with its haar measure) is given by left translations α ( g )( f )( x ) := f ( g − 1 x ) , we call α ( G ) ′′ the group von Neumann algebra of G and denote it by L ( G ) . Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 5 / 34

  7. Introduction to von Neumann algebras R Example Let M 2 denote the set of 2 × 2 matrices with entries from C . We consider the canonical embeddings M 2 ֒ → M 2 ⊗ M 2 ֒ → M 2 ⊗ M 2 ⊗ M 2 ֒ → · · · and set M := � ∞ � n M 2 . n = 1 The normalized traces on � n M 2 form a cohesive family of traces, yielding a trace tr : M → C . We can define an inner product on M by � A , B � := tr ( B ∗ A ) . Set H to be the completion of M with respect to this inner product. M acts on H by left multiplication, whence we can view M as a ∗ -subalgebra of B ( H ) . We set R to be the von Neumann algebra generated by M . R is called the hyperfinite II 1 factor . Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 6 / 34

  8. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Tracial von Neumann algebras Suppose that A is a von Neumann algebra. A tracial state (or just trace ) on A is a linear functional τ : A → C satisfying: τ ( 1 ) = 1; τ ( x ∗ x ) ≥ 0 for all x ∈ A ; τ ( xy ) = τ ( yx ) for all x , y ∈ A . A tracial von Neumann algebra is a pair ( A , τ ) , where A is a von Neumann algebra and τ is a trace on A . In the case that τ is also faithful , meaning that τ ( x ∗ x ) = 0 ⇒ x = 0, the function � x , y � τ := τ ( y ∗ x ) is an inner product on A , yielding the so-called 2-norm � · � 2 on A . The associated metric is complete on any bounded subset of A . ( A , τ ) is called separable if the metric associated to the 2-norm is separable. Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 7 / 34

  9. Introduction to von Neumann algebras II 1 Factors A von Neumann algebra A is said to be a factor if A ∩ A ′ = C · 1. Fact � ⊕ If A is a von Neumann algebra, then A ∼ X A x (a direct integral ) = where each A x is a factor. A factor is said to be of type II 1 if it is infinite-dimensional and admits a trace. Fact A II 1 factor admits a unique weakly continuous trace, which is automatically faithful. Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 8 / 34

  10. Introduction to von Neumann algebras II 1 Factors A von Neumann algebra A is said to be a factor if A ∩ A ′ = C · 1. Fact � ⊕ If A is a von Neumann algebra, then A ∼ X A x (a direct integral ) = where each A x is a factor. A factor is said to be of type II 1 if it is infinite-dimensional and admits a trace. Fact A II 1 factor admits a unique weakly continuous trace, which is automatically faithful. Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 8 / 34

  11. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Examples-revisited B ( H ) is a factor. If dim ( H ) < ∞ , then B ( H ) admits a trace, but is not a II 1 factor. If dim ( H ) = ∞ , then B ( H ) admits no trace. Thus, B ( H ) is never a II 1 factor. L ∞ ( X , µ ) admits a trace f �→ � X f d µ but is not a factor. If G is a countable group that is ICC , namely all conjugacy classes (other than { 1 } ) are infinite, then L ( G ) is a II 1 factor; the trace is given by T �→ � T δ e , δ e � . In particular, if n ≥ 2, then L ( F n ) is a II 1 factor. R is a II 1 factor; the trace tr : � � n M 2 → C extends uniquely to n the completion. Moreover, R embeds into any II 1 factor. Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 9 / 34

  12. Introduction to von Neumann algebras Continuous model theory There is a natural language of continuous logic in which to discuss tracial von Neumann algebras. Theorem (Farah-Hart-Sherman) The class of tracial von Neumann algebras is universally axiomatizable. The class of II 1 factors is ∀∃ -axiomatizable. Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 10 / 34

  13. Isomorphic ultrapowers Introduction to von Neumann algebras 1 Isomorphic ultrapowers 2 Connes Embedding Problem 3 4 Model companions Computability theory 5 6 Future directions Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 11 / 34

  14. Isomorphic ultrapowers Ultrapowers of von Neumann algebras Suppose that ( A , τ ) is a tracial von Neumann algebra and U is a nonprincipal ultrafilter on N . We set ℓ ∞ ( A ) := { ( a n ) ∈ A N : � a n � is bounded } . Unfortunately, if we quotient this out by the ideal { ( a n ) ∈ A N : lim U � a n � = 0 } , the resulting quotient is usually never a von Neumann algebra. Rather, we have to quotient out by the smaller ideal { ( a n ) ∈ A N : lim U � a n � 2 = 0 } , yielding the tracial ultrapower A U of A . (This is the continuous logic ultrapower, so the result is once again a von Neumann algebra.) Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 12 / 34

  15. Isomorphic ultrapowers Property (Γ) For a while, Murray and von Neumann could not figure out whether R and L ( F 2 ) were isomorphic or not. They finally figured out a property that distinguished them. Say that a II 1 factor M has property (Γ) if, for any finite F ⊆ M and any ǫ > 0, there is a trace 0 unitary u such that � ux − xu � 2 < ǫ for all x ∈ F . R has (Γ) (easy) while L ( F 2 ) does not (M-vN), so R �∼ = L ( F 2 ) . Equivalently, M has property (Γ) if and only if M ′ ∩ M U � = C ( M has nontrivial relative commutant ). Note that (Γ) is axiomatizable by the sentences � � yy ∗ − 1 � 2 + | tr ( y ) | + � � σ n := sup inf y � [ x i , y ] � 2 . � x Therefore, R and L ( F 2 ) are not elementarily equivalent! Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 13 / 34

  16. Isomorphic ultrapowers Property (Γ) For a while, Murray and von Neumann could not figure out whether R and L ( F 2 ) were isomorphic or not. They finally figured out a property that distinguished them. Say that a II 1 factor M has property (Γ) if, for any finite F ⊆ M and any ǫ > 0, there is a trace 0 unitary u such that � ux − xu � 2 < ǫ for all x ∈ F . R has (Γ) (easy) while L ( F 2 ) does not (M-vN), so R �∼ = L ( F 2 ) . Equivalently, M has property (Γ) if and only if M ′ ∩ M U � = C ( M has nontrivial relative commutant ). Note that (Γ) is axiomatizable by the sentences � � yy ∗ − 1 � 2 + | tr ( y ) | + � � σ n := sup inf y � [ x i , y ] � 2 . � x Therefore, R and L ( F 2 ) are not elementarily equivalent! Isaac Goldbring (UIC) Model theory of tracial vNas Harvard-MIT Logic Seminar 13 / 34

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend