the strongly proper forcing axiom
play

The -Strongly Proper Forcing Axiom David Asper o University of - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

The -Strongly Proper Forcing Axiom David Asper o University of East Anglia Fifth Workshop on Generalised Baire Spaces Bristol, February 2020 Properness and strong properness A partial order P is proper iff for every large enough (Shelah)


  1. The κ -Strongly Proper Forcing Axiom David Asper´ o University of East Anglia Fifth Workshop on Generalised Baire Spaces Bristol, February 2020

  2. Properness and strong properness A partial order P is proper iff for every large enough (Shelah) cardinal θ (i.e., such that P ∈ H ( θ ) ), every countable N � H ( θ ) such that P ∈ N and every p ∈ P ∩ N there is some q ≤ P p which is ( N , P ) -generic, i.e., for every q ′ ≤ P q and every dense set D ⊆ P such that D ∈ N , q ′ is compatible with some condition in D ∩ N . (Mitchell) A partial order P is strongly proper iff for every large enough cardinal θ , every countable N � H ( θ ) such that P ∈ N and every p ∈ P ∩ N there is some q ≤ P p which is strongly ( N , P ) -generic , i.e., for every q ′ ≤ P q there is some π N ( q ′ ) ∈ P ∩ N weaker than q ′ and such that every r ∈ P ∩ N such that r ≤ P π N ( q ′ ) is compatible with q ′ .

  3. Examples of strongly proper partial orders: • Cohen forcing • Baumgartner’s forcing for adding a club of ω 1 with finite conditions. • Given a cardinal λ ≥ ω 2 , the forcing of finite ∈ -chains of countable N � H ( λ ) . Caution : ccc does not imply strongly proper. In fact, most ccc forcings are not strongly proper.

  4. Some basic facts Fact If P is strongly proper, N � H ( θ ) is countable, P ∈ N, q is strongly ( N , P ) -generic, G ⊆ P is generic over V, and q ∈ G, then G ∩ N is P ∩ N-generic over V.

  5. Fact Every ω -sequence of ordinals added by a strongly proper forcing notion is in a generic extension of V by Cohen forcing. Proof. Let P be strongly proper, ˙ r a P -name for an ω -sequence of ordinals, p ∈ P , and N � H ( θ ) countable and such that P , p , ˙ r ∈ N . Let q ≤ P p be strongly ( N , P ) -generic. Then, if G is P -generic over V and q ∈ G , H = G ∩ N is P ∩ N -generic over V . But P ∩ N is countable and non-atomic, and therefore forcing-equivalent to Cohen forcing. And of course ˙ r G = ˙ r H .

  6. Lemma (Neeman) Suppose P is strongly proper, ˙ f is a P -name for a function with dom(˙ f ) = α ∈ Ord. Let N � H ( θ ) countable and such that P , ˙ f ∈ N. Let q be strongly ( N , P ) -generic, let G be P -generic over V such that q ∈ G, and suppose ˙ f G ↾ M ∈ V. Then ˙ f G ∈ V. Corollary (Neeman) Suppose P is strongly proper. Then P does not add new branches through trees T such that cf( ht ( T )) ≥ ω 1 .

  7. Lemma (Neeman) Suppose P , Q are forcing notions, N � H ( θ ) is countable and such that P , Q ∈ N, p is strongly ( N , P ) -generic, and q is ( N , Q ) -generic. Then ( p , q ) is ( N , P × Q ) -generic.

  8. Extending to κ > ω This part is joint work with Sean Cox, Asaf Karagila, and Christoph Weiss.

  9. The notion of strong properness can be naturally extended to higher cardinals: Suppose κ is an infinite regular cardinal such that κ <κ = κ . A partial order P is κ -strongly proper iff for every N � H ( θ ) such that P ∈ N and such that • | N | = κ , and • <κ N ⊆ N , every P -condition in N can be extended to a strongly ( N , P ) -generic condition.

  10. We will need the following closure property: Given an infinite regular cardinal κ , a partial order P is <κ -directed closed with greatest lower bounds in case every directed subset X of P (i.e., every finite subset of X has a lower bound in P ) such that | X | < κ has a greatest lower bound in P . We will also say that P is κ -lattice .

  11. All fact about strongly proper (i.e., ω -strongly proper) forcing we have seen extend naturally to κ -strongly proper forcing notion which are κ -lattice (always assuming κ <κ = κ ). For example, every κ -sequence of ordinals added by a forcing in this class belongs to a generic extension by adding a Cohen subset of κ .

  12. Lemma (Reflection Lemma) Let κ be an infinite regular cardinal such that κ <κ = κ . Suppose P is a κ -lattice and κ -strongly proper forcing. If θ is large enough and ( Q i ) i <κ + is a ⊆ -continuous ∈ -chain of elementary submodels of H ( θ ) such that P ∈ Q i , | Q i | = κ , and <κ Q i ⊆ Q i for all i ∈ S κ + κ , then P ∩ Q is κ -lattice and κ -strongly proper, for Q = � i <κ + Q i . Proof. Given large enough cardinal χ and N � H ( χ ) such that P , ( Q i ) i <κ + ∈ N , | N | = κ and <κ N ⊆ N , N ∩ Q = Q δ ∈ Q for δ = N ∩ κ + . But any strongly ( Q δ , P ) -generic q ∈ Q is ( N , P ∩ Q ) -generic. Compare the above reflection property with the reflection of κ -c.c. forcing to substructures Q such that <κ Q ⊆ Q .

  13. Theorem Assume GCH, and let κ < κ + < θ be infinite regular cardinals. Then there is a κ -lattice and κ -strongly proper forcing P which forces 2 κ = κ ++ = θ together with the κ -Strongly Proper Forcing Axiom. Proof sketch: By first forcing with Coll( κ + , <θ ) , we may assume that θ = κ ++ and that ♦ ( S θ κ + ) holds. Hence there is a ‘diamond sequence’ � A = ( A α ) α ∈ S θ κ + , where A α ⊆ H ( θ ) for all α . Let κ + : ( A α ; ∈ , � A ↾ α ) � ( H ( θ ); ∈ , � E = { α ∈ S θ A ) } , T = { A α : α ∈ E } , and S = { N � H ( θ ) : | N | = κ, <κ N ⊆ N } Our forcing P is P θ , where ( P α ∈ E ∪ { θ } ) is a <κ -support iteration ` a la Neeman with models from S ∪ T as side conditions.

  14. More specifically, given β ∈ E ∪ { θ } , P β is the set of all pairs � p , s � such that: (1) s ∈ [ S ∪ T ] <κ and ∈ is a weak total order on s . (2) p is a function with dom( p ) ∈ [ E ∩ β ] <κ such that for each α ∈ dom( p ) , (a) A α is a P α -name for a κ -lattice κ -strongly proper forcing notion whose conditions are ordinals, (b) H ( α ) ∈ s , and (c) p ( α ) is a nice P α -name such that � α p ( α ) ∈ A α . (3) For every α ∈ dom( p ) and every N ∈ s ∩ S such that α ∈ N , � p ↾ α, s ∩ H ( α ) � is a condition in P α which forces in P α that p ( α ) is a strongly ( N [ ˙ G α ] , A α ) -generic condition. Extension relation: � p 1 , s 1 � ≤ β � p 0 , s 0 � iff (i) s 0 ⊆ s 1 , (ii) dom( p 0 ) ⊆ dom( p 1 ) , and (ii) for all α ∈ dom( p 0 ) , � p 1 ↾ α, s 1 ∩ H ( α ) � � α p 1 ( α ) ≤ A α p 0 ( α ) .

  15. The Reflection Property is used to show that our construction captures κ -strongly proper forcings of arbitrary size. Also: The proof crucially uses the fact that our forcings are κ -lattice (it would not work if we just assumed <κ -directed closedness). �

  16. The κ -Strongly Proper Forcing Axiom does not decide 2 κ . In fact: Theorem Assume GCH, and let κ < κ + < κ ++ ≤ θ be infinite regular cardinals. Suppose ♦ ( S κ ++ ) holds. Then there is a κ -lattice κ and κ -strongly proper forcing P which forces 2 κ = θ together with the κ -Strongly Proper Forcing Axiom. Proof sketch: We fix ‘diamond sequence’ � A = � A α : α ∈ S κ ++ κ + � , where A α ⊆ H ( κ ++ ) for all α , and build an iteration ( P α ∈ α ∈ E ∪ { κ ++ } ) as before, except that at each stage α ∈ E now we look at whether A α is a P α × Add( κ, κ + ) -name for a κ -lattice and κ -strongly proper poset (and if so we force with it).

  17. The forcing witnessing the theorem is P = P κ ++ × Add( κ, θ ) To see this, take a κ -lattice κ -strongly proper forcing in the extension via P . By the Reflection Property it reflects to a forcing of size κ + . Let ˙ Q be a P -name for the corresponding forcing. By κ ++ -c.c. of P we may identify ˙ Q with a P κ ++ × Add( κ, κ + ) -name, which of course we may assume is a subset of H ( κ ++ ) . Now we use our diamond � A to capture ˙ Q by some A α as in the proof of the previous theorem.

  18. The final point is that A α will be a P α × Add( κ, κ + ) -name for a κ -lattice κ -strongly proper forcing. This uses the fact that every κ -sequence of ordinals is in a κ -Cohen extension since P α × Add( κ, κ + ) is κ -lattice and κ -strongly proper (which enables A α to have enough access to arbitrary P α × Add( κ, κ + ) -names for κ -sized elementary submodels N ). � As far as I know this is the first example of a forcing axiom FA κ + (Γ) such that FA κ ++ (Γ) is false but nevertheless FA κ + (Γ) is compatible with 2 κ arbitrarily large.

  19. The final point is that A α will be a P α × Add( κ, κ + ) -name for a κ -lattice κ -strongly proper forcing. This uses the fact that every κ -sequence of ordinals is in a κ -Cohen extension since P α × Add( κ, κ + ) is κ -lattice and κ -strongly proper (which enables A α to have enough access to arbitrary P α × Add( κ, κ + ) -names for κ -sized elementary submodels N ). � As far as I know this is the first example of a forcing axiom FA κ + (Γ) such that FA κ ++ (Γ) is false but nevertheless FA κ + (Γ) is compatible with 2 κ arbitrarily large.

  20. Some applications of the κ -Strongly Proper Forcing Axiom • d ( κ ) > κ + • The covering number of natural meagre ideals is > κ + . • Weak failures of Club-Guessing at κ . • Suppose ( C α : α ∈ S κ + κ ) is a club sequence of S κ + κ , and let � F = ( f α , α ∈ S κ + κ ) be a colouring, i.e., for each α , → { 0 , 1 } . Then there is G : κ + → { 0 , 1 } , and f α : C α − clubs D α ⊆ C α , for α ∈ S κ + κ , such that G ( β ) = f α ( β ) for all α and all β ∈ D α .

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend