the grothendieck construction for model categories
play

The Grothendieck construction for model categories CT2015, Protugal - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

The Grothendieck construction for model categories CT2015, Protugal Matan Prasma joint work with Y. Harpaz Radboud University Nijmegen, The Netherlands The Grothendieck construction Theorem A: the integral model structure Theorem B: the


  1. Observation For a relative functor F ∶ M � → ModCat, our notion of weak equivalence is symmetric in that a map ( f ,ϕ ) ∶ ( A , X ) � → ( B , Y ) is a weak equivalence iff f ∶ A � → B is a weak equivalence and ϕ ad � → f ∗ ( Y fib ) � → f ∗ Y is a weak equivalence. X Definition Let M be a model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat a functor.

  2. Observation For a relative functor F ∶ M � → ModCat, our notion of weak equivalence is symmetric in that a map ( f ,ϕ ) ∶ ( A , X ) � → ( B , Y ) is a weak equivalence iff f ∶ A � → B is a weak equivalence and ϕ ad � → f ∗ ( Y fib ) � → f ∗ Y is a weak equivalence. X Definition Let M be a model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat a functor. We shall say that F is proper if whenever f ∶ A � → B is a trivial cofibration in M , f ! (W F( A ) ) ⊆ W F( B ) and whenever f ∶ A � → B is a trivial fibration in M , f ∗ (W F( B ) ) ⊆ W F( A ) .

  3. The properness condition allows us to simplify the description of trivial (co)fibrations as follows.

  4. The properness condition allows us to simplify the description of trivial (co)fibrations as follows. Lemma Let F ∶ M � → ModCat be a proper relative functor.

  5. The properness condition allows us to simplify the description of trivial (co)fibrations as follows. Lemma Let F ∶ M � → ModCat be a proper relative functor. A morphism ( f ,ϕ ) ∶ ( A , X ) � → ( B , Y ) is a

  6. The properness condition allows us to simplify the description of trivial (co)fibrations as follows. Lemma Let F ∶ M � → ModCat be a proper relative functor. A morphism ( f ,ϕ ) ∶ ( A , X ) � → ( B , Y ) is a 1. trivial cofibartion if and only if f ∶ A � → B is a trivial cofibration and ϕ ∶ f ! X � → Y is a trivial cofibration in F( B ) ;

  7. The properness condition allows us to simplify the description of trivial (co)fibrations as follows. Lemma Let F ∶ M � → ModCat be a proper relative functor. A morphism ( f ,ϕ ) ∶ ( A , X ) � → ( B , Y ) is a 1. trivial cofibartion if and only if f ∶ A � → B is a trivial cofibration and ϕ ∶ f ! X � → Y is a trivial cofibration in F( B ) ; 2. trivial fibration if and only if f ∶ A � → B is a trivial fibration and ϕ ad ∶ X � → f ∗ Y is a trivial fibration in F( A ) .

  8. The properness condition allows us to simplify the description of trivial (co)fibrations as follows. Lemma Let F ∶ M � → ModCat be a proper relative functor. A morphism ( f ,ϕ ) ∶ ( A , X ) � → ( B , Y ) is a 1. trivial cofibartion if and only if f ∶ A � → B is a trivial cofibration and ϕ ∶ f ! X � → Y is a trivial cofibration in F( B ) ; 2. trivial fibration if and only if f ∶ A � → B is a trivial fibration and ϕ ad ∶ X � → f ∗ Y is a trivial fibration in F( A ) . This description in turn enables us to establish the appropriate lifting properties and factorizations for these three classes. As a result, we get:

  9. Theorem A Let M be a model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat a proper relative functor.

  10. Theorem A Let M be a model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat a proper relative functor. The classes of weak equivalences, fibrations and cofibrations defined above endow ∫ M F with the structure of a model category, called the integral model structure .

  11. Theorem A Let M be a model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat a proper relative functor. The classes of weak equivalences, fibrations and cofibrations defined above endow ∫ M F with the structure of a model category, called the integral model structure . Moreover, the ∞ -categorical Grothendieck construction of the associated ∞ -functor F ∞ ∶ M ∞ � → Cat ∞ (given by restricting to cofibrant objects and left Quillen functors, F cof ∶ M cof � → RelCat and then taking the marked nerve)

  12. Theorem A Let M be a model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat a proper relative functor. The classes of weak equivalences, fibrations and cofibrations defined above endow ∫ M F with the structure of a model category, called the integral model structure . Moreover, the ∞ -categorical Grothendieck construction of the associated ∞ -functor F ∞ ∶ M ∞ � → Cat ∞ (given by restricting to cofibrant objects and left Quillen functors, F cof ∶ M cof � → RelCat and then taking the marked nerve) is equivalent to (∫ M F) ∞ over M ∞ .

  13. Applications of Theorem A

  14. Applications of Theorem A ▸ The functor (S B ( − ) ) proj is proper and relative.

  15. Applications of Theorem A ▸ The functor (S B ( − ) ) proj is proper and relative. The resulting integral model structure ⎛ S B G ⎞ ⎝ ∫ ⎜ ⎟ ⎠ G ∈ sGp int may be referred to as a model for a global (coarse) equivariant homotopy theory .

  16. Applications of Theorem A ▸ The functor (S B ( − ) ) proj is proper and relative. The resulting integral model structure ⎛ S B G ⎞ ⎝ ∫ ⎜ ⎟ ⎠ G ∈ sGp int may be referred to as a model for a global (coarse) equivariant homotopy theory . ▸ Let M be a right (resp. left) proper model category.

  17. Applications of Theorem A ▸ The functor (S B ( − ) ) proj is proper and relative. The resulting integral model structure ⎛ S B G ⎞ ⎝ ∫ ⎜ ⎟ ⎠ G ∈ sGp int may be referred to as a model for a global (coarse) equivariant homotopy theory . ▸ Let M be a right (resp. left) proper model category. The slice (resp. coslice) functor M /( − ) ∶ M � → ModCat ( resp. M ( − )/ ∶ M � → ModCat ) is proper and relative.

  18. Applications of Theorem A ▸ The functor (S B ( − ) ) proj is proper and relative. The resulting integral model structure ⎛ S B G ⎞ ⎝ ∫ ⎜ ⎟ ⎠ G ∈ sGp int may be referred to as a model for a global (coarse) equivariant homotopy theory . ▸ Let M be a right (resp. left) proper model category. The slice (resp. coslice) functor M /( − ) ∶ M � → ModCat ( resp. M ( − )/ ∶ M � → ModCat ) is proper and relative. The category ∫ M M /( − ) (resp. ∫ M M ( − )/ ) is isomorphic to the arrow category M [ 1 ] and Theorem A ensures that we get a model structure.

  19. Applications of Theorem A ▸ The functor (S B ( − ) ) proj is proper and relative. The resulting integral model structure ⎛ S B G ⎞ ⎝ ∫ ⎜ ⎟ ⎠ G ∈ sGp int may be referred to as a model for a global (coarse) equivariant homotopy theory . ▸ Let M be a right (resp. left) proper model category. The slice (resp. coslice) functor M /( − ) ∶ M � → ModCat ( resp. M ( − )/ ∶ M � → ModCat ) is proper and relative. The category ∫ M M /( − ) (resp. ∫ M M ( − )/ ) is isomorphic to the arrow category M [ 1 ] and Theorem A ensures that we get a model structure. Under this identification, this is precisely the injective (resp. projective) model structure.

  20. ▸ Recall:

  21. ▸ Recall: Theorem (Schwede-Shipley) Let M be a combinatorial symmetric monoidal model category satisfying the Schwede-Shipley assumptions ("monoid axiom" + "flatness").

  22. ▸ Recall: Theorem (Schwede-Shipley) Let M be a combinatorial symmetric monoidal model category satisfying the Schwede-Shipley assumptions ("monoid axiom" + "flatness"). Then there is a (combinatorial) model structure on the category of algebra objects Alg (M)

  23. ▸ Recall: Theorem (Schwede-Shipley) Let M be a combinatorial symmetric monoidal model category satisfying the Schwede-Shipley assumptions ("monoid axiom" + "flatness"). Then there is a (combinatorial) model structure on the category of algebra objects Alg (M) and for each A ∈ Alg (M) there is a (combinatorial) model structure on the category of left A-modules LMod ( A ) .

  24. Theorem Let M be a combinatorial symmetric monoidal model category satisfying the Schwede-Shipley assumptions.

  25. Theorem Let M be a combinatorial symmetric monoidal model category satisfying the Schwede-Shipley assumptions. Then the functor LMod (−) ∶ Alg (M) � → ModCat is proper and relative, hence endowing ∫ Alg ( M ) LMod ( A ) with an integral model structure.

  26. Example The following categories satisfy the assumptions of the last theorem:

  27. Example The following categories satisfy the assumptions of the last theorem: 1. Simplicial sets. Algebra objects in S are simplicial monoids.

  28. Example The following categories satisfy the assumptions of the last theorem: 1. Simplicial sets. Algebra objects in S are simplicial monoids. 2. Γ-spaces. Algebra objects are called Γ-rings and model connective ring spectra.

  29. Example The following categories satisfy the assumptions of the last theorem: 1. Simplicial sets. Algebra objects in S are simplicial monoids. 2. Γ-spaces. Algebra objects are called Γ-rings and model connective ring spectra. 3. All the monoidal model categories for spectra except S -modules. The algebra objects model ring spectra.

  30. Example The following categories satisfy the assumptions of the last theorem: 1. Simplicial sets. Algebra objects in S are simplicial monoids. 2. Γ-spaces. Algebra objects are called Γ-rings and model connective ring spectra. 3. All the monoidal model categories for spectra except S -modules. The algebra objects model ring spectra. 4. Non-negatively graded chain complexes over a commutative ring. The algebra objects are the (non-negatively graded) DGAs.

  31. Example The following categories satisfy the assumptions of the last theorem: 1. Simplicial sets. Algebra objects in S are simplicial monoids. 2. Γ-spaces. Algebra objects are called Γ-rings and model connective ring spectra. 3. All the monoidal model categories for spectra except S -modules. The algebra objects model ring spectra. 4. Non-negatively graded chain complexes over a commutative ring. The algebra objects are the (non-negatively graded) DGAs. 5. Unbounded chain complexes over a commutative ring. The algebra objects are the (unbounded) DGAs.

  32. Outline The Grothendieck construction Theorem A: the integral model structure Theorem B: the Grothendieck correspondence for model categories

  33. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck)

  34. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck) 1. For every F ∶ C � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a coCartesian fibration

  35. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck) 1. For every F ∶ C � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a coCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , Cat ) ≃ � → coCart (C)

  36. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck) 1. For every F ∶ C � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a coCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , Cat ) ≃ � → coCart (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors

  37. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck) 1. For every F ∶ C � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a coCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , Cat ) ≃ � → coCart (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors and the 2 -category of coCartesian fibrations over C .

  38. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck) 1. For every F ∶ C � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a coCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , Cat ) ≃ � → coCart (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors and the 2 -category of coCartesian fibrations over C . 2. Similarly, for every F ∶ C op � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C op F � → C is a Cartesian fibration

  39. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck) 1. For every F ∶ C � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a coCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , Cat ) ≃ � → coCart (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors and the 2 -category of coCartesian fibrations over C . 2. Similarly, for every F ∶ C op � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C op F � → C is a Cartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C op , Cat ) ≃ � → Cart (C)

  40. Recall Theorem (Grothendieck) 1. For every F ∶ C � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a coCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , Cat ) ≃ � → coCart (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors and the 2 -category of coCartesian fibrations over C . 2. Similarly, for every F ∶ C op � → Cat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C op F � → C is a Cartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C op , Cat ) ≃ � → Cart (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors and that of Cartesian fibrations.

  41. Theorem (Folklore) For every F ∶ C � → AdjCat ,

  42. Theorem (Folklore) For every F ∶ C � → AdjCat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a biCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , AdjCat ) ≃ � → BiFib (C)

  43. Theorem (Folklore) For every F ∶ C � → AdjCat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a biCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , AdjCat ) ≃ � → BiFib (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors

  44. Theorem (Folklore) For every F ∶ C � → AdjCat , the projection π ∶ ∫ C F � → C is a biCartesian fibration and the Grothendieck construction induces an equivalence of ( 2 , 1 ) -categories ∫ C ∶ Fun (C , AdjCat ) ≃ � → BiFib (C) between the 2 -category of (pseudo-)functors and the 2 -category of biCartesian fibrations over C , adjoint functors over C whose (left) right part preserves (co)Cartesian arrows and fiberwise natural transformations of adjunctions.

  45. Model fibrations

  46. Model fibrations Let π ∶ D � → C be a biCartesian fibration.

  47. Model fibrations Let π ∶ D � → C be a biCartesian fibration. Recall that every morphism ϕ ∶ X � → Y in D can factored in two ways:

  48. � � � � Model fibrations Let π ∶ D � → C be a biCartesian fibration. Recall that every morphism ϕ ∶ X � → Y in D can factored in two ways: coCart X f ! X ϕ f ∗ Y � Y Cart A = π ( X ) � B = π ( Y ) f = π ( ϕ )

  49. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations:

  50. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor.

  51. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor.

  52. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover,

  53. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover, ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) cofibration in M ,

  54. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover, ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) cofibration in M , then for every X ∈ F( A ) , the coCartesian lift ( A , X ) � → ( B , f ! X ) is a (trivial) cofibration in ∫ M F .

  55. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover, ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) cofibration in M , then for every X ∈ F( A ) , the coCartesian lift ( A , X ) � → ( B , f ! X ) is a (trivial) cofibration in ∫ M F . ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) fibration in M ,

  56. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover, ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) cofibration in M , then for every X ∈ F( A ) , the coCartesian lift ( A , X ) � → ( B , f ! X ) is a (trivial) cofibration in ∫ M F . ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) fibration in M , then for every Y ∈ F( B ) , the Cartesian lift ( A , f ∗ Y ) � → ( B , Y ) is a (trivial) fibration in ∫ M F .

  57. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover, ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) cofibration in M , then for every X ∈ F( A ) , the coCartesian lift ( A , X ) � → ( B , f ! X ) is a (trivial) cofibration in ∫ M F . ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) fibration in M , then for every Y ∈ F( B ) , the Cartesian lift ( A , f ∗ Y ) � → ( B , Y ) is a (trivial) fibration in ∫ M F . Let us call a category M with three distinguished classes of maps W , F ib , C of a pre-model category .

  58. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover, ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) cofibration in M , then for every X ∈ F( A ) , the coCartesian lift ( A , X ) � → ( B , f ! X ) is a (trivial) cofibration in ∫ M F . ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) fibration in M , then for every Y ∈ F( B ) , the Cartesian lift ( A , f ∗ Y ) � → ( B , Y ) is a (trivial) fibration in ∫ M F . Let us call a category M with three distinguished classes of maps W , F ib , C of a pre-model category . If M is a pre-model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat is a (formal) proper relative functor,

  59. In our model categorical setup there is an intimate relation between (co)Cartesian lifts and (co)fibrations: Observation Suppose F ∶ M � → ModCat is a proper relative functor. The functor π ∶ ∫ M F � → M is both a biCartesian fibration and a right-left Quillen functor. Moreover, ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) cofibration in M , then for every X ∈ F( A ) , the coCartesian lift ( A , X ) � → ( B , f ! X ) is a (trivial) cofibration in ∫ M F . ▸ If f ∶ A � → B is a (trivial) fibration in M , then for every Y ∈ F( B ) , the Cartesian lift ( A , f ∗ Y ) � → ( B , Y ) is a (trivial) fibration in ∫ M F . Let us call a category M with three distinguished classes of maps W , F ib , C of a pre-model category . If M is a pre-model category and F ∶ M � → ModCat is a (formal) proper relative functor, the projection π ∶ ∫ M F � → M enjoys good formal properties:

  60. Definition Let π ∶ N � → M be (any) functor and (L , R ) be two classes of maps in M which contain all the identities.

  61. Definition Let π ∶ N � → M be (any) functor and (L , R ) be two classes of maps in M which contain all the identities. Two classes of maps ( L , R ) in N will be called a weak factorization systems relative to ( L , R ) if the following holds:

  62. Definition Let π ∶ N � → M be (any) functor and (L , R ) be two classes of maps in M which contain all the identities. Two classes of maps ( L , R ) in N will be called a weak factorization systems relative to ( L , R ) if the following holds: ▸ L and R contain all the identities.

  63. Definition Let π ∶ N � → M be (any) functor and (L , R ) be two classes of maps in M which contain all the identities. Two classes of maps ( L , R ) in N will be called a weak factorization systems relative to ( L , R ) if the following holds: ▸ L and R contain all the identities. ▸ π ( L ) ⊆ L and π ( R ) ⊆ R .

  64. Definition Let π ∶ N � → M be (any) functor and (L , R ) be two classes of maps in M which contain all the identities. Two classes of maps ( L , R ) in N will be called a weak factorization systems relative to ( L , R ) if the following holds: ▸ L and R contain all the identities. ▸ π ( L ) ⊆ L and π ( R ) ⊆ R . ▸ L (resp. R ) contains any retract f of a morphism in L (resp. R )

  65. Definition Let π ∶ N � → M be (any) functor and (L , R ) be two classes of maps in M which contain all the identities. Two classes of maps ( L , R ) in N will be called a weak factorization systems relative to ( L , R ) if the following holds: ▸ L and R contain all the identities. ▸ π ( L ) ⊆ L and π ( R ) ⊆ R . ▸ L (resp. R ) contains any retract f of a morphism in L (resp. R ) provided that π ( f ) is contained in L (resp. R ).

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend