table of contents tutorial on fair division
play

Table of Contents Tutorial on Fair Division Introduction . . . . . - PDF document

Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Table of Contents Tutorial on Fair Division Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 Ulle


  1. Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Table of Contents Tutorial on Fair Division Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 Ulle Endriss Fairness and Efficiency Criteria . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8 Institute for Logic, Language and Computation Divisible Goods: Cake-Cutting Procedures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 University of Amsterdam Indivisible Goods: Combinatorial Optimisation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 68 " # COST-ADT Doctoral School on Computational Social Choice Estoril, Portugal, 9–14 April 2010 ( http://algodec.org ) Ulle Endriss 1 Ulle Endriss 2 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division Fair division is the problem of dividing one or several goods amongst two or more agents in a way that satisfies a suitable fairness criterion. Introduction • Traditionally studied in economics (and to some extent also in mathematics , philosophy , and political science ); now also in computer science (particularly multiagent systems and AI ). • Abstract problem, but immediately relevant to many applications . Ulle Endriss 3 Ulle Endriss 4 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 The Problem Fair Division and Social Choice Consider a set of agents and a set of goods. Each agent has their own Fair division can be considered a problem of social choice: preferences regarding the allocation of goods to agents to be selected. • A group of agents each have individual preferences over a ◮ What constitutes a good allocation and how do we find it? collective agreement (the allocation of goods to be found). • But: in fair division preferences are often assumed to be cardinal What goods? One or several goods? Available in single or multiple ( utility functions ) rather than ordinal (as in voting) units? Divisible or indivisible? Can goods be shared? Are they static or do they change properties (e.g., consumable or perishable goods)? • And: fair division problems come with some internal structure What preferences? Ordinal or cardinal preference structures? Are often absent from other social choice problems (e.g., I will be monetary side payments possible, and how do they affect preferences? indifferent between allocations giving me the same set of goods) How are the preferences represented in the problem input? Ulle Endriss 5 Ulle Endriss 6 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Tutorial Outline This tutorial consists of three parts: • Part 1. Fairness and Efficiency Criteria — What makes a good allocation? We will review and compare several proposals from the literature for how to define “fairness” and the related notion of economic “efficiency”. Fairness and Efficiency Criteria • Part 2. Cake-Cutting Procedures — How should we fairly divide a “cake” (a single divisible good )? We will review several algorithms and analyse their properties. • Part 3. Combinatorial Optimisation — The fair division of indivisible goods gives rise to a combinatorial optimisation problem. We will cover centralised approaches (similar to auctions) and a distributed negotiation approach. Ulle Endriss 7 Ulle Endriss 8

  2. Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Notation and Terminology • Let N = { 1 , . . . , n } be a set of agents (or players , or individuals ) What is a Good Allocation? who need to share several goods (or resources , items , objects ). In this part of the tutorial we are going to give an overview of criteria • An allocation A is a mapping of agents to bundles of goods. that have been proposed for deciding what makes a “good” allocation: • Most criteria will not be specific to allocation problems, so we also • Of course, there are application-specific criteria, e.g.: speak of agreements (or outcomes , solutions , alternatives , states ). – “ the allocation allows the agents to solve the problem ” • Each agent i ∈ N has a utility function u i (or valuation function ), mapping agreements to the reals, to model their preferences. – “ the auctioneer has generated sufficient revenue ” – Typically, u i first defined on bundles, so: u i ( A ) = u i ( A ( i )) . Here we are interested in general criteria that can be defined in terms of the individual agent preferences ( preference aggregation ). – Discussion: preference intensity, interpersonal comparison • An agreement A gives rise to a utility vector � u 1 ( A ) , . . . , u n ( A ) � . • As we shall see, such criteria can be roughly divided into fairness and (economic) efficiency criteria. • Sometimes, we are going to define social preference structures directly over utility vectors u = � u 1 , . . . , u n � (elements of R n ), rather than speaking about the agreements generating them. Ulle Endriss 9 Ulle Endriss 10 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Pareto Efficiency Social Welfare Agreement A is Pareto dominated by agreement A ′ if u i ( A ) ≤ u i ( A ′ ) Given the utilities of the individual agents, we can define a notion of for all agents i ∈ N and this inequality is strict in at least one case. social welfare and aim for an agreement that maximises social welfare. An agreement A is Pareto efficient if there is no other feasible Common definition of social welfare (e.g., in the MAS literature): agreement A ′ such that A is Pareto dominated by A ′ . � SW( u ) = u i The idea goes back to Vilfredo Pareto (Italian economist, 1848–1923). i ∈N Discussion: That is, social welfare is defined as the sum of the individual utilities. • Pareto efficiency is very often considered a minimum requirement Maximising this function amounts to maximising average utility . for any agreement/allocation. It is a very weak criterion. This is a reasonable definition, but it does not capture everything . . . • Only the ordinal content of preferences is needed to check Pareto ◮ We need a systematic approach to defining social preferences. efficiency (no preference intensity, no interpersonal comparison). Ulle Endriss 11 Ulle Endriss 12 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Social Welfare Orderings A social welfare ordering (SWO) � is a binary relation over R n that is reflexive , transitive , and complete . Collective Utility Functions Intuitively, if u, v ∈ R n , then u � v means that v is socially preferred A collective utility function (CUF) is a function SW : R n → R over u (not necessarily strictly). mapping utility vectors to the reals. We also use the following notation: Every CUF induces an SWO: u � v ⇔ SW( u ) ≤ SW( v ) • u ≺ v iff u � v but not v � u ( strict social preference ) • u ∼ v iff both u � v and v � u ( social indifference ) Ulle Endriss 13 Ulle Endriss 14 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Fair Division COST-ADT School 2010 Utilitarian Social Welfare Egalitarian Social Welfare One approach to social welfare is to try to maximise overall profit. The egalitarian CUF measures social welfare as follows: This is known as classical utilitarianism (advocated, amongst others, by Jeremy Bentham, British philosopher, 1748–1832). min { u i | i ∈ N} SW egal ( u ) = The utilitarian CUF is defined as follows: Maximising this function amounts to improving the situation of the � SW util ( u ) = u i weakest member of society. i ∈N The egalitarian variant of welfare economics is inspired by the work of So this is what we have called “social welfare” a few slides back. John Rawls (American philosopher, 1921–2002) and has been formally Remark: We define CUFs and SWOs on utility vectors, but the developed, amongst others, by Amartya Sen since the 1970s (Nobel definitions immediately extend to allocations: Prize in Economic Sciences in 1998). � SW util ( A ) = SW util ( � u 1 ( A ) , . . . , u n ( A ) � ) = u i ( A ( i )) J. Rawls. A Theory of Justice . Oxford University Press, 1971. i ∈N A.K. Sen. Collective Choice and Social Welfare . Holden Day, 1970. Ulle Endriss 15 Ulle Endriss 16

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend