on projective manifolds with semi positive holomorphic
play

On projective manifolds with semi-positive holomorphic sectional - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics On projective manifolds with semi-positive holomorphic sectional curvature Shin-ichi Matsumura ( ) Tohoku University (mshinichi-math@tohoku.ac.jp,


  1. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Frankel conjecture prove by Siu-Yau’80, Hartshorne conjecture proved by Mori’ 79) (1) If BSC g is positive ( that is, BSC g ( v , w ) > 0 for any non-zero vectors v , w ∈ T X at any point of X ) , then X ∼ = P n . (2) If T X is ample, then the same conclusion holds. Ampleness of T X is an algebraic counterpart of BSC g > 0. Theorem (Igusa ’55) TFAE. (1) ∃ g: BSC g ≡ 0 (2) ∃ g: R g ≡ 0 (3) X is a torus up to finite ´ etale cover, namely, there exists a torus T s.t. finite ´ etale T − − − − − − → X 4 / 21

  2. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Frankel conjecture prove by Siu-Yau’80, Hartshorne conjecture proved by Mori’ 79) (1) If BSC g is positive ( that is, BSC g ( v , w ) > 0 for any non-zero vectors v , w ∈ T X at any point of X ) , then X ∼ = P n . (2) If T X is ample, then the same conclusion holds. Ampleness of T X is an algebraic counterpart of BSC g > 0. Theorem (Igusa ’55) TFAE. (1) ∃ g: BSC g ≡ 0 (2) ∃ g: R g ≡ 0 (3) X is a torus up to finite ´ etale cover, namely, there exists a torus T s.t. finite ´ etale T − − − − − − → X 4 / 21

  3. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Frankel conjecture prove by Siu-Yau’80, Hartshorne conjecture proved by Mori’ 79) (1) If BSC g is positive ( that is, BSC g ( v , w ) > 0 for any non-zero vectors v , w ∈ T X at any point of X ) , then X ∼ = P n . (2) If T X is ample, then the same conclusion holds. Ampleness of T X is an algebraic counterpart of BSC g > 0. Theorem (Igusa ’55) TFAE. (1) ∃ g: BSC g ≡ 0 (2) ∃ g: R g ≡ 0 (3) X is a torus up to finite ´ etale cover, namely, there exists a torus T s.t. finite ´ etale T − − − − − − → X 4 / 21

  4. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Frankel conjecture prove by Siu-Yau’80, Hartshorne conjecture proved by Mori’ 79) (1) If BSC g is positive ( that is, BSC g ( v , w ) > 0 for any non-zero vectors v , w ∈ T X at any point of X ) , then X ∼ = P n . (2) If T X is ample, then the same conclusion holds. Ampleness of T X is an algebraic counterpart of BSC g > 0. Theorem (Igusa ’55) TFAE. (1) ∃ g: BSC g ≡ 0 (2) ∃ g: R g ≡ 0 (3) X is a torus up to finite ´ etale cover, namely, there exists a torus T s.t. finite ´ etale T − − − − − − → X 4 / 21

  5. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Frankel conjecture prove by Siu-Yau’80, Hartshorne conjecture proved by Mori’ 79) (1) If BSC g is positive ( that is, BSC g ( v , w ) > 0 for any non-zero vectors v , w ∈ T X at any point of X ) , then X ∼ = P n . (2) If T X is ample, then the same conclusion holds. Ampleness of T X is an algebraic counterpart of BSC g > 0. Theorem (Igusa ’55) TFAE. (1) ∃ g: BSC g ≡ 0 (2) ∃ g: R g ≡ 0 (3) X is a torus up to finite ´ etale cover, namely, there exists a torus T s.t. finite ´ etale T − − − − − − → X 4 / 21

  6. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Frankel conjecture prove by Siu-Yau’80, Hartshorne conjecture proved by Mori’ 79) (1) If BSC g is positive ( that is, BSC g ( v , w ) > 0 for any non-zero vectors v , w ∈ T X at any point of X ) , then X ∼ = P n . (2) If T X is ample, then the same conclusion holds. Ampleness of T X is an algebraic counterpart of BSC g > 0. Theorem (Igusa ’55) TFAE. (1) ∃ g: BSC g ≡ 0 (2) ∃ g: R g ≡ 0 (3) X is a torus up to finite ´ etale cover, namely, there exists a torus T s.t. finite ´ etale T − − − − − − → X 4 / 21

  7. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Frankel conjecture prove by Siu-Yau’80, Hartshorne conjecture proved by Mori’ 79) (1) If BSC g is positive ( that is, BSC g ( v , w ) > 0 for any non-zero vectors v , w ∈ T X at any point of X ) , then X ∼ = P n . (2) If T X is ample, then the same conclusion holds. Ampleness of T X is an algebraic counterpart of BSC g > 0. Theorem (Igusa ’55) TFAE. (1) ∃ g: BSC g ≡ 0 (2) ∃ g: R g ≡ 0 (3) X is a torus up to finite ´ etale cover, namely, there exists a torus T s.t. finite ´ etale T − − − − − − → X 4 / 21

  8. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  9. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  10. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  11. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  12. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  13. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  14. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  15. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Howard-Smyth-Wu’81) If BSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. BSC g F ≥ 0 and Ric g F > q 0 . Moreover, we obtain X univ ∼ = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) Theorem (Mok’88) A manifold F ( which corresponds to the fiber of φ : X → Y ) satisfying that BSC g F ≥ 0 Ric g F > q 0 and is always a Hermitian symmetric space. 5 / 21

  16. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  17. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  18. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  19. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  20. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  21. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  22. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  23. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  24. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Problem (Main problem in this talk) (1) If HSC g > 0 , then what can we say for X?? ( HSC version of Mok’s result ) . (2) If HSC g ≥ 0 , then can we obtain a structure thm?? ( HSC version of Howard-Smyth-Wu’s result ) . Motivation : • HSC g determines R g (in particular BSC g ), namely, if HSC g = HSC h , then R g = R h . • In this sense, HSC g is a more primitive object. • However, a relation between positivity of BSC and HSC is unknown and still mysterious. • HSC g is closely related to the geometry of rational curves . • For example, by Schwarz lemma generalized by Yau, if HSC g < 0, then there is no rational curves in X . 6 / 21

  25. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is ( projective and ) rationally connected. Definition (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. 7 / 21

  26. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is ( projective and ) rationally connected. Definition (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. 7 / 21

  27. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is ( projective and ) rationally connected. Definition (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. 7 / 21

  28. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is ( projective and ) rationally connected. Definition (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. 7 / 21

  29. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is ( projective and ) rationally connected. Definition (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. 7 / 21

  30. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is ( projective and ) rationally connected. Definition (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. 7 / 21

  31. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is ( projective and ) rationally connected. Definition (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. 7 / 21

  32. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Definition (Reprint) (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve ( R-curve ) if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. Example (1) Any Fano manifolds ( including P n ) are RC. (2) Any torus T has no rational curve. (3) X := P ( E ) → Y is always uniruled. (4) X := P ( E ) is not RC when Y is torus. 8 / 21

  33. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Definition (Reprint) (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve ( R-curve ) if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. Example (1) Any Fano manifolds ( including P n ) are RC. (2) Any torus T has no rational curve. (3) X := P ( E ) → Y is always uniruled. (4) X := P ( E ) is not RC when Y is torus. 8 / 21

  34. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Definition (Reprint) (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve ( R-curve ) if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. t . (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. R' T → f- Example (1) Any Fano manifolds ( including P n ) are RC. (2) Any torus T has no rational curve. (3) X := P ( E ) → Y is always uniruled. (4) X := P ( E ) is not RC when Y is torus. 8 / 21

  35. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Definition (Reprint) (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve ( R-curve ) if ° FIR ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . h (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. BE ) (3) X is called uniruled if ⇐ ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. Example (1) Any Fano manifolds ( including P n ) are RC. (2) Any torus T has no rational curve. (3) X := P ( E ) → Y is always uniruled. (4) X := P ( E ) is not RC when Y is torus. 8 / 21

  36. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Definition (Reprint) (1) A curve R ⊂ X is called a rational curve ( R-curve ) if ∃ f : P 1 → X s.t. R = f ( P 1 ) . :¥÷ 7 (2) X is called rationally connected ( RC ) if in ∀ x , y ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x , y ∈ R. (3) X is called uniruled if ∀ x ∈ X , ∃ R ⊂ X s.t. x ∈ R. Example (1) Any Fano manifolds ( including P n ) are RC. torus (2) Any torus T has no rational curve. (3) X := P ( E ) → Y is always uniruled. (4) X := P ( E ) is not RC when Y is torus. 8 / 21

  37. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  38. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  39. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  40. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  41. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  42. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  43. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  44. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  45. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Conjecture (Reprint, Yau’s conjecture) If HSC g is positive, then X is projective and RC. Known Reults: • Heier-Wong’15 solved Yau’s conjecture when X is projective. • Yang’18 solved Yau’s conjecture in a general situation. However • Yang’s method is based on the maximal principle and it can not be applied to the quasi-positive case. • It is important to consider the quasi-positive case of Yau’s conjecture from the viewpoint of a structure thm. Theorem (Thm A) If X is projective and satisfies P ( X , g ) = n ( which is satisfied in the quasi-positive case ) , then X is RC. • P ( X , g ) is an invariant defined by an analogue of the numerical Kodaira dimension. • The proof depends on Heier-Wong’s idea and RC positivity (partial positivity) introduced by Yang. 9 / 21

  46. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  47. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  48. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  49. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  50. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  51. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  52. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  53. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  54. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Theorem (Thm B) If X is projective and HSC g is non-negative, then ∃ φ : X → Y satisfying that: (1) φ is locally trivial ( all the fibers F are non-singular and biholo ) . (2) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g Y on Y : R g Y ≡ 0 . (3) ∃ K¨ ahler metric g F on F s.t. HSC g F ≥ 0 and F is RC . Moreover, we obtain = F × C m ( biholo and isometric ) X univ ∼ • There are two bad points in Thm B, compared to Howard-Smyth-Wu’s structure theorem. • One is the assumption of X being projective. • The other is the lack of “quasi-positivity” of HSC g F . 10 / 21

  55. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  56. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. ↳ :* • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). ftp.jiinm • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . = . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . ¥ (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, - K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  57. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. Rf 641 • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is , not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). EE • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . , (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  58. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  59. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark LIE (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are ho at unique up to birational models of Y . curve (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . , (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. I ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, m =D - K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  60. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  61. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  62. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  63. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . X (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. idx MRI ¥ ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  64. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  65. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 1: MRC fibration • ∃ φ : X ��� Y : MRC fibration (Campana, Koll´ ar-Miyaoka-Mori): (1) φ is a rational map whose general fiber is compact. (2) A general fiber F is RC. (3) ∄ horizontal rational curve at “general points”. • For example, X := P ( E ) → Y is always an RC fibration, but it is not necessarily an MRC fibration (consider Y = P m ). • X := P ( E ) → Y is MRC when Y has no rational curve. Remark (1) MRC fibrations are not uniquely determined, but they are unique up to birational models of Y . (2) X is RC i ff dim Y = 0 . (3) X is not uniruled i ff dim Y = dim X. ( 4 ) If MRC is non-trivial ( that is, 0 < dim Y < dim X ) , then K Y is always pseudo-e ff ective ( psef ) , namely, K Y has a singular metric h such that Θ h ( K X ) ≥ 0 ( by the result of Graber-Harris-Starr ) . 11 / 21

  66. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  67. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  68. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  69. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  70. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  71. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  72. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  73. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  74. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics • If HSC g ≡ 0, then X is torus up to ´ etale covers. We may assume: HSC g ≥ 0 and HSC g ̸≡ 0 Claim Then X is uniruled. In particular, K Y is psef. Theorem (BDPP) X is not uniruled if and only if K X is psef. Proof. Assume K X is psef. Then c 1 ( K X ) ∧ ω n − 1 = − 1 � � Scal g ω n . 0 ≤ π n X X On the the hand, we have � Scal g ( p ) = HSC ( v ) dV FS . v ∈ P ( T X , p ) Hence Scal g is a quasi-positive function on X . 12 / 21

  75. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  76. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  77. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  78. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  79. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  80. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  81. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  82. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

  83. Introduction Main results Strategy of Thm B Details of proof Related topics Step 2: Splitting of T X • Assume that MRC φ : X → Y is holo in Step 2 and Step 3. In Step 2, we will prove the followings: • φ : X → Y is smooth (that is, any fiber F is non-singular). In particular, we have the exact sequence of the tangent bundles: 0 → T X / Y → T X → φ ∗ T Y → 0 . g �� g Q • The sequence above admits the holo and orthogonal decomposition: Namely, a bundle morphism ∃ j : φ ∗ T Y → T X satisfying that T X = T X / Y ⊕ j ( φ ∗ T Y ) , T X / Y and j ( φ ∗ T Y ) is orthogonal w.r.t. g . • a metric ∃ g Y on Y s.t. g Q = φ ∗ g Y and R g Y ≡ 0 . 13 / 21

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend