lexical syntax 25 years later
play

Lexical Syntax 25 Years Later A Retrospective and Prospective Look - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Lexical Syntax 25 Years Later A Retrospective and Prospective Look at the Dative Alternation in LFG J OAN B RESNAN Stanford University Outline Early LFG: The lexicon drives the syntax LMT: principles of


  1. ✩ ✪ Lexical Syntax 25 Years Later A Retrospective and Prospective Look at the Dative Alternation in LFG J OAN B RESNAN Stanford University ✬ ✫

  2. ✩ ✪ Outline Early LFG: The lexicon drives the syntax LMT: principles of function-argument correspondence exploit the se- mantics of lexical argument structures OT-LFG: Anti-lexicalist problems Stochastic OT-LFG: Toward quantitative syntax and usage studies of lexical relations, undermining some of the original motivations for lexically driven syntax ✬ ✫

  3. ✩ ✪ Early LFG: The lexicon drives the syntax ✬ ✫

  4. ✩ ✪ Oehrle (1976) a : Different ‘success criteria’ for giving: I gave you a book for your birthday. (You now own the book.) I gave you my bicycle for the afternoon. (I left it unlocked, so you could use it, but I am still the owner. I just gave you custody.) Besides transfer of ownership and transfer of custody, the verb give a third reading (causative): Interviewing Nixon gave Mailer a book. (p. 44) That movie gave me the creeps. (p. 66) “A notable fact about what we have called the ‘third reading’ of sentences with give is that the prepositional dative construction is not available—or if so only in certain rather special cases.” (p. 67) *Interviewing Nixon gave a book to Mailer. *That movie gave the creeps to me. ‘. . . in all cases in which the third reading is available, the double object ✬ ✫ construction is base-generated . . . ” p. 68 a building on Green (1974)

  5. ✩ ✪ The dative alternation as a lexical regularity Fred handed a boy to the baby. Fred handed the baby a toy. “Both syntactic structures can be base-generated, and the seeming transformational relationship between them can be expressed instead as a relationship between the lexical forms for hand .” Bresnan (1979) “Polyadicity” p. 313 Syntactic properties of the alternation—its being lexically governed, bounded, and structure preserving—follow from the fact that the rules deriving the dative alternation are restricted to the information available in the lexical entries of verbs (Bresnan 1978, 1982). ✬ ✫

  6. ✩ ✪ In subsequent work initiated by Pinker (1983, 1989) , each of a number of fine-grained semantic classes of dative verbs and idioms has been mapped onto a unique syntax: a ⇒ ‘x causes y to have z’ (possessive) NP V NP NP ‘x causes z to go to/be at y’ (allative) ⇒ NP V NP [to NP] a Gropen et al. 1989, Speas 1990, Levin 1993, Marantz 1993, Goldberg 1995, Pesetsky 1995, Davis 1997, Harley 1996, in press, Arad 1998, Kay 2000, Bruening 2001, Krifka 2001, ao ✬ ✫

  7. ✩ ✪ Supported by semantic restrictions on the dative alternation: a. I threw the box to John. ∼ I threw John the box. (1) b. I lowered the box to John. �∼ *I lowered John the box. (Pinker 1989: 110–111; Levin 1993: 46, 114) (2) a. Ann faxed the news to Beth. ∼ Ann faxed Beth the news b. Ann yelled the news to Beth . �∼ *Ann yelled Beth the news. (Krifka 2001) (3) The lighting here gives me a headache. �∼ *The lighting here gives a headache to me. (Marantz 1993; Bruening 2001: 261) ✬ ✫

  8. ✩ ✪ Giving someone a headache is causing them to have a headache, not transferring the headache from one location to another. ⇒ Possessive Throwing specifies a causing event. ⇒ Possessive or Allative Lowering specifies both the causing event and a movement event, since there is a homomorphoric mapping between the two events in lowering actions (Krifka 2001, Pinker 1989). ⇒ Allative only With yelling, there is “a homomorphism between speech production (e.g. the activity of yelling) and the transfer of information,” (Krifka 2001) ⇒ Allative only With faxing there is no homomorphism between the causing event and the movement event; only the initial stage of the transfer is specified as with throw . ⇒ Possessive or Allative ‘x causes y to have z’ (possessive) NP V NP NP ⇒ ✬ ✫ ‘x causes z to go to/be at y’ (allative) NP V NP [to NP] ⇒

  9. ✩ ✪ In sum . . . When the same verb appears with both dative NP and dative PP syntax on this account, the meanings of the two constructions differ. Either the verbs throw, fax , and the like are lexically polysemous, or polysemy is imposed by the differing constructional contexts they appear in. ✬ ✫

  10. ✩ ✪ Problem: Alternating dative syntax can be found in contexts of repeti- tion: “You don’t know how difficult it is to find something which will please everybody—especially the men.” “Why not just give them cheques ?’ I asked. “You can’t give cheques to people . It would be insulting.” a “You carrying a doughnut to your aunt again this morning?” J.C. sneered. Shelton nodded and turned his attention to a tiny TV where “Hawaii Five-O” flickered out into the darkness of the little booth. “Looks like you carry her some breakfast every morning.” b a Davidse (1996a: 291), from Graham Green (1980) Doctor Fischer of Geneva or the Bomb Party . London: The Bodley Head) ✬ ✫ b www.flagpole.com/Issues/12.23.98/shortstory.html

  11. ✩ ✪ A proposed solution: Pinker (1989: 83): “the meaning of give inherently specifies change of possession”. It cannot be used to specify a spatial motion: I *gave/threw a book onto the table . Krifka (2001) on give : a “every transfer of possession entails an abstract movement event in the dimension of possession spaces.” b , c By means of such meaning postulates, different semantic representations of give can be made truth-functionally equivalent. a building on Gropen et al. (1989) and Pinker (1989: 83) b The latinate verbs ( donate, contribute , etc.) remain an exception to this generalization for morphophonological reasons. c The give a headache idiom is not affected by this meaning postulate, according to Krifka ✬ ✫ (2001), because the theme does not just change possession but comes into existence.

  12. ✩ ✪ Lexical Mapping Theory: principles of function-argument correspondence exploit the semantics of lexical argument structures ✬ ✫

  13. ✩ ✪ Semantic classification of a-structure roles for function : patientlike roles (including possessor): θ [ − r ] secondary patientlike roles (not including possessor): θ [+ o ] other semantic roles: θ [ − o ] A-structure to f-structure mapping principles: a. Subject roles: ˆ (i) θ is mapped onto SUBJ ; otherwise: [ − o ] (ii) θ is mapped onto SUBJ . [ − r ] ✬ ✫ b. Other roles are mapped onto the lowest compatible syntactic function on the markedness hierarchy: S ≻ O , OBL θ ≻ O θ .

  14. ✩ ✪ y = Recipient/possessor; z = Theme give 1 < x y z > [ − o ] [ − r ] [+ o ] y = Recipient/goal; z = Theme give 2 < x y z > [ − o ] [ − o ] [ − r ] ✬ ✫

  15. ✩ ✪ y = Recipient/possessor; z = Theme < x y z > give 1 [ − o ] [ − r ] [+ o ] S / OBL θ S / O O / O θ (ai) S (b) O O θ I gave them cheques. y = Recipient/goal; z = Theme give 2 < x y z > [ − o ] [ − o ] [ − r ] S / OBL θ S / OBL θ S / O (ai) S ✬ ✫ (b) OBL θ O I gave cheques to them.

  16. ✩ ✪ OT-LFG: Anti-lexicalist problems ✬ ✫

  17. ✩ ✪ Nick Evans (1997: 398): “. . . is only the role important, or does the choice of cast also influence the way an event is portrayed?” The dative alternation (and the behavior of applicatives) depends not only on the semantics of the verb, which determines the roles, but also on the properties of the cast of referents that fill the roles: animacy, person, information status. Witness Mayali (Evans 1997), Southern Tiwa (Rosen 1990), Shona (Hawkinson and Hyman 1974) and Sesotho (Morolong and Hyman 1977), among many others. ✬ ✫

  18. ✩ ✪ I n Kanuri (Hutchison 1981, Nikitina 2003) there is a person-driven dative alternation. With the Kanuri verb ‘give’ a third person recipient can be expressed only in a postpositional phrase: shi-ro yik na � him-to give- PRF ‘I gave (it) to him’ Note that it appears to be highly dispreferred to drop the third person recipient: a ? yik na � 0-give- PRF ‘I give (it) to him’ However, if the recipient is second or first person, it is normally expressed as a direct object prefix on the verb: nj-ikin ✬ ✫ 2S G .O BJ -give ‘I give (it) to you’ a —suggesting the lack of a zero morph for 3 rd person object on the verb

  19. ✩ ✪ We could simply annotate person and other ‘cast’ properies onto the lexical argument structure (as both Evans 1997 and Bresnan and Moshi 1990 do): y = Recipient/possessor; z = Theme give 1 < x y z > [ − o ] [ − r ] [+ o ] [ PERS 1,2] give 1 < x y z > [ − o ] [ − o ] [+ o ] [ PERS 3] But there is no meaning difference in the giving verb when the person of the recipient changes. Here LMT has been tacitly augmented with a principle that intrinsically classifies the roles of lexical argument structures ✬ ✫ on the basis of properties far outside the lexical entry for a verb, deriving ultimately from the reference and information status of its arguments.

  20. ✩ ✪ This looks like an anti-lexical move from the perspective of traditional LFG. Recall: Syntactic properties of the alternation—its being lexically governed, bounded, and structure preserving—follow from the fact that the rules deriving the dative alternation are restricted to the information available in the lexical entries of verbs (Bresnan 1978, 1982). ✬ ✫

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend